Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-22dnz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T06:38:03.251Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Tyranny of Abstractions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2009

William P. D. Wightman
Affiliation:
112 Rutten Lane, Yarnton, Oxford 0X5 1LR
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Presidential Address
Copyright
Copyright © British Society for the History of Science 1973

References

1 See, for example, McGuire, J. E. and Rattansi, P. M., ‘Newton and the pipes of Pan’, Notes and records of the Royal Society of London, xxi (1966), 108–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

2 Bacon, De sapientia veterum (London, 1609).Google Scholar

3 I am currently engaged on a critical essay in which the basis of this judgment is discussed.

4 In his The idea of progress (London, 1920).Google Scholar

5 Whittaker, E. T., ‘Some disputed questions in the philosophy of the physical sciences’, Proceedings of the Royal Society of Edinburgh, Section A, lxi (1942), 160–75.Google Scholar

6 Lucretius, , De rerum natura, i. 11. 262–4.Google Scholar

7 Erasmus, , Enchiridion militis christiani (1503).Google Scholar

8 Fernel, , De abditis rerum causis libri duo (Paris, 1548).Google Scholar

9 Smith, , Essays on philosophical subjects, ed. Black, J. and Hutton, J. (London, 1795).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

10 See especially Whitehead, A. N., Science and the modern world (Cambridge, 1926), p. 82Google Scholar, but the whole of Chapter 3 leads up to the notion. See also Chapter 4 (p. 85).

11 Letter from Jones, to Althorpe, , 5 10 1782Google Scholar, in Shore, John (Baron Teignmouth), Memoirs of the life, writings and correspondence of Sir William Jones (new edn., 2 vols., London, 1835).Google Scholar

12 Whitehead, , Process and reality (Cambridge, 1929), p. 55 and passim.Google Scholar

13 Sophist, 247Google Scholar E. See Cornford, F. M., Plato's theory of knowledge (London, 1935), p. 234–8Google Scholar for a discussion of the context.

14 Gilbert, , De magnete (London, 1600), Book V, chapter 12.Google Scholar

15 In the Everyman edition of An anatomical disquisition on the motion of the heart & blood in animals (London, 1923), the relevant passage is on p. 142.Google Scholar

16 His dogmatic hostility to mathematics as mere passamento dei pazzi ingegnosi (La cena de le ceneri [London, 1584], third dialogue) appears passim in his works. In the De immenso et innumera-bilibus (III, vi) the Platonic source of the above argument provides another example of the danger referred to in note 14. See Michel, P.-H., La cosmologie de Giordano Bruno (Paris, 1962), p. 223 and passim.Google Scholar

17 See Corsano, A., ‘Vico and mathematics’, in Tagliacozzo, G. and White, H. V. (eds.), Giambattista Vico. An international symposium (Baltimore, 1969), pp. 425–37.Google Scholar

18 ‘Discours préliminaire des éditeurs’, in the Encyclopédie, ou dictionnaire raisonné des sciences, des arts et des métiers, i (Paris, 1751), pp. vi and viiGoogle Scholar. A more detailed study of d'Alembert reveals an inconsistency of this judgment with his life-long aim to ‘prove’ that ‘geometry’ (to which he believed he had ‘reduced’ mechanics) alone gives certain knowledge. I can but suggest on the one hand that he was hoping to persuade as large a public as possible to invest in the Encyclopédie, and on the other that the inconsistency is only apparent. Medicine was not, nor ever could be, ‘exact’; but to force upon it the deductive, abstract method of mathematics was a bar to the attainment of such a degree of ‘knowledge’ as was possible. See the excellent biography, Jean d'Alembert. Science and the Enlightenment (Oxford, 1970)Google Scholar by Thomas L. Hankins, who, however, does not refer to this matter specifically.

19 Morrell, J. B., ‘The University of Edinburgh in the late eighteenth century: its scientific eminence and academic structure’, Isis, lxii (1971), 158.Google Scholar

20 Hegel's philosophy of nature, ed. and trans. Petry, M. J. (3 vols., London, 1970).Google Scholar

21 For an illustration of this tradition see, for example, Oken, Lorenz, Elements of physiophilosophy, trans. Tulk, A. (London, 1847).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

22 Hegel's philosophy of nature, i. 193.Google Scholar

23 Quoted by Auden, W. H. in A certain world (London, 1970), p. 333.Google Scholar

24 The English word ‘science’ in its present connotation was in fact first used in 1796 by Richard Kirwan; see the passage quoted in the OED entry on ‘science’: ‘Previous to the year 1780 mineralogy though tolerably well understood as an art could scarce be deemed a science.’ Much the same might have been said about chemistry, botany, geology, for example, but mechanics, optics, sound, static electricity, and (to a lesser extent) heat were firmly founded as departments of the science of physics. By the time Hegel was writing, only chemistry, and that but partially, could compete with physics.

25 Hegel, , Reason in history. A general introduction to the philosophy of history, ed. and trans. Hartmann, R. S. (Indianapolis, 1953), p. 87.Google Scholar

26 Cf. Joan Robinson's comment: ‘An equilibrium system, by its very nature, is cut off from reality. It is useless to interpret history in terms of it and illegitimate to appeal to history for evidence to support it. All it can do is to display the logical relations generated by its assumption’; from her Collected economic papers, (3 vols., Oxford, 19511965), iii. 19.Google Scholar See further Beer, Stafford, ‘The world, the flesh and the metal: the prerogatives of systems’, Nature, ccv (1965), 223–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar; the whole article might be regarded as an attack on the ‘futility of abstraction’.

27 ‘Either your experience is of no content or it is a perceptible amount of content or change. Your acquaintance with reality grows literally by buds or drops of perception’ (William James; quoted in Whitehead, , op. cit. [12], p. 94)Google Scholar. James comments: ‘Intellectually [i.e. by abstraction] and on reflection you can divide these into components, but as immediately given they come totally or not at all.’

28 See Hegel's philosophy of nature, i. 229 f.Google Scholar, but especially the ‘Addition’ on p. 231.

29 This is what I said ‘in my haste’. I now recognize that in respect of economics my remark was far too sweeping. I am again indebted to Mrs Robinson, who, in ‘What remains of Marxism’ (Robinson, , op. cit. [26], iii. 158–66)Google Scholar argues persuasively that comparison with the neo-classical (pre-Keynesian) equilibrium theory is ‘highly favourable to Marx’. But in ‘prophesying’ the collapse of capitalistic society on the analogy of the past, Marx was mixing somewhat dubious history with political ideology. Nevertheless, once more to plunder Mrs Robinson (‘Marxism, religion and science’, op. cit. p. 155)Google Scholar: ‘You have nothing to lose but [sc. under continuing capitalistic expansion] the prospect of a suburban house and a motor car would not have been much of a slogan.’

30 Plekhanov, , The materialist conception of history (New York, 1940)Google Scholar

31 To pick out lapidary phrases from Hegel's works is notoriously to invite misunderstanding; but the Zusatz on pp. 18–20 of Miller, A. V.'s recent Hegel's philosophy of mind (Oxford, 1971)Google Scholar is as free from danger of misunderstanding as most. A ‘sympathetic’ refutation of materialism will he found on p. 34.