Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-c654p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-31T08:15:58.320Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

Kostas Kampourakis
Affiliation:
Université de Genève
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Akey, J. M., Ruhe, A. L., Akey, D. T., et al. (2010). Tracking footprints of artificial selection in the dog genome. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 107(3), 1160–1165.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Albert, F. W., Carlborg, O., Plyusnina, I., et al. (2009). Genetic architecture of tameness in a rat model of animal domestication. Genetics 182, 541–554.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alekshun, M. N. and Levy, S. B. (2007). Molecular mechanisms of antibacterial multidrug resistance. Cell 128(6), 1037–1050.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Alexander, D. R. (2013). The implications of evolutionary biology for religious belief. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, 179–204.Google Scholar
Alexopoulos, J. S., Grievel, R. A. F., and Robertson, P. B. (1988). Microscopic lamellar deformation features in quartz: discriminative characteristics of shock-generated varieties. Geology 16(9), 796–779.2.3.CO;2>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alizon, S., Luciani, F., and Regoes, R. R. (2011). Epidemiological and clinical consequences of within-host evolution. Trends in Microbiology 19(1), 24–32.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Allchin, D. (2005). The dilemma of dominance. Biology and Philosophy 20, 427–451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alvarez, L. W., Alvarez, W., Asaro, F., and Michel, H. V. (1980). Extraterrestrial cause for the Cretaceous–Tertiary extinction. Science 208(4448), 1095–1108.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Appel, T. A. (1987). The Cuvier–Geoffroy Debate: French Biology in the Decades Before Darwin. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Arabatzis, T. and Kindi, V. (2008). The problem of conceptual change in the philosophy and history of science. In Vosniadou, S. (Ed.) International Handbook of Research on Conceptual Change. New York and London: Routledge, 345–373.Google Scholar
Ariew, A. (2003). Ernst Mayr’s “Ultimate/Proximate” distinction reconsidered and reconstructed. Biology & Philosophy 18, 553–565.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ariew, A. (2007). Teleology. In Hull, D. and Ruse, M. (Eds.) The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 160–181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ariew, A. and Lewontin, R. C. (2004). The confusions of fitness. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55, 347–363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arthur, W. (2002). The emerging conceptual framework of evolutionary developmental biology. Nature 415, 757–764.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Arthur, W. (2004). Biased Embryos and Evolution. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arthur, W. (2011). Evolution: A Developmental Approach. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Asher, Y. M. and Kemler-Nelson, D. G. (2008). Was it designed to do that? Children’s focus on intended function in their conceptualization of artifacts. Cognition 106, 474–483.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Athanasiou, K. and Papadopoulou, P. (2011). Conceptual ecology of the evolution acceptance among Greek education students: knowledge, religious practices and social influences. International Journal of Science Education, .
Atran, S. (2004). In Gods We Trust: The Evolutionary Landscape of Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Audi, R. (2009). Religion and the politics of science: can evolutionary biology be religiously neutral?Philosophy & Social Criticism 35(1–20), 23–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, R. (2011). Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge (3rd edn.). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Avise, J. C. (2010). Inside the Human Genome: A Case for Non-Intelligent Design. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ayala, F. J. (2006). Darwin and Intelligent Design. Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press.Google Scholar
Ayala, F. J. (2007). Darwin’s Gift to Science and Religion. Washington, DC: Joseph Henry Press.Google Scholar
Ayala, F. J. (2009). Molecular evolution. In Ruse, M. and Travis, J. (Eds.) Evolution: The First Four Billion Years. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, 132–151.Google Scholar
Ayala, F. J. (2010a). Am I a Monkey?Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Ayala, F. J. (2010b). The difference of being human: morality. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 107(2), 9015–9022.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ayala, F. J. (2013). Biology and religion: the case for evolution. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, 161–178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barlow, N. (Ed.) (2005) [1958]. The Autobiography of Charles Darwin 1809–1882. New York: W.W. Norton.Google Scholar
Bateson, P. and Gluckman, P. (2011). Plasticity, Robustness, Development and Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baum, D. A. and Offner, S. (2008). Phylogenies and tree-thinking. The American Biology Teacher 70(4), 222–229.Google Scholar
