Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-22dnz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T23:03:02.729Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Question of Properly Rights: Richard Owen's Evolutionism Reassessed

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2009

Evelleen Richards
Affiliation:
Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Wollongong, P.O. Box 1144, (Northfields Avenue), Wollongong, N.S.W. 2500, Australia.

Extract

When Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation, the anonymous evolutionary work which caused such a furore in mid-Victorian England, was published towards the close of 1844, Richard Owen, by then well-entrenched as the ‘British Cuvier’, received a complementary copy and addressed a letter to the author. This letter and how it should be interpreted have recently become the subject of historical debate, and this paper is directed at resolving the controversy. The question of Owen's attitude to the Vestiges argument is central to the larger historical problem of the views of this leading British morphologist and palaeontologist on the contentious issue of the ‘secondary causes’ of species. Owen wrote so little directly on this subject prior to 1858, that the letter in question, together with his two letters of 1848 to the rationalist publisher John Chapman, and the controversial conclusion to his On the Nature of Limbs (1849), constitute the major evidence that Owen in this period subscribed to a naturalistic theory of organic change. On the basis of this evidence, historians of biology have generally concurred with Owen's biographer grandson that Owen had a ‘certain leaning towards the theories enunciated by Robert Chambers [the Vestiges' author]’, but that his ‘official’ anti-transmutationist stance of the 1840s did not permit full public expression of his own views. As Ruse most recently summed up this historical consensus: Owen in the 1840s was ‘moving down a path not completely dissimilar from that followed by Chambers’, and he ‘tried to have matters two ways, praising Vestiges to its author and condemning it to its critics’.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © British Society for the History of Science 1987

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Quoted by Hobsbawm, E.J., The Age of Revolution: Europe 1789–1848, London, 1973, p. 336.Google Scholar

2 Cited in Desmond, A., Archetypes and Ancestors: Palaeontology in Victorian London, 1850–1875, London, 1982, p. 60.Google Scholar

3 Published in Rev. Owen, R., The Life of Richard Owen, 2 vols, London, 1894, Vol. 1, pp. 249252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar The location of the original letter is unknown.

4 Ibid., pp. 309–311. Desmond has identified Owen's correspondent as Chapman, , op. cit. (2), pp. 29, 210 (note 27).Google Scholar

5 Owen, R., On the Nature of Limbs, London, 1849, pp. 8586.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

6 Rev. Owen, R., op. cit. (3), p. 255.Google Scholar

7 MacLeod, R.M., ‘Evolutionism and Richard Owen, 1830–1868: an episode in Darwin's Century’, Isis, (1965), 56, pp. 259280, p. 261CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hodge, M.J.S., ‘The universal gestation of nature: Chambers' Vestiges and Explanations’, Journal of the History of Biology, (1972), 5, pp. 127151, pp. 133134CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Rudwick, M.J.S., The Meaning of Fossils: Episodes in the History of Palaeontology, London, 1972, p. 207Google Scholar; Bowler, P.J., Fossils and Progress: Palaeontology and the Idea of Progressive Evolution in the Nineteenth Century, N.Y., 1976, p. 93Google Scholar; Ospovat, D., ‘The influence of K.E. von Baer's embryology, 1828–1859: a reappraisal in light of Richard Owen's and William B. Carpenter's palaeontological application of “von Baer's law”’, Journal of the History of Biology, (1976), 9, pp. 128Google Scholar; Ospovat, D., ‘Perfect adaptation and teleological explanation: approaches to the problem of the history of life in the mid-nineteenth century’, Studies in the History of Biology, (1978), 2, pp. 3356Google ScholarPubMed; Ruse, M., The Darwinian Revolution: Science Red in Tooth and Claw, Chicago and London, 1979, pp. 124, 125, 127, 144, 228.Google Scholar

8 Ibid. Ruse seems not to have known of Brooke's reassessment at the time of writing. See Note 9.

9 Brooke, J.H., ‘Richard Owen, William Whewell and the Vestiges’, British Journal for the History of Science, (1977), 10, pp. 132145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

10 Brooke, J.H., ‘The natural theology of the geologists: some theological strata’. In: Jordanova, L.J. and Porter, R.S. (eds), Images of the Earth: Essays in the Environmental Sciences, Chalfont St Giles, 1979, pp. 3964, p. 41.Google Scholar

11 Ospovat, D., 1976, op. cit. (7), p. 22.Google Scholar

12 Ospovat, D., The Development of Darwin's Theory: Natural History, Natural Theology and Natural Selection, 1838–1859, Cambridge, 1981, p. 138.Google Scholar

13 Ibid., p. 285.

14 Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2), pp. 2937, p. 33.Google Scholar

15 Ibid. See also Richards, E., ‘The German Romantic Concept of Embryonic Repetition and its Role in Evolutionary Theory in England up to 1859’, Ph.D. dissertation, University of New South Wales, 1976, pp. 313315.Google Scholar

16 Desmond, A., ‘Richard Owen's reaction to transmutation in the 1830's’, British Journal for the History of Science, (1985), 18, pp. 2550.CrossRefGoogle Scholar See also Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2)Google Scholar; Young, R.M., ‘The historiographic and ideological contexts of the nineteenth century debate on man's place in nature’, in: Teich, M. and Young, R.M., eds, Changing Perspectives in the History of Science, London, 1973, pp. 344438Google Scholar; Shapin, S., ‘History of science and its sociological reconstructions’, History of Science, (1982), 20, pp. 157211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

17 Brooke, J.H., 1977, op.cit. (9), p. 135.Google Scholar

18 Rev. Owen, R., op. cit. (3), p. 252.Google Scholar

19 Brooke, J.H., 1977, op. cit. (9), p. 137.Google Scholar

20 Ibid., p. 134.

21 Ospovat, D., 1976, op. cit. (7); 1981, op. cit. (12), pp. 129135.Google Scholar For Huxley's opinion of Owen's embryology, see Notes 191 and 192.

