Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-fnpn6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-25T07:39:16.415Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Feminism and Agency1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Extract

Given conditions of oppression presupposed by a feminist understanding of social structures, feminist agency is paradoxical. I am going to understand feminist agency as women's ability to be effective agents against their own oppression. The paradox of feminist agency arises because feminist assumptions about women's socialization seem to entail that women's agency is compromised by sexist oppression. In particular, women's agency appears to be diminished in ways that interfere with their capacity for feminist action, that is, action against sexist oppression.

Feminist philosophers have taken issue with traditional conceptions of agency, claiming that these conceptions are overly individualistic and valorize an illusory and unattractive ideal of agents and agency. If the paradox arises because women do not attain traditional ideals of independence, control, choice, and free action, then, if we reject the tradition, we may be able to articulate a preferable ideal of agency. This alternative may be one that women satisfy. Hence, a feminist reconstrual of the self could dispel the paradox.

Type
II. Human Nature and Moral Agency
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2002

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

I would like to thank Samantha Brennan for inviting me to participate in this volume, giving me the opportunity to present the work-in-progress at the Feminist Moral Philosophy Conference at the University of Western Ontario in August 2002, and providing helpful comments on earlier drafts. An earlier version of this paper was also presented at the Society for Analytical Feminism (SAF) meeting in Chicago in May 2002. Many thanks to Ann Cudd for her insightful commentary at that session, and to audiences at both the SAF meeting and the Feminist Moral Philosophy conference. I am grateful for funding for this project, awarded through the University of Western Ontario's internal Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (SSHRC) research grant competition.

References

2 Claudia, Card, “The Fiestiness of Feminist,” in Feminist Ethics, ed. C., Card (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1991);Google ScholarMarilyn, Frye, The Politics of Reality (Freedom, CA: The Crossing Press, 1983);Google ScholarAlison, Jaggar, “Feminist Ethics: Projects, Problems, Prospects,” in Feminist Ethics (op. cit.).Google Scholar

3 Sandra, Bartky, Femininity and Domination: Studies in the Phenomenology of Oppression (New York: Routledge, 1990);Google Scholar Card, “Fiestiness”; N., Hartsock, “The Feminist Standpoint: Developing a Ground for a Specifically Feminist Historical Materialism,” in Discovering Reality: Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, ed. S., Harding and M., Hintikka (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1983);Google ScholarDiana Tietjens, Meyers, ”Agency,” in A Companion to Feminist Philosophy, Alison, Jaggar and Iris Marion, Young, ed. (Oxford: Blackwell, 2000);Google ScholarRosemarie, Tong, Feminine and Feminist Ethics (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1993).Google Scholar

4 John Martin, Fischer, “Responsibility and Control,” in Moral Responsibility, ed. John Martin, Fischer (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1986);Google ScholarHarry, Frankfurt, “Freedom of the Will and the Concept of the Person,” Journal of Philosophy 68 (1971): 520;Google ScholarImmanuel, Kant, Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (1785), trans.Google ScholarJames W., Ellington (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993);Google ScholarJohn, Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971);Google Scholar R. Tong, Feminine and Feminist Ethics.

5 It might strike some people as odd that I have left “autonomous” off of the list, for many people think of autonomy as a fundamental condition of agency. I have omitted autonomy because it means such different things to different people and because it is likely captured by several of the features that I have mentioned.

6 Meyers, “Agency.“

7 Susan Sherwin has suggested that feminists should distinguish between agency and autonomy. She maintains that “agency” involves the exercising of reasonable choice, but does not take into account oppressive circumstances that circumscribe the range of choices available. A broadened, more relational account of autonomy that goes beyond the traditional idea of self-governance would be sensitive to oppression. I have two reasons for not distinguishing here between agency and autonomy in the way that Sherwin recommends. First, I have presented the paradox of feminist agency as stemming from feminist assumptions about patriarchal oppression. Thus, it does not ignore circumstances of oppression. And second, I am not concerned so much with the idea of agency as the exercise of reasonable choice, as with the possibility of feminist agency. I understand feminist agency to be effective action by women against patriarchal oppression. Thus, my focus here is quite different from Sherwin's. I have consciously and explicitly set aside the task of articulating an account of autonomy (see note 5), as the paradox of feminist agency arises regardless of our conception of autonomy. See Susan, Sherwin'sA Relational Approach to Autonomy in Health Care,” in The Politics of Women's Health: Exploring Agency and Autonomy, Susan, Sherwin, Coordinator (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1998), 33.Google Scholar