Baum, D. and Smith, S. (2013). Tree Thinking: An Introduction to Phylogenetic Biology. Greenwood Village, CO: Roberts and Company Publishers.Google Scholar
Baum, D. A., DeWitt Smith, S., and Donovan, S. S. (2005). The tree thinking challenge. Science 310, 979–980.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Beatty, J. (1984). Chance and natural selection. Philosophy of Science 51(2), 183–211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beatty, J. (1994). The proximate/ultimate distinction in the multiple careers of Ernst Mayr. Biology & Philosophy 9, 333–356.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beatty, J. (1995). The evolutionary contingency thesis. In Wolters, G. and Lennox, J. G. (Eds.) Concepts, Theories, and Rationality in the Biological Sciences: The Second Pittsburgh-Konstanz Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press, 45–81.Google Scholar
Beatty, J. (2006). Replaying life’s tape. Journal of Philosophy CIII(7), 336–362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beatty, J. (2010). Reconsidering the importance of chance variation. In Müller, G. and Pigliucci, M. (Eds.) Evolution: The Extended Synthesis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 21–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bechtel, W. (2013). Understanding biological mechanisms: using illustrations from circadian rhythm research. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) Philosophical Issues in Biology Education. Springer: Dordrecht, 487–510.Google Scholar
Bechtel, W. and Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: a mechanistic alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of the Biological and Biomedical Sciences 36, 421–441.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Belyaev, D. K. (1979). Destabilizing selection as a factor in domestication. Journal of Heredity 70, 301–308.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Benton, M. (2009). Paleontology and the history of life. In Ruse, M. and Travis, J. (Eds.) Evolution: The First Four Billion Years. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 80–104.Google Scholar
Benton, M. J. and Donoghue, P. C. J. (2007). Paleontological evidence to date the tree of life. Molecular Biology and Evolution 24, 26–53.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Berger, L. R., de Ruitter, D. J., Churchill, S. E., et al. (2010). Australopithecus sediba: a new species of Homo-like Australopith from South Africa. Science 328, 195–204.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Berkman, M. and Plutzer, E. (2010). Evolutionism, Creationism, and the Battle to Control America’s Schools. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berkman, M. and Plutzer, E. (2011). Defeating Creationism in the courtroom, but not in the classroom. Science 331(6016), 404–405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berkman, M. and Plutzer, E. (2012). An evolving controversy: the struggle to teach science in science classes. The American Educator Summer, 12–23.
Blancke, S., Hjermitslev, H. H., Braeckman, J., and Kjærgaard, P. C. (2013). Creationism in Europe: facts, gaps and prospects. Journal of the American Academy of Religion, .CrossRef
Bloom, P. (2004). Descartes’ Baby: How the Science of Child Development Explains What Makes Us Human. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Bloom, P. and Weisberg, D. S. (2007). Childhood origins of adult resistance to science. Science 316, 996–997.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bock, W. J. (1980). The definition and recognition of biological adaptation. American Zoologist 20(1), 217–227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bohor, B. F., Foord, E. E., Modreski, P. J., and Triplehorn, D. M. (1984). Mineralogic evidence for an impact event at the Cretaceous–Tertiary boundary. Science 224(4651), 867–869.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bowler, P. J. (1975). The changing meaning of evolution. Journal of the History of Ideas 36(1), 95–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowler, P. J. (1976). Malthus, Darwin and the concept of struggle. Journal of the History of Ideas 37(4), 631–650.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bowler, P. J. (1983). The Eclipse of Darwinism: Anti-Darwinian Evolution Theories in the Decades around 1900. Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Bowler, P. J. (2005). Revisiting the eclipse of Darwinism. Journal of the History of Biology 38, 19–32.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bowler, P. J. (2007). Monkey Trials and Gorilla Sermons: Evolution and Christianity from Darwin to Intelligent Design. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowler, P. J. (2009a). Evolution: The History of an Idea. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Bowler, P. J. (2009b). Geographical distribution in the Origin of Species. In Ruse, M. and Richards, R. J. (Eds.) The Cambridge Companion to the “Origin of Species.”Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 153–172.Google Scholar