22 Chambers, R., Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation, 10th edn., London, 1853, p. vi.Google Scholar

23 The terminology and the distinctions drawn are indebted to Russell, E.S.'s classic analysis, Form and Function: A Contribution to the Study of Animal Morphology, London, 1916, reprinted, 1972.Google Scholar See also Richards, , 1976, op. cit. (15)Google Scholar; and Gould, S.J., Ontogeny and Phylogeny, Cambridge (Mass.) and London, 1977.Google Scholar

24 Ospovat, D., 1976, op. cit. (7)Google Scholar; Richards, , op. cit. (15), Chapter 5.Google Scholar

25 Chambers, R., Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation, 1st edn., 1844, reprinted, N.Y., 1969, pp. 199213Google Scholar; Ruse, , 1979, op. cit. (7), pp. 102104.Google Scholar Chambers drew on three major sources for the embryological information in the first edition of Vestiges, two of which he acknowledged. They were: the work of the transcendentalist Fletcher, John (Rudiments of Physiology, Edinburgh, 1837)Google Scholar; a popular treatise on physiology by Perceval Barton Lord who seems to have been influenced by transcendental ideas while at Edinburgh (Popular Physiology, London, 1834)Google Scholar; and the third and unacknowledged source was William Carpenter's Physiology of 1841, see Note 29. Both Fletcher and Lord propounded the law of parallelism, while Carpenter adopted von Baer's law.

26 Sedgwick devoted twelve pages to his review of Vestiges to just such a selective critique of its embryology, Edinburgh Review, 1845, LXXXIII, pp. 185.Google Scholar Note that Sedgwick obtained his embryological information from the Cambridge professor of anatomy, William Clark, not from Owen (see text). Other early reviews which made much of the embryological confusion of Vestiges included those in Blackwood's Magazine (1845, LVII, pp. 448460)Google Scholar, Westminster Review (1845, XLIV, pp. 152203)Google Scholar, British Quarterly Review, (1845, I, pp. 490513)Google Scholar. It is interesting to note that Carpenter wrote a very sympathetic review of Vestiges which did not dwell upon its embryological inadequacies [British and Foreign Medical Review, (1845), XIX, pp. 155181].Google Scholar

27 von Baer, K.E., Uber die Entwickelungsgeschichte der Thiere: Beobachtung und Reflexion, Konigsberg, 1828, p. 225.Google Scholar For von Baer's explanation of his table, see pp. 229–230.

28 Barry, M., ‘Further observations on the unity of structure in the animal kingdom, and on congenital abnormalities, including ‘hermaphrodites;’ with some remarks on embryology, as facilitating animal nomenclature, classification, and the study of comparative anatomy’, Edinburgh New Philosophical Journal, (18361837), XXII, pp. 345364.Google Scholar See also Barry's previous paper, ‘On the unity of structure in the animal kingdom’, ibid., (1836–1837), XXII, pp. 116–141.

29 Carpenter, W.B., Principles of General and Comparative Physiology, 2nd edn., London, 1841, pp. 196197.Google Scholar

30 This is also the opinion of Ospovat, [1976, op. cit. (7), p. 13]Google Scholar; Ruse, [1979, op. cit. (7), p. 103]Google Scholar; and Gould, [1977, op. cit. (23), p. 103].Google Scholar

31 Vestiges, 1844, op. cit. (25), p. 212.Google Scholar The prior endorsement of parallelism occurs on pp. 199–203.

32 Gould, , 1977, op. cit. (23), pp. 109112.Google Scholar

33 Vestiges, 1844, op. cit. (25), p. 213.Google Scholar

34 Chambers argued by reference to Babbage's calculating machine, that the law that like produces like is subordinate to a higher law which on occasion permits the production of a higher form of life, ibid., p. 210. Thus new species are formed by law in accordance with a Divine plan, ibid., pp. 230–233. At the same time, as he insisted on a parallel between geological and biological uniformitarianism, he also admitted the direct action of the environment on the reproductive system (p. 229). This latter was Geoffrey's thesis, to which Owen was opposed (see Notes 77 and 78). However, in discussing the Vestiges thesis, Owen focused on the idea of a pre-ordained higher generative law (see Notes 61, 62, 69). In later editions of Vestiges, Chambers adopted the more Lamarckian explanation of an ‘inherent impulse’ to advance, although this was, of course, still Divinely induced. For a discussion of Chambers' changing evolutionary ideas and their relation to the romantic conception of nature and, in particular, the ideas of Geoffroy, see Hooykaas, R., ‘The parallel between the history of the earth and the history of the animal world’, Archives Intern. Hist. Sci. (1957), 10, pp. 318Google Scholar; Hodge, , 1972, op. cit. (7).Google Scholar

35 Geoffroy's major evolutionary writings are contained in two memoirs: ‘Mémoire où l'on se propose de rechercher dan quels rapports de structure organique et de parenté sont entre eux les animaux des âges historiques, et vivant actuellement, et les espèces antédiluviennes et perdues’, Mém. Mus. d'Hist. Nat. (1828), XVII, pp. 209229Google Scholar; ‘Le degré d'influence du monde ambiant pour modifier les formes animales; question intéressant l'origine des espèces téléosauriennes et successivement celle des animaux de l'époque actuelle’, Mém. Acad. Sc. (1833), XII, pp. 6392.Google Scholar See also Russell, , op. cit. (23), Chapter 5Google Scholar; Canguilhem, G. et al. , ‘Du développment à l'évolution au XIXe siecle’, Thalès (1960), pp. 363Google Scholar; Gould, , op. cit. (23), pp. 4952.Google Scholar

36 Vestiges, 1844, op. cit. (25), p. 219.Google Scholar It was this aspect of Chambers' mechanism from which Owen dissented, see Notes 68, 125. See text for Owen's conception of ‘transmutation’, and the basis of his anti-transmutationism.

