Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-4rdrl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-29T21:22:43.986Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Dynamic properties of computably enumerable sets

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 February 2010

S. B. Cooper
Affiliation:
University of Leeds
T. A. Slaman
Affiliation:
University of Chicago
S. S. Wainer
Affiliation:
University of Leeds
Get access

Summary

Abstract

A set A ⊆ ω is computably enumerable (c.e.), also called recursively enumerable, (r.e.), or simply enumerable, if there is a computable algorithm to list its members. Let ε denote the structure of the c.e. sets under inclusion. Starting with Post [1944] there has been much interest in relating the definable (especially ε-definable) properties of a c.e. set A to its “information content”, namely its Turing degree, deg(A), under ≤T, the usual Turing reducibility. [Turing 1939]. Recently, Harrington and Soare answered a question arising from Post's program by constructing a nonemptly ε-definable property Q(A) which guarantees that A is incomplete (A <TK). The property Q(A) is of the form (∃C)[AmC & Q(A, C)], where AmC abbreviates that “A is a major subset of C”, and Q(A,C) contains the main ingredient for incompleteness.

A dynamic property P(A), such as prompt simplicity, is one which is defined by considering how fast elements elements enter A relative to some simultaneous enumeration of all c.e. sets. If some set in deg(A) is promptly simple then A is prompt and otherwise tardy. We introduce here two new tardiness notions, small-tardy (A, C) and Q-tardy(A, C). We begin by proving that small-tardy(A, C) holds iff A is small in C (AsC) as defined by Lachlan [1968]. Our main result is that Q-tardy(A, C) holds iff Q(A,C). Therefore, the dynamic property, Q-tardy(A, C), which is more intuitive and easier to work with than the ε-definable counterpart, Q(A,C), is exactly equivalent and captures the same incompleteness phenomenon.

Type
Chapter
Information
Computability, Enumerability, Unsolvability
Directions in Recursion Theory
, pp. 105 - 122
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1996

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×