Bowler, P. J. (2013). Darwin Deleted: Imagining a World Without Darwin. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowler, P. J. and Morus, I. R. (2005). Making Modern Science: A Historical Survey. Chicago, IL: The Continuum University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyer, P. (2001). Religion Explained: The Evolutionary Origins of Religious Thought. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Branch, G. and Scott, E. C. (2009). The latest face of Creationism. Scientific American 300(1), 92–99.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brandon, R. N. (1990). Adaptation and Environment. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Brem, S. K., Ranney, M., and Schindel, J. (2003). Perceived consequences of evolution: college students perceive negative personal and social impact in evolutionary theory. Science Education 87(2), 181–206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brigandt, I. (2013). Intelligent Design and the nature of science: philosophical and pedagogical points. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, 205–238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brigandt, I. and Love, A. C. (2010). Evolutionary novelty and the evo-devo synthesis: field notes. Evolutionary Biology 37, 93–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brigandt, I. and Love, A. C. (2012). Conceptualizing evolutionary novelty: moving beyond definitional debates. Journal of Experimental Zoology (Mol. Dev. Evol.) 318B, 417–427.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brooke, J. H. (1991). Science and Religion: Some Historical Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brooke, J. H. (2001). The Wilberforce–Huxley debate: why did it happen?Science & Christian Belief 13(2), 127–141.Google Scholar
Brooke, J. H. (2009a). Darwin and Victorian Christianity. In Hodge, J. and Radick, G. (Eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Darwin (2nd edn.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 197–218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brooke, J. H. (2009b). “Laws impressed on matter by the creator”? The Origin and the question of religion. In Ruse, M. and Richards, R. J. (Eds.) The Cambridge Companion to the “Origin of Species.”Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 256–274.Google Scholar
Brooke, J. H. and Numbers, R. L. (2010). Science and Religion Around the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Browne, J. (2003a) [1995]. Charles Darwin: Voyaging. London: Pimlico.Google Scholar
Browne, J. (2003b) [2002]. Charles Darwin: The Power of Place. London: Pimlico.Google Scholar
Browne, J. (2006). Darwin’s “Origin of Species”: A Biography. London: Atlantic Books.Google Scholar
Burian, R. M. (1992). Adaptation: historical perspectives. In Keller, E. F. and Lloyd, E. A. (Eds.) Keywords in Evolutionary Biology. Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press, 7–12.Google Scholar
Burian, R. M. (2013). On concepts that change with the advance of science: comments on Lennox. In Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (Eds.) Concepts and their Role in Knowledge: Reflections on Objectivist Epistemology. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press, 185–199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burian, R. M. and Kampourakis, K. (2013). Against “genes for”: could an inclusive concept of genetic material effectively replace gene concepts? In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, 597–628.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carey, S. (1985). Conceptual Change in Childhood. Cambridge, MA and London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Carey, S. (2009). The Origin of Concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carroll, S. B. (2003). Genetics and the making of Homo sapiens. Nature 422, 849–857.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Carroll, S. B. (2005a). Endless Forms Most Beautiful: The New Science of Evo-Devo. New York: W.W. Norton.Google Scholar
Carroll, S. B. (2005b). Evolution at two levels: on genes and form. PLoS Biology 3, 1159–1166.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cavicchioli, R. (2011). Archaea: timeline of the third domain. Nature Reviews Microbiology 9, 51–61.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Chi, M. T. H. (2008). Three types of conceptual change: belief revision, mental model transformation and categorical shift. In Vosniadou, S. (Ed.) International Handbook of Research on Conceptual Change. New York and London: Routledge, 61–82.Google Scholar
Ciccarelli, F. D., Doerks, T., Von Mering, C., Creevey, C. J., Snel, B., and Bork, P. (2006). Toward automatic reconstruction of a highly resolved tree of life. Science 311, 1283–1287.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cleland, C. E. (2002). Methodological and epistemic differences between historical science and experimental science. Philosophy of Science 69, 474–496.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cleland, C. E. (2011). Prediction and explanation in historical natural science. British Journal of Philosophy of Science 62, 551–582.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cleland, C. E. and Zerella, M. (2013). What is life? In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, 31–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohn, M. J. and Tickle, C. (1999). Developmental basis of limblessness and axial regionalization in snakes. Nature 399, 474–479.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conway Morris, S. (2003). Life’s Solution: Inevitable Humans in a Lonely Universe. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coppinger, R. and Coppinger, L. (2001). Dogs: A Startling New Understanding of Canine Origin, Behaviour and Evolution. New York: Scribner.Google Scholar