37 See Ospovat, , 1976, op. cit. (7).Google Scholar

38 For instance, the table on pp. 226–227, Vestiges, op. cit. (25).

39 Vestiges, 10th edn., 1853, pp. cit. (22), Preface and pp. 147162Google Scholar; Ospovat, , 1976, op. cit. (7), p. 13, fn, 35Google Scholar; Ospovat, , 1981, op. cit. (12), p. 216.Google Scholar

40 Chambers, R., Explanations, 2nd edn., London, 1846, pp. 103109.Google Scholar Richard Yeo has documented how Chambers was able to exploit a similar controversial situation with respect to the nebular hypothesis in dealing with his critics: Yeo, R., ‘Science and intellectual authority in mid-nineteenth-century Britain: Robert Chambers and Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation’, Victorian Studies, (1984), 28, pp. 531, pp. 1819.Google Scholar

41 Owen, R., Lectures on the Comparative Anatomy and Physiology of the Invertebrate Animals, London, 1843, p. 24.Google Scholar Owen states only that Barry provided him with some notes for his Lectures, but he was clearly familiar with Barry's 1836/37 papers (see Note 28) and these were the obvious source of Owen's embryological references in his Hunterian Lectures of 1837 when he first began advocating the embryological law of divergence in opposition to the transmutationism of Grant and Geoffroy (see Note 79). See also Ospovat, , 1976, op. cit. (7), pp. 910Google Scholar; Ospovat, , 1981, op. cit. (12), pp. 130132Google Scholar; Desmond, A., 1985, op. cit. (16), pp. 2550, pp. 4649.Google Scholar Owen's relationship with Barry warrants closer investigation in view of their embryological and morphological affinity, and Barry's failure to protest Owen's apparent appropriation of his work (see below). They corresponded frequently and Barry regarded Owen as his mentor, dedicating his final work to him [British Museum (Natural History), hereafter referred to as BM(NH), Owen Correspondence, vol. 2, ff. 253–309; vol. 9, f. 214]. It was Owen who confirmed Barry's observation of the presence of spermatozoa ‘on, and apparently in, the fallopian ovum of a rabbit’ in 1842 (Royal College of Surgeons, Stone Watson Papers, Mss and Autographs).

42 BM(NH), Owen Correspondence, vol. 6, ff. 333338.Google Scholar Carpenter's earliest letter to Owen on this problem of priority is dated 20 August 1851. Although Carpenter put up a good fight, Owen wore him down over the following years, until in a final exasperated retort, dated 11 February 1854, Carpenter conceded defeat: ‘You will see that I have differentiated the principle which is properly yours from that which I thought to be mine, having been in the habit of stating it in Lectures for the last 12 or 14 years, and not being aware that it had been enunciated by anyone else. But I do not intend to make any claim to it whatever … In fact, I do not intend to make any claims to originality, being quite satisfied that my labours are doing good, and caring little about anything else.’ See also Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2), pp. 9293Google Scholar; Ospovat, , 1976, op. cit. (7), pp. 1819.Google Scholar

43 [Owen, R.], ‘Lyell—on life and its successive development’, Quarterly Review, (1851), 89, pp. 412451, p. 430, fn.Google Scholar

44 Milne-Edwards, H., ‘Considérations sur quelques principes relatifs à la classification naturelle des animaux’, Annales des Sciences Naturelles, (1844), 1 (3), pp. 6599.Google Scholar For a discussion of Milne-Edwards' views on development and their relation to those of von Baer and Owen, see Ospovat, , 1976, op. cit. (7), pp. 1012Google Scholar; Ospovat, , 1981, op. cit. (12), pp. 117140.Google Scholar

45 Owen, R., ‘Considérations sur le plan organique et le mode de développement des animaux’, Annales des Science Naturelles, (1844), 2 (3), pp. 162168.Google Scholar

46 Ibid., p. 162, fn.

47 Owen, R., ‘Proofs of Reviews, 1847–1882,’ BM(NH), OC, vol. 39Google Scholar. There are two relevant proofs in this collection, one dated ‘Quarterly Review’ 1851, and the other ‘Review of Archetype’ in “Quarterly” for 1852?’; Both have been extensively revised and amended in Owen's own hand, and much-pruned versions were published as ‘Professor Owen—progress of comparative anatomy’, Quarterly Review, (18511852), 90, pp. 363413Google Scholar; and ‘Generalizations of comparative anatomy’, ibid. (1853), 93, pp. 46–83. Their production was a collaborative process between Owen and William Broderip, naturalist and jurist, extending over almost 4 years, and documented in Broderip's correspondence with Owen. Lockhart, the editor of the conservative Quarterly, first approached Broderip in August 1849, requesting an article on Owen [BM(NH), OC, vol. 5, f. 176, Broderip to Owen], and the final revised proof of the second article was not received until May, 1853 (ibid., ff. 236–237). Close study of the various proofs and their final published versions reveals a lengthy process of arbitration between Owen and Lockhart (who argued that Owen did not require ‘minute vindication’ of his priority claims, Broderip to Owen, 23 May, 1852, ibid., ff. 213–214), with Broderip acting as go-between. Rupke has discussed the contents of the final published versions of these papers in some detail, but attributes their production entirely to Broderip and overlooks Owen's guiding hand: Rupke, N., ‘Richard Owen's Hunterian lectures on comparative anatomy and physiology, 1837–1855’, Medical History, (1985), 29, pp. 237258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

48 [Owen, R. and Broderip, W.], ‘Review of Archetype’, proof, op. cit. (47), p. 11, pp. 712.Google Scholar This statement was edited out by Lockhart in the published version, and the whole section on Owen's embryological researches was ‘pruned’ on Lockhart's insistence: ‘Generalizations of comparative anatomy’, op. cit. (47), pp. 59–65; Broderip, to Owen, , 26 05 1853, BM(NH), OC, vol. 5, ff. 236237.Google Scholar

49 ‘Review of Archetype’, op. cit. (47), p. 9.Google Scholar See also ‘Generalizations of comparative anatomy’, op. cit. (47), pp. 6263Google Scholar; ‘Lyell on life and its successive development’, op. cit. (43), p. 430Google Scholar, fn., where Owen gave the same references.