8 Lawrence, Blum, Friendship, Altruism and Morality (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1980);Google ScholarAdrienne, Rich, Of Woman Born (New York: W. W. Norton, 1979);Google ScholarLorraine, Code, “Second Persons,” in Science, Morality and Feminist Theory, ed. Marsha, Hanen and Kai, Neilsen (Calgary: University of Calgary Press, 1987);Google ScholarCaroline, Whitbeck, “A Different Reality: Feminist Ontology,” in Women, Knowledge and Reality: Explorations in Feminist Philosophy, ed. Ann, Garry and Marilyn, Pearsall (Boston: Unwin Hyman, 1989);Google Scholar see also Catriona, Mackenzie and Natalie, Stoljar, eds., Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).Google Scholar

9 Carol, Gilligan, In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women's Development (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982).Google Scholar

10 Meyers, “Agency.“

11 Ibid., 377.

12 Card, “Fiestiness”; Michelle-Moody Adams, “Gender and the Complexity of Moral Voices,” in Feminist Ethics, ed. C. Card; Adrienne Rich, Of Woman Born; R. Tong, Feminist and Feminine Ethics.

13 Marilyn Frye, The Politics of Reality; R. Tong, Feminine and Feminist Ethics.

14 Margaret Urban Walker, Moral Understandings: A Feminist Study in Ethics (New York: Routledge, 1998).

15 Ibid., 96.

16 Ibid., 100.

17 Ibid., 107.

18 Susan, Dwyer, “Learning from Experience,” in Daring to Be Good: Essays in Feminist Ethico-Politics, ed. Bat-Ami Bar, On and Ann, Ferguson (New York: Routledge, 1998);Google Scholar Jaggar, “Feminist Ethics.”

19 Samantha Brennan suggested this example.

20 Urban, Walker, Moral Understandings, 107.Google Scholar

21 The Chilly Climate for Women Faculty in Colleges and Universities, executive producers, Western's Caucus on Women's Issues and the President's Standing Committee on Employment Equity, the University of Western Ontario, producer Kern Murch Productions, written and directed by Kern Murch, 1991.

22 As Marilyn Frye says, “to recognize a person as oppressed, one has to see that individual as belonging to a group of a certain sort.” Frye, The Politics of Reality, 8.

23 Michael, Bratman, “Shared Intention,” Ethics 104 (1993): 97113;Google ScholarMargaret, Gilbert, “What Is It for Us to Intend?” in Contemporary Action Theory, Vol. 2, ed. Raimo, Tuomela and Ghita, Holmstrom (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1997), 6585;Google ScholarChristopher, Kutz, Complicity: Ethics and Law for a Collective Age (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2000);Google ScholarLarry, May, The Morality of Groups (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1987);Google ScholarRaimo, Tuomela and Karl, Miller, “We-Intentions,” Philosophical Studies 53 (1988): 115-37.Google Scholar

24 Ibid.

25 “Guidelines for the Use of Non-Sexist Language,” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 59 (1986): 471-82.

26 Frye, Politics of Reality, 16.

27 Ann Cudd put this point to me in her helpful commentary on an earlier version of the paper, presented at the Meeting of the Society for Analytical Feminism, Chicago, April 2002.

28 Such as Jean, Grimshaw, “Autonomy and Identity in Feminist Thinking,” in Feminist Perspectives in Philosophy, ed. Morwenna, Griffiths and Margaret, Whitford (Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1988).Google Scholar

29 R., Tong, Feminine and Feminist Ethics, 59.Google Scholar

30 For a very interesting discussion of the way that women make choices that leave them worse off, see Rhona, Mahoney'sKidding Ourselves: Breadwinning, Babies, and Bargaining Power (New York: Basic Books, 1995).Google Scholar

31 Ann, Cudd, “Comments on Isaacs,” presented at the meeting of the Society for Analytical Feminism, Chicago (April 2002), 4.Google Scholar

32 Ibid.

33 Ibid.

34 Ann Cudd provides an excellent discussion of blaming the victim and of the moral duty of the oppressed to resist oppression in her article “Strikes, Housework, and the Moral Obligation to Resist,” Journal of Social Philosophy 29 (1998): 20–36.

35 See ibid., 31.

36 Ibid., 33.

37 Ibid., 34.

38 Ibid., 34.

39 Lisa Tessman put this question to me in the discussion period of my session at the Feminist Moral Philosophy Conference, August 23-25, 2002, The University of Western Ontario, London, Ontario, Canada.

40 Maria C., Lugones and Elizabeth V., Spelman, “Have We Got a Theory for You! Feminist Theory, Cultural Imperialism and the Demand for ‘The Woman's Voice,“’ reprinted in Women and Values: Readings in Recent Feminist Philosophy, ed. Marilyn, Pearsall (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1999).Google Scholar

41 Ibid., 15--16.

42 Ibid., 17.

43 See also Moody-Adams, “Gender and the Complexity of Moral Voices.“

44 Lugones and Spelman, “Have We Got a Theory for You!“

45 Marilyn Frye, The Politics of Reality, 16.

46 Card, “Feistiness.“