Cornell, J. F. (1984). Analogy and technology in Darwin’s vision of nature. Journal of the History of Biology 17(3), 303–344.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Corsi, P. (2005). Before Darwin: transformist concepts in European natural history. Journal of the History of Biology 38, 67–83.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Coyne, J. A. (2009). Why Evolution is True. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Coyne, J. A. (2012). Science, religion, and society: the problem of evolution in America. Evolution 66(8), 2654–2663.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Coyne, J. and Orr, H. (2004). Speciation. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.Google Scholar
Curry, A. (2009). Creationist beliefs persist in Europe. Science 323, 1159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cyranoski, D., Grimme, S., and Watt, F. (2010). A global survey of the scientifically literate public reveals a Pacific divide on key issues in science. Nature 467, 388–389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Daeschler, E. B., Shubin, N. H., and Jenkins, F. A. (2006). A Devonian tetrapod-like fish and the evolution of the tetrapod body plan. Nature 440, 757–763.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Danielson, D. R. (2009). That the Copernican System demoted humans from the center of the cosmos. In Numbers, R. (Eds.) Galileo Goes to Jail, and Other Myths About Science and Religion. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 50–58.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1859). On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life (1st edn.). London: John Murray.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1868). The Variation of Animals and Plants Under Domestication, Vol. 2. London: John Murray.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1871). The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex (1st edn.). London: John Murray.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1964) [1859]. On the Origin of Species: A Facsimile of the First Edition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. R. and Wallace, A. R. (1858). On the tendency of species to form varieties; and on the perpetuation of varieties and species by natural means of selection. Journal of the Proceedings of the Linnean Society of London. Zoology 3, 45–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwin, F. (1995) [1902]. The Life of Charles Darwin. London: Senate.Google Scholar
Darwin, F. (Ed.) (1909). The Foundations of the Origin of Species: Two Essays Written in 1842 and 1844. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dawkins, R. (2006a) [1986]. The Blind Watchmaker. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. (2006b). The God Delusion. London: Bantam Press.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. (2009). The Greatest Show on Earth: The Evidence for Evolution. London: Bantam Press.Google Scholar
De Robertis, E. M. (2008). Evo-devo: variations on ancestral themes. Cell 132, 185–195.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
De Robertis, E. M. (2009). Spemann’s organizer and the self-regulation of embryonic fields. Mechanisms of Development 126, 925–941.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
De Robertis, E. M. and Sasai, Y. (1996). A common plan for dorsoventral patterning in Bilateria. Nature 380, 37–40.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Deniz, H., Donnelly, L. A., and Yilmaz, I. (2008). Exploring the factors related to acceptance of evolutionary theory among Turkish preservice biology teachers: toward a more informative conceptual ecology for biological evolution. Journal of Research in Science Teaching 45(4), 420–443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. (2006). Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon. New York: Viking.Google Scholar
Depew, D. (2008). Consequence etiology and biological teleology in Aristotle and Darwin. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 39, 379–390.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Depew, D. (2013). Conceptual change and the rhetoric of evolutionary theory: “Force talk” as a case study and challenge for science pedagogy. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, 121–144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Depew, D. J. and Weber, B. H. (1995). Darwinism Evolving: Systems Dynamics and the Genealogy of Natural Selection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Desjardins, E. (2011). Historicity and experimental evolution. Biology & Philosophy 26, 339–364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Desmond, A. and Moore, J. (1994) [1991]. Darwin: The Life of a Tormented Evolutionist. New York: W.W. Norton.Google Scholar
Desmond, A. and Moore, J. (2009). Darwin’s Sacred Cause: How a Hatred of Slavery Shaped Darwin’s Views on Human Evolution. New York: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.Google Scholar
Desmond, D., Moore, J., and Browne, J. (2007). Charles Darwin. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Diamond, J. M. (1997). Guns Germs and Steel: The Fate of Human Societies. New York: W.W. Norton.Google Scholar