50 Owen, R., Lectures on the Comparative Anatomy and Physiology of the Invertebrate Animals, op. cit. (41), p. 368.Google Scholar

51 Ibid., pp. 369–370.

52 This interpretation is consistent with that of Ospovat, Note 44.

53 This seems to be the basis of his claim for precedence over von Baer [‘Lyell—on life…’, op. cit. (43)] and Barry, [‘Generalizations of comparative anatomy’, op. cit. (47), pp. 6162]Google Scholar. Both claims, however, are specious. It is significant that Owen refers to neither von Baer's 1828 publication (which contains the relevant 5th Scholion, Note 27) nor to Barry's second paper of 1837 (which contains Barry's diagram of divergent development, Note 28) in this connection. Nor did he ever cite Carpenter's 1841 publication throughout his dispute with Carpenter. The only conclusions possible are either that Owen was guilty of duplicity and deliberately suppressed the relevant publications, or, that he was not aware of their existence (which seems most unlikely in the case of Barry and Carpenter). With respect to von Baer, I have formed the opinion that Owen's claim to precedence was based on the simple fact that he did not read the relevant Scholion until its translation into English by Huxley in 1853 (see Note 54). Owen's German was not as good as he liked to make out, and he often required assistance with the translation of his German correspondence.

54 The second edition of Owen's Lectures on Invertebrates of 1855, reproduced substantially the same summary on development as that of 1843, but Owen conceded in a footnote that his propositions were ‘well supported and illustrated by von Baer’, and cited von Baer's Entwickelungsgeschichte of 1828 in this and other notes appended to this edition: Owen, R., Lectures on the Comparative Anatomy and Physiology of the Invertebrate Animals, 2nd edn., London, 1855, p. 645, fn.Google Scholar However, on the basis of the similarity between Owen's quotations from von Baer and Huxley's translation, his source was most likely the latter: ‘Fragments relating to philosophical zoology, selected from the works of K.E. von Baer’, (tr. Huxley, T.H.), in Henfrey, A. and Huxley, T.H. (eds), Scientific Memoirs, London, 1853, pp. 176238.Google Scholar

55 Brooke, , 1977, op. cit. (9) p. 137.Google Scholar

56 Op. cit. (3), p. 251. Brooke concedes that this sentence ‘sticks in the gullet’, op. cit. (9), p. 138.Google Scholar

57 In his Explanations, in rebutting the embryological criticisms of Vestiges, Chambers did refer to Owen's Lectures on Invertebrates, but not to the summary: Explanations, 1845, op. cit. (41), pp. 106107.Google Scholar The passage cited by Chambers is the second reference discussed in Note 58—and indicates that Chambers did follow up Owen's references. Significantly, Chambers interpreted Owen's reference to the early ‘vermiform’ stage of the human embryo as meaning that the human embryo at this stage was comparable to an invertebrate, and cited this passage in opposition to Sedgwick's criticism (see Note 26). Nevertheless, although he misconstrued Owen's embryology, he evidently did not construe Owen's reference to ‘the idea and diagram’ of Vestiges as criticism.

58 Owen, , Lectures on Invertebrates 1843, op. cit. (41), p. 147.Google Scholar Owen's second reference to the conclusion of the lecture ‘On the Metamorphosis of Insects’ (see text) is the same as the first reference cited in the 1851 account of his priority dispute with Milne-Edwards (see text). It is to the effect that the human embryo passes through the earlier forms of the vertebrates, and although it is superficially similar to an articulate in its very early stages, it does not actually represent one (ibid., p. 249). This is compatible with the Vestiges diagram, but hardly warrants the description of Owen's ‘true law’.

59 Brooke, , 1977, op. cit. (9), p. 137.Google Scholar

60 Other interpretations are, of course, possible. Owen may merely have been careless, or the letter may have been mistranscribed for publication.

61 [Owen, R.], ‘Darwin on the origin of species’, Edinburgh Review, (1860), 111, pp. 487532, 504505.Google Scholar See also pp. 497, 503, 508.

62 Ibid., p. 508. Note Owen's discussion of the distinctions and similarities between his conception of the forces controlling the ‘development of organized beings’ and those of the Vestiges author, and his related reference to his ‘true law’ of embryological development of 1843 (pp. 506–507). As Owen explained it, the ideological principle (‘the specific organizing principle’ which shapes the living thing to its functions) is opposed by a ‘general polarizing force’ which brings about repetition of parts (Owen's ‘irrelative repetition’) and similarity of forms–all the signs of unity of organization and of the archetype. The extent to which the teleological principle overcomes the general polarizing force is an index of the grade of the species. These antagonistic forces not only control individual development, but the development of life on earth. Owen first enunciated his conception of the principles of polarity in development in his major theoretical work On the Archetype and Homologies of the Vertebrate Skeleton, London, 1848, pp. 171172.Google Scholar See also Russell, , op. cit. (23), pp. 111112.Google Scholar

63 Owen, R., On the Anatomy of Vertebrates, vol. 3, London, 1868, pp. 807808.Google Scholar

64 [Owen, R.], ‘Lyell–on life and its successive development’, op. cit. (43), pp. 448450.Google Scholar See Ospovat, , 1981, op. cit. (12), pp. 136140.Google Scholar

65 Owen, , 1868, op. cit., pp. 794795.Google Scholar

66 Ibid., p. 797. In Owen's own words, the series evidences ‘(preordained) departures from parental type, probably sudden and seemingly monstrous, but adapting the progeny inheriting such modifications to higher purposes’.

67 Ibid., p. 795.

68 This would conform with Owen's conception of the antagonistic forces controlling development. The production of a new species is dependent upon the agency of the teleological principle, the ‘specific organizing force’, which ‘subdues and moulds’ the ‘general polarizing force’ in ‘subserviency to the exigencies of the resulting specific form’. See Note 62. The three toes of the Palaeotherium are the signs of irrelative repetition and are due to the action of the general polarizing force. The development of the extra toes is suppressed or arrested through the agency of the teleological principle which thus brings about the birth of the Hipparion, and ultimately, through further arrest of development, the single-toed modern horse.