Diamond, J. (2002). Evolution, consequences and future of plant and animal domestication. Nature 418, 700–707.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Diedrich, C. R. and Flynn, J. L. (2011). HIV-1/Mycobacterium tuberculosis coinfection immunology: how does HIV-1 exacerbate tuberculosis?Infection and Immunity 79(4), 1407–1417.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dietrich, M. (2010). Microevolution and macroevolution are governed by the same processes. In Ayala, F. J. and Arp, R. (Eds.) Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Biology. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 169–179.Google Scholar
Dietrich, M. (2013). Molecular evolution. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, 239–248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dixon, T., Cantor, G., and Pumfrey, S. (Eds.) (2011). Science and Religion: New Historical Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dobzhansky, T. (1973). Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution. The American Biology Teacher 35(3), 125–129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donoghue, P. C. J. and Benton, M. J. (2007). Rocks and clocks: calibrating the tree of life using fossils and molecules. Trends in Ecology and Evolution 22, 424–431.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Doolittle, W. F. (2000). Uprooting the tree of life. Scientific American 282(2), 90–95.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Duit, R. and Treagust, D. F. (2012). How can conceptual change contribute to theory and practice in science education? In Fraser, B.J., Tobin, K. G., and McRobbie, C. J. (Eds.) Second International Handbook of Science Education. Dordrecht: Springer, 107–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duncan, M. J., Bourrat, P., DeBerardinis, J., and O’ Malley, M. (2013). Small things, big consequences: microbiological perspectives on biology. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, 373–394.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dupré, J. (2003). Darwin’s Legacy: What Evolution Means Today. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dye, C. and Williams, B. (2010). The population dynamics and control of tuberculosis. Science 328, 856–861.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ecklund, E. H. (2010). Science vs. Religion: What Scientists Really Think. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eldredge, N. (2000). The Triumph of Evolution and the Failure of Creationism. New York: W.H. Freeman and Co.Google Scholar
Eldredge, N. and Gould, S. J. (1972). Punctuated equilibria: an alternative to phyletic gradualism. In Schopf, T. J. M. (Ed.) Models in Paleobiology. San Francisco, CA: Freeman, Cooper, 82–115.Google Scholar
Endersby, J. (2008). Imperial Nature: Joseph Hooker and the Practices of Victorian Science. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Endersby, J. (Ed.) (2009). Charles Darwin: On the Origin of Species. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ereshefsky, M. (2010a). Darwin’s solution to the species problem. Synthese 175, 405–425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ereshefsky, M. (2010b). Microbiology and the species problem. Biology & Philosophy 25, 553–568.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Erwin, D. H. (2010). Microevolution and macroevolution are not governed by the same processes. In Ayala, F. J. and Arp, R. (Eds.) Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Biology. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 180–193.Google Scholar
Evans, L. T. (1984). Darwin’s use of the analogy between artificial and natural selection. Journal of the History of Biology 17(1), 113–140.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Evans, M. E. (2001). Cognitive and contextual factors in the emergence of diverse belief systems: creation versus evolution. Cognitive Psychology 42, 217–266.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Evans, M. E. (2008). Conceptual change and evolutionary biology: a developmental analysis. In Vosniadou, S. (Ed.) International Handbook of Research in Conceptual Change. New York and London: Routledge, 263–294.Google Scholar
Fabre, P. H., Rodrigues, A., and Douzery, E. J. P. (2009). Patterns of macroevolution among primates inferred from a supermatrix of mitochondrial and nuclear DNA. Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution 53, 808–825.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Firestein, S. (2012). Ignorance: How it Drives Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fitch, W. M. (2000). Homology: a personal view on some of the problems. Trends in Genetics 16, 227–231.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fong, J. J., Brown, J. M., Fujita, M. K., and Boussau, B. (2012). A phylogenomic approach to vertebrate phylogeny supports a turtle-archosaur affinity and a possible paraphyletic lissamphibia. PLoS ONE 7(11): e48990, .CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forber, P. (2010). Confirmation and explaining how possible. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 41, 32–40.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Forber, P. (2013). Debating the power and scope of adaptation. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, 145–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forber, P. and Griffith, E. (2011). Historical reconstruction: gaining epistemic access to the deep past. Philosophy and Theory in Biology 3, e203, CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frigg, R. and Hartmann, S. (2012). Models in science. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. .
Ganapathy, R. (1980). A major meteorite impact on the Earth 65 million years ago: evidence from the Cretaceous–Tertiary boundary clay. Science 209, 921–923.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gandhi, N. R., Moll, A., Sturm, A. W., et al. (2006). Extensively drug-resistant tuberculosis as a cause of death in patients co-infected with tuberculosis and HIV in a rural area of South Africa. Lancet 368, 1575–1580.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gandhi, N. R., Nunn, P., Dheda, K., et al. (2010). Multidrug-resistant and extensively drug-resistant tuberculosis: a threat to global control of tuberculosis. Lancet 375, 1830–1843.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gass, G. L. and Bolker, J. A. (2003). Modularity. In Hall, B. K. and Olson, W. M. (Eds.) Keywords and Concepts in Evolutionary Developmental Biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 260–267.Google Scholar
Gelman, S. A. (2003). The Essential Child: Origins of Essentialism in Everyday Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gelman, S. A. (2004). Psychological essentialism in children. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 8(9), 404–409.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gelman, S. A. and Bloom, P. (2000). Young children are sensitive to how an object was created when deciding what to name it. Cognition 76, 91–103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gelman, S. A. and Ebeling, K. S. (1998). Shape and representational status in children’s early naming. Cognition 66, 35–47.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gelman, S. A. and Hirschfeld, L. A. (1999). How biological is essentialism? In Medin, D. L. and Atran, S. (Eds.) Folkbiology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 403–446.Google Scholar
Gelman, S. A. and Markman, E. M. (1986). Categories and induction in young children. Cognition 23, 183–209.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gelman, S. A. and Markman, E. M. (1987). Young children’s inductions from natural kinds: the role of categories and appearances. Child Development 58, 1532–1541.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gelman, S. A. and Rhodes, M. (2012). “Two-thousand years of stasis”: how psychological essentialism impedes evolutionary understanding. In Rosengren, K., Brem, S., Evans, E. M., and Sinatra, G. M. (Eds.) Evolution Challenges: Integrating Research and Practice in Teaching and Learning About Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 3–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gelman, S. A. and Wellman, H. M. (1991). Insides and essences: early understandings of the nonobvious. Cognition 38, 213–244.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giere, R. N. (2006). Scientific Perspectivism. Chicago, IL and London: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, S. F. and Burian, R. M. (2003a). Developmental genetics. In Hall, B. K. and Olson, W. M. (Eds.) Keywords and Concepts in Evolutionary Developmental Biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 68–74.Google Scholar
Gilbert, S. F. and Burian, R. M. (2003b). Development, evolution and evolutionary developmental biology. In Hall, B.K. and Olson, W. M. (Eds.) Keywords and Concepts in Evolutionary Developmental Biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 61–68.Google Scholar
Gingerich, O. (1985). Did Copernicus owe a debt to Aristarchus?Journal for the History of Astronomy 16(1), 37–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gingerich, O. (2005). Copernicus Nicholas. In Heilbron, J.L. (Ed.) The Oxford Guide to the History of Physics and Astronomy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 73–74.Google Scholar
Glick, T. F. and Kohn, D. (1996). Charles Darwin on Evolution: The Development of the Theory of Natural Selection. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. (2003). Theory and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Darwinian Populations and Natural Selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, R. F. and Thompson-Schill, S. L. (2009). Developmental “roots” in mature biological knowledge. Psychological Science 20(4), 480–487.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Goldstein, B. R. (2002). Copernicus and the origins of his heliocentric system. Journal for the History of Astronomy 33, 219–235.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gould, S. J. (1977). Ontogeny and Phylogeny. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. (1996). Full House: The Spread of Excellence from Plato to Darwin. New York: Harmony Books.