69 Owen, , 1860, op. cit. (61), pp. 502503.Google Scholar See also Owen, R., On Parthenogenesis, or the Successive Production of Procreating Individuals from a Single Ovum, London, 1949, p. 3Google Scholar; Owen, R., ‘Presidential Address’, Report of the British Association for the Advancement of Science, (1858) Leeds, pp. xlixcx, p. lxxv. See also Note 15.Google Scholar

70 Owen, , 1868, op. cit. (63), p. 807.Google Scholar In all his writings on the topic, Owen seems, in the light of hindsight, to have been fumbling towards some conception of paedomorphosis: (literally, ‘shaped like a child’), the retention of youthful ancestral characters in later ontogenetic stages of descendants. See Gould, , op. cit. (23), pp. 221228.Google Scholar Owen's 1849 Hunterian Lectures on Generation [BM(NH), OC, vol. 38], warrant further study.

71 Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2), p. 78.Google Scholar

72 De Beer, G. (ed.), ‘Darwin's notebooks on transmutation of species, Part 1. First notebook’, Bulletin of the British Museum (Natural History), Historical Series, (1960), 2, p. 61.Google Scholar Note also Darwin's reference to Owen's contemporaneous criticism of the Meckel-Serres law (p. 62). Darwin also had recently been reading some of Geoffroy's work (pp. 53–55).

73 Hunter, J., Observations on Certain Parts of the Animal Oeconomy, with notes by Owen, Richard, London, 1837.Google Scholar

74 Ibid., pp. xxiv–xxvii; pp. 44–45.

75 Ibid., p. xxvi.

76 There are many instances of such ‘double monsters’ in the extant Hunterian Collection. See also ‘Ms. Catalogue of Physiological Series of Hunterian Museum’, original fascicules partly in John Hunter's hand corrected by William Clift, 1816, Royal College of Surgeons, 49.d.5.

77 Geoffrey St Hilaire, 1828 and 1833, op. cit. (35). In his 1833 Memoir, Geoffrey referred to monstrosities as ‘êtres ébauchés’—preparatory or precursory beings, ibid., p. 85. Geoffrey also expressed organic change as the resolution of polar conflict. He distinguished between two conflicting influences on the developing organism: a conservative factor inherent in the germ which tends to produce an offspring exactly like the parent; and a factor for change—the external influence of the environment. Any alteration in the environment resolves the conflict in favour of change, ibid., p. 69; 1828, op. cit., pp. 214–216.

78 Owen, , 1868, op. cit. (63), p. 795.Google Scholar

79 R. Owen, Hunterian Lectures 3 and 4,6 and 9 May, Royal College of Surgeons, MS 42.d.4, ff. 95–98; Desmond, , 1985, op. cit. (16), p. 48. See Note 41.Google Scholar

80 To wit: ‘If the progressive development of animal organization ever extended beyond the acquisition of the mature characters of the individual, so as to abrogate fixity of species by a transmutation of a lower into a higher organization, some evidence of it ought surely to be obtained …’, Owen, R., ‘Report on British fossil reptiles’, Part II, Report of the British Association for the Advancement of Science, (1841) pp. 60204, p. 197.Google Scholar Note the similarity between Owen's speculations ‘with all due diffidence’ on the relationship between the changing oxygen content of the atmosphere and the succession of the vertebrate classes in time (pp. 202–204), and Geoffrey's idea that as the respiratory medium changes it brings about a corresponding change in the species (see Note 77).

81 See Note 11.

82 [Owen, ], 1860, op. cit. (61), p. 500.Google Scholar

83 MacLeod, , 1965, op. cit. (7), pp. 264270Google Scholar; Ruse, , 1979, op. cit. (7), pp. 116125.Google Scholar

84 Russell, , op. cit. (23), pp. 312, 214.Google Scholar

85 On the Nature of Limbs, 1849, op. cit. (5).Google Scholar

86 Ospovat, , 1978, op. cit. (7), p. 36.Google Scholar

87 Morphology is not the science of fixed form or Gestalt, but of the formation and transformation of organic forms or Bildung. For a discussion of the historic process implicit in romantic morphology see Gode-von Aesch, A., Natural Science in German Romanticism, NY, 1966Google Scholar; Temkin, O., ‘German concepts of ontogeny and history around 1800’, Bulletin of the History of Medicine, (1950), 24, pp. 227246.Google ScholarPubMed

88 See Notes 62, 68 and 77.

89 Ospovat, , 1981, op. cit. (12), p. 133Google Scholar; Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2), pp. 4248, 50, 6572.Google Scholar See also Note 42.

90 Owen, , On the Nature of Limbs, op. cit. (5), pp. 8586Google Scholar; Ospovat, , 1978, op. cit. (7), pp. 4748.Google Scholar

91 See Note 4.

92 Op. cit. (69); Note 15.

93 Sedgwick to Owen [early 1850], BM(NH), Owen Correspondence, vol. 23, ff. 283–284. This letter is undated, but 1 have assigned a date of early 1850 to it on the basis of Sedgwick's references to his forthcoming book (see Note 163), and to his previous letter of Feb., 1850, ibid., ff. 249–250. See also ff. 306–307.