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gould, S. J. (1999). Rocks of Ages: Science and Religion in the Fullness of Life. New York: Ballantine Books.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. (2000) [1989]. Wonderful Life: The Burgess Shale and the Nature of History. London: Vintage.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. (2002). The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Cambridge, MA and London: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. and Lewontin, R. C. (1979). The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society London, Series B, Biological Sciences 205, 581–598.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gould, S. J. and Vrba, E. S. (1982). Exaptation: a missing term in the science of form. Paleobiology 8(1), 4–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Graebsch, A. and Schiermeier, Q. (2006). Anti-evolutionists raise their profile in Europe. Nature 444, 406–407.Google Scholar
Grant, P. R. and Grant, B. R. (2002). Unpredictable evolution in a 30-year study of Darwin’s finches. Science 296, 707–711.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grant, P. R. and Grant, B. R. (2008). How and Why Species Multiply: The Radiation of Darwin’s Finches. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gregory, T. R. (2008). Understanding evolutionary trees. Evolution: Education and Outreach 1, 121–137.Google Scholar
Grehan, J. R. and Schwartz, J. H. (2009). Evolution of the second orangutan: phylogeny and biogeography of hominid origins. Journal of Biogeography 36(10), 1823–1844.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greif, M., Kemler-Nelson, D., Keil, F. C., and Guiterrez, F. (2006). What do children want to know about animals and artifacts? Domain-specific requests for information. Psychological Science 17(6), 455–459.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greiffenhagen, C. and Sherman, W. (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual change in science and children. Science & Education 17, 1–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grene, M. and Depew, D. (2004). The Philosophy of Biology: An Episodic History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gribaldo, S., Poole, A. M., Daubin, V., Forterre, P., and Brochier-Armanet, C., (2010). The origin of eukaryotes and their relationship with the archaea: are we at a phylogenomic impasse?Nature Reviews Microbiology 8, 743e752, CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gribbin, J. (2003). Science: A History. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Griffiths, A. J. F., Wessler, S., Carroll, S. B., and Doebley, J. (2012). Introduction to Genetic Analysis. New York: W.H. Freeman.Google Scholar
Hall, B. K. (2003). Descent with modification: the unity underlying homology and homoplasy as seen through an analysis of development and evolution. Biological Reviews of the Cambridge Philosophical Society 78, 409–433.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hall, B. K. (2012). Parallelism, deep homology and evo-devo. Evolution and Development 14(1), 29–33.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hall, B. K. and Kerney, R. (2012). Levels of biological organization and the origin of novelty. Journal of Experimental Zoology (Mol. Dev. Evol.) 318B, 428–437.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hall, B. K. and Olson, W. M. (Eds.) (2003). Keywords and Concepts in Evolutionary Developmental Biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hameed, S. (2008). Bracing for Islamic Creationism. Science 322, 1637.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hare, B., Brown, M., Williamson, C., and Tomasello, M. (2002).The domestication of social cognition in dogs. Science 298, 1634.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Harrison, T. (2010). Apes among the tangled branches of human origins. Science 327, 532–534.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Heeney, J. L., Dalgleish, A. G., and Weiss, R. A. (2006). Origins of HIV and the evolution of resistance to AIDS. Science 313, 462–466.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Heilbron, J. L. (2010). Galileo. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. (1965). Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. and Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science 15, 135–175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herbert, S. (2005). Charles Darwin, Geologist. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Hilpinen, R. (2011). Artifact. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. .
Hitchcock, C. (2008). Causation. In Psillos, S. and Curd, M. (Eds.) The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science. New York: Routledge, 317–326.Google Scholar
Hodge, J. (2009). The notebook programmes and projects of Darwin’s London years. In Hodge, J. and Radick, G. (Eds.) Cambridge Companion to Darwin (2nd edn.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 44–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodge, J. (2010). Darwin, the Galápagos and his changing thoughts about species origins: 1835–1837. Proceedings of the California Academy of Sciences 61(II, 7), 89–106.Google Scholar
Hodge, J. and Radick, G. (Eds.) (2009a). The Cambridge Companion to Darwin (2nd edn.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodge, J. and Radick, G. (2009b). Darwin’s theories in the intellectual long run. In Hodge, J. and Radick, G. (Eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Darwin (2nd edn.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 277–301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodge, M. J. S. (1977). The structure and strategy of Darwin’s “long argument.”British Journal for the History of Science 10, 237–246.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodge, M. J. S. (1992). Darwin’s argument in the Origin. Philosophy of Science 59(3), 461–464.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodge, M. J. S. and Kohn, D. (1985). The immediate origins of natural selection. In Kohn, D. (Ed.) The Darwinian Heritage. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 185–206.Google Scholar
Hoekstra, H. E. and Coyne, J. A. (2007). The locus of evolution: evo devo and the genetics of adaptation. Evolution 61(5), 995–1016.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hokayem, H. and Boujaoude, S. (2008). College students’ perceptions of the theory of evolution. Journal of Research in Science Teaching 45(4), 395–419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2013). Systematicity: The Nature of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, D. (1992). The particular circumstance model of scientific explanation. In Nitecki, M. and Nitecki, D. (Eds.) History and Evolution. Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 69–80.Google Scholar
Hull, D. L. (2005). Deconstructing Darwin: evolutionary theory in context. Journal of the History of Biology 38(1), 137–152.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hull, D. L. (2009). Darwin’s science and Victorian philosophy of science. In Hodge, J. and Radick, G. (Eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Darwin (2nd edn.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 173–196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. (1993) [1779/1777]. Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion and Natural History of Religion. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Huxley, J. (1942). Evolution: The Modern Synthesis. London: Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Huxley, T. H. (1860). [Review of] The origin of Species. Westminster Review 17 (n.s.), 541–570.Google Scholar
Huxley, T. H. (1863). Evidence as to Man’s Place in Nature. London: Williams and Norgate.Google Scholar
Inagaki, K. and Hatano, G. (2002). Young Children’s Naive Thinking About the Biological World. New York: Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Ingraham, J. (2010). March of the Microbes: Sighting the Unseen. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ingram, E. L. and Nelson, C. E. (2006). Relationship between achievement and students’ acceptance of evolution or creation in an upper-level evolution course. Journal of Research in Science Teaching 43(1), 7–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jablonski, D. (2004a). Extinction: past and present. Nature 427, 589.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jablonski, D. (2004b). Extinction and the spatial dynamics of biodiversity. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 105, 11535–11538.Google Scholar
Jablonski, D. (2007). Scale and hierarchy in macroevolution. Palaeontology 50, 87–109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jablonski, D. (2008). Species selection: theory and data. Annual Review of Ecology, Evolution and Systematics 39, 501–524.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jamieson, A. and Radick, G. (2013). Putting Mendel in his place: how curriculum reform in genetics and counterfactual history of science can work together. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, 577–596.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) (2013a). The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kampourakis, K. (2013b). Teaching about adaptation: why evolutionary history matters. Science & Education 22(2), 173–188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kampourakis, K. and McComas, W. F. (2010). Charles Darwin and evolution: illustrating human aspects of science. Science & Education 19, 637–654.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kampourakis, K. and Nehm, R. (2014). History and philosophy of science and the teaching of evolution: students’ conceptions and explanations. In Matthews, M. R. (Ed.) International Handbook of Research