94 Ospovat, , 1978, op. cit. (7), p. 46.Google Scholar

95 Brooke, , 1979, op. cit. (10), p. 47.Google Scholar

96 Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2), pp. 2948, 6264Google Scholar; Ospovat, , 1978, op. cit. (7).Google Scholar

97 See text, Part 2.

98 Darwin, C., The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, London, 1859, pp. 488490Google Scholar; Gruber, H.E., Darwin on Man, London, 1974, Ch. 2 and p. 209.Google Scholar

99 [Owen, R.], ‘Darwin on the origin of species’, op. cit. (61), p. 514.Google Scholar See also Owen, R., ‘On the Aye-Aye’, Transactions of the Zoological Society, (1866), 5, pp. 3101, p. 92Google Scholar; Owen, , 1868, op. cit. (63), pp. 809, 814825.Google Scholar

100 By this stage, Owen seems to have been, like Chambers in 1844, advocating a form of continuous parallel evolution; see Hodge, , 1972, op. cit. (7).Google Scholar

101 Ospovat, , 1978, op. cit. (7).Google Scholar

102 Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2)Google Scholar; Desmond, , 1985, op. cit. (16)Google Scholar. See also Desmond, A., ‘Robert E. Grant: the social predicament of a pre-Darwinian transmutationist’, Journal of the History of Biology, (1984), 17, pp. 189223CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Desmond, A., ‘The making of institutional zoology in London 1822–1836: Parts 1 and 2’, History of Science, (1985), 23, pp. 153185; 223250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar Desmond offers by far the most perceptive and detailed contextual reconstruction of Owen's early intellectual and institutional milieu. But see also Rupke, , op. cit. (47).Google Scholar

103 See Note 3.

104 Desmond, , 1982, op. cit, (2), pp. 115121Google Scholar; Desmond, , 1985, op. cit. (16).Google Scholar

105 Desmond, , 1985Google Scholar, ibid., pp. 41–43. Note Gould's remarks on Geoffrey's relation of the young ape to man, with its implication of a paedomorphic theory of human origins: Gould, , op. cit. (23), pp. 353355Google Scholar, and refer to Note 70.

106 Desmond, , 1985, op. cit. (16), pp. 4345, 4950.Google Scholar

107 Ibid., pp. 47–49. See Notes 41 and 79.

108 See Note 102. Desmond stresses these aspects of Owen's anti-transmutationism over and over in his writings. This is also the thrust of Ospovat's criticism of Brooke's interpretation of Owen's Vestiges letter (see Note 13). Owen himself drew these distinctions between his own position and that of the ‘transmutationists’ in his 1860 review of The Origin [Owen, , 1860, op. cit. (61), pp. 500506].Google Scholar

109 ‘Naturalistic’ in the sense that Owen subscribed to the belief that natural laws were the basis of Omnipotent design and that all causes were hence ‘secondary’. See text, Part 1.

110 See also Ospovat, , 1978, op. cit. (7), pp. 4748.Google Scholar

111 Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2), p. 37Google Scholar; Farley, J. and Geison, G.L., ‘Science, politics and spontaneous generation in nineteenth-century France: the Pasteur-Pouchet Debate’, in Darwin to Einstein: Historical Studies on Science and Belief, Chant, C. and Fauvel, J. (eds.), Harlow and N.Y., 1980, pp. 107133.Google Scholar

112 Owen, R., ‘Manuscripts, notes and synopses of lectures, 1828–1841’, Hunterian Lectures, 1840Google Scholar, Lecture 2, BM(NH), OC, vol. 38, ff. 28, 23.

113 Millhauser, M.Just before Darwin: Robert Chambers and Vestiges, Connecticut, 1959, pp. 93, 94, 99Google Scholar; Gillispie, C.C., Genesis and Geology, N.Y., 1959, p. 104.Google Scholar

114 Lenoir, T., The Strategy of Life: Teleology and Mechanics in Nineteenth Century German Biology, Dordrecht, 1982.Google Scholar As late as 1876, von Baer was still arguing for the spontaneous generation of complex organisms in opposition to natural selection (ibid., p. 263). Owen discussed (and rejected) such speculations within the context of German physiology in his 1840 lectures [op. cit. (112), ff. 27–29. Note Owen's references to Oken]. This was almost certainly one of the six possible ‘secondary causes’ of the production of new species Owen claimed to know in his 1848 letter to Chapman (see Note 4). Note also William Carpenter's review of Vestiges where he stated his own preference for such an explanation and defended the experiments of Crosse, and Weekes, [op. cit. (26), pp. 169181].Google Scholar

115 Brooke, , 1977, op. cit. (9), pp. 135136.Google Scholar

116 Owen, , 1860, op. cit. (61), p. 514.Google Scholar See also Note 99. See Farley and Geison for a discussion of the political dimensions of the Pasteur-Pochet Debate, op. cit. (111).

117 Owen, , 1868, op. cit. (63), p. 814.Google Scholar Owen's expression ‘party of order’ is interesting. The ‘party of order’ was the name the French gave to the union of conservative and formerly moderate forces with the old regimes against the revolutionary forces of 1848. See Hobsbawm, E.J., The Age of Capital, 1848–1875, London, 1975, p. 17Google Scholar; Farley, and Geison, , op. cit. (111).Google Scholar

118 Brooke, , 1979, op. cit. (10), p. 53.Google Scholar See also Young, R.M. ‘Natural Theology, Victorian Periodicals and the Fragmentation of a Common Context’Google Scholar, in Chant, and Fauvel, , op. cit. (111), pp. 69107.Google Scholar

119 Cf. MacLeod, , op. cit. (7).Google Scholar

120 Desmond, , 1985, op. cit. (16), p. 50Google Scholar; Ruse, , op. cit. (7), Ch. 5.Google Scholar

121 Herbert, S., ‘The place of man in the development of Darwin's theory of transmutation’, Part 2, Journal of the History of Biology, (1977), 10, pp. 155227, pp. 156157.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

122 See Hodge, , 1972, op. cit. (7), p. 134.Google Scholar

123 Rev. Owen, R., 1894, op. cit. (3), vol. 1, pp. 252256.Google Scholar

124 Reprinted in Brooke, , 1977, op. cit. (9), p. 141.Google Scholar

125 Ibid., p. 138.

126 Ibid., p. 142.

127 See Note 8.

128 Murchison, to Owen, , 2 04 1845Google Scholar, in Rev. Owen, R., op. cit. (3), p. 254.Google Scholar

129 Brooke, , 1977, op. cit. (9), p. 142.Google Scholar

130 Owen, to Whewell, , 22 02 1845Google Scholar, quoted in Brooke, ibid., p. 140.

131 Owen, to Whewell, , 14 02 [1845]Google Scholar, ibid., p. 142.

132 Ibid., p. 134.

133 Rev. Owen, R., op. cit. (3).Google Scholar

134 Ibid., pp. 309–310. See also Owen's second letter to Chapman, , pp. 310311. See Note 4.Google Scholar

135 Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2), p. 35.Google Scholar

136 Owen, , On Parthenogenesis, op. cit. (69).Google Scholar

137 Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2), pp. 210211.Google Scholar

138 Whewell, , Indications of the Creator, London, 1846, Preface, p. 21.Google Scholar Quoted in Brooke, , 1977, op. cit. (9), p. 139.Google Scholar

139 Ruse, , op. cit. (7), p. 127.Google Scholar

140 Ibid., p. 270.

141 Owen's expression, Owen, to Powell, , 26 01 1850Google Scholar, cited in Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2), p. 46Google Scholar; cf. Brooke's commentary on this letter, 1979, op. cit. (10), pp. 40–41. The ‘Puseyites’ were the Anglo-Catholic followers of E.B. Pusey who denounced science for its incompatability with revealed religion. Although Owen associated his critic with the Puseyites, the doctrinal affiliations of the author of the articles are not so clear cut. He seems, if anything, to have been an admirer of Francis W. Newman, and, when challenged by Owen, claimed that it was not the policy of the Spectator to ‘set a mere theologic dogma in opposition to an established scientific fact’. ‘Christianity and Civilization’, The Manchester Spectator, 1849: 24 November, p. 4Google Scholar; 1 December, p. 4; 8 December, pp. 4–5; 22 December, p. 4.

142 Ruse, , op. cit. (7), p. 129Google Scholar; Hobsbawm, E.J., Industry and Empire, Harmondsworth, 1979, p. 77Google Scholar; Hobsbawm, , 1975, op. cit. (117), Ch. 1.Google Scholar

143 Brooke, , 1979, op. cit. (10), p. 47.Google Scholar

144 Owen, , 1868, op. cit. (63), p. 796Google Scholar, fn. See also Owen, , 1860, op. cit. (61), p. 511Google Scholar; 1866, op. cit. (99), p. 90.

145 Owen, R., On the Nature of Limbs, 1849Google Scholar; Owen's own interleaved copy with his autograph notes and memoranda, BM(NH), OC, 18, pp. 85–92.

146 The Manchester Spectator was founded in 1849 and ceased publication in 1851. Judging by its leaders, it was competing for the same middle-class provincial readers as its more successful rivals, the Manchester Guardian and the Manchester Examiner and Times. See Read, D., Press and People, 1790–1850, London, 1961Google Scholar; Koss, S., The Rise and Fall of the Political Press in Britain, vol. 1, ‘The Nineteenth Century’, London, 1981, pp. 6062.Google Scholar

147 See Note 141.

148 ‘Christianity and Civilization’, Manchester Spectator, 3rd article, 8 12, 1849, p. 4.Google Scholar

149 Ibid., 1st article, 24 November, 1849, p. 4.

150 Ibid., 3rd article, 8 December.

151 Ibid.

152 See, for instance, Owen, , 1848, op. cit. (62), pp. 8, 7375.Google Scholar Owen later wrote a laudatory Brittanica article on Oken, 8th edn., 1858–1859. See Rupke, , op. cit. (47), pp. 249, 252.Google Scholar

153 English translation of 3rd German edn., Zurich, 1843, by Tulk, A. for the Ray Society, as Elements of Physiophilosophy, London, 1847.Google Scholar See Oken, to Owen, , 12 01 1847Google Scholar, BM(NH), OC, vol. 20, ff. 362–363.

154 See Note 53.

155 The Zoologist, (1847), 5, Preface, pp. v–x.Google Scholar

156 ‘Minutes of the Ray Society, from its commencement in 1844 to 31 December, 1847’, October 16 and November 5, 1847, Ray Society Archives, BM(NH).

157 Ibid., 5 November 1847.

158 Ibid., 19 November and 17 December 1847. See also copy of letter of 20 December from Thomas Bell to William [Thompson].

159 See Huxley, T.H., ‘Owen's position in the history of anatomical science’Google Scholar, in Life of Richard Owen, op. cit. (3), vol. 2, pp. 273332, p. 313.Google Scholar

160 Hodge, M.J.S., ‘England’, in Click, T.F. (ed.), The Comparative Reception of Darwinism, Austin and London, 1974, pp. 2526.Google Scholar

161 Desmond makes this point with respect to Owen's leanings towards Geoffroyian transcendental anatomy: 1984, op. cit. (102), pp. 218–219.

162 Hugh Miller referred to the author of Vestiges as ‘the most popular contemporary expounder of Oken's hypothesis’, Miller, H., Footprints of the Creator, 4th edn., Edinburgh (1851), p. 274.Google Scholar See also the Athenaeum review of Oken's Physiophilosophy, 2 October 1847.

163 Sedgwick, A., A Discourse on the Studies of the University of Cambridge, 5th edn., Cambridge, 1850, Supplement to the Appendix, pp. 283, 230.Google Scholar

164 Ibid., Preface, p. ccxiv; see also pp. ccvi–ccxviii.

165 Owen, to Powell, , 26 01 1850Google Scholar, cited in Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2), p. 46Google Scholar; Note 141.

166 Manchester Spectator, 22 12 1849, p. 4Google Scholar. Brooke has republished Owen's letter entire, 1977, op. cit.(9), p. 143.

167 Manchester Spectator, 22 12 1849, p. 4.Google Scholar Owen preserved the entire ‘Puseyite’ response along with his own letter to the editor, see Note 145.

168 See Note 166.

169 See Desmond, A., ‘Artisan resistance and evolution in Britain 1819–1848’Google Scholar, Osiris, forthcoming.

170 Sedgwick wanted information on the incidence of larval sexual precocity (paedogenesis), and asked: ‘… with low animals which have more than one larva type, and exhibit the parthenogenesis of certain forms, the ultimate form, or perfect animal is always of one specific type. Is it not so?’ Sedgwick to Owen, 1850, op. cit. (93). To which Owen, as the strict inductivist, responded, keeping to the facts and giving no hint of his heretical speculations: ‘not any of these facts of larval fecundity … support… “progressive development”. The most complex cases of Parthenogenesis only show a more roundabout way of arriving at the specific structure from which the generative process started.’ Owen to Sedgwick, ibid., f. 285; cf. Owen, , 1860 (61), pp. 502503Google Scholar, Note 69.

171 Sedgwick, , 1850, op. cit. (163), Preface, p. ccxxvii.Google Scholar

172 Political considerations aside, Desmond makes the point that Owen's ‘timing was inopportune’. His transcendentalism was out of phase with the growing positivism and secular naturalism of contemporary science. Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2), p. 48.Google Scholar

173 Desmond, ibid., pp. 41, 79–80.

174 Ibid., Chapter 2.

175 See references, Notes 2, 7 and 102.

176 Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2), p. 78Google Scholar; Lenoir, , op. cit. (114), pp. 263270.Google Scholar

177 See Desmond's remarks on the London ‘idealist community’ of the 1860s (those like Argyll and Mivart who championed Owen's views) and their lack of an effective power base by comparison with die pro-Darwinian scientific naturalists: Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2), pp. 176177.Google Scholar

178 Owen, R., ‘On metamorphosis and metagenesis’, Notices of the Meetings of the Royal Institution, 7 02 1851, pp. 916.Google Scholar

179 Owen, , 1858, op. cit. (69), p. liGoogle Scholar. See Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2), pp. 6162.Google Scholar

180 Ibid., p. 62.

181 [Huxley, T.H.], ‘The vestiges of creation’, British and Foreign Medico-Chirurgical Review, (1854), XIII, pp. 425439.Google Scholar See Ruse's comments on this review, 1979, op. cit. (7), p. 143.

182 Huxley, , ‘Owen's position in the history of anatomical science’, op. cit. (159), pp. 312320.Google Scholar

183 Ibid., pp. 320–330. See Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2), Chs. 1 and 2Google Scholar; Ruse, , 1979, op. cit. (7), Ch. 6.Google Scholar Both Desmond and Ruse offer a revisionist interpretation of the Owen-Huxley clashes of the fifties, and Ruse suggests that Huxley's ‘baiting of Owen’ in the fifties pushed Owen into opposition to Darwinism, pp. 144–145.

184 See Owen's comments facing pp. 84, 85 in his personal copy of On the Nature of Limbs, op. cit. (145). Note also the quotation inside the front cover.

185 Owen, , 1860, op. cit. (61), p. 511.Google Scholar

186 Powell, R.S.S. Baden, Essays on the Spirit of the Inductive Philosophy, the Unity of Worlds, and the Philosophy of Creation, London, 1855, pp. 333, 365411 (n.b. pp. 400–401), 456457.Google Scholar See also Desmond, , 1982, op. cit. (2), pp. 4647Google Scholar; Bowler, , op. cit. (7), p. 103.Google Scholar

187 ‘I am much obliged to thy striking out the passage on the possible organic origin of all things’, Barry, to Owen, , 11 09, [1854], BM(NH), OC, vol. 2, ff. 303304.Google Scholar I am aware of the ambiguity of this passage, and I have been unable to trace the publication to which it refers. Nevertheless, it seems likely that Barry, who died not long after this was written, was another of those von Baerians who saw in embryogenesis a model for the derivation of species. Darwin's famous diagram of divergence in The Origin could be superimposed over Barry's 1837 ‘Tree of Animal Development’. Barry, like Owen, was also influenced by Geoffroy, and certain of his 1837 statements could be given an evolutionary interpretation: Barry, , 18361837, op. cit. (28), pp. 362363.Google Scholar See also Note 41. In any case, Owen's censorship of this (admittedly ambiguous) passage, illustrates my point of the degree of caution he had adopted in the post-1849 period.

188 I have discussed this elsewhere. See Richards, E., ‘Darwin and the descent of woman’, in Oldroyd, D. and Langham, I. (eds), The Wider Domain of Evolutionary Thought, Dordrecht, 1983, pp. 57111, pp. 8797.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

189 Bowler, , op. cit. (7), Ch. 5Google Scholar; Ospovat, , 1976, op. cit. (7), and 1981, op. cit. (12), Ch. 5Google Scholar; Desmond, , 1982, op. cit., Chs. 1 and 2 and passim; 1985, op. cit. (16), p. 49.Google Scholar

190 Ospovat, , 1981, op. cit. (12), pp. 159165, 174176.Google Scholar

191 Huxley, , ‘Owen's position in the history of anatomical science,’ op. cit. (159), p. 299, fn.Google Scholar

192 Ibid., p. 320. In a period when embryology was assuming increasing importance as an arbiter in settling questions of comparative anatomy, Owen fought a rear-guard action against this trend. Thus Owen, in contrast to Huxley, refused to regard embryology as the criterion of homology. See Russell, , op. cit. (23), Ch. 10.Google Scholar However, although they received short shrift from Huxley, Owen had cogent reasons for his stance, and they were consistent with his conception of development: Owen, , On the Anatomy of Vertebrates, vol. 1, London (1866), pp. xxixxv.Google Scholar

193 See Huxley, to Leuckart, , 1859Google Scholar, in Life and Letters of Thomas Henry Huxley (ed. Huxley, L.), 2 vols., London, 1900, vol. 1, pp. 162163Google Scholar; see also Huxley, to Darwin, , 1859Google Scholar, ibid., p. 175. See also references in Note 183.

194 Lenoir, , op. cit. (114), pp. 263270.Google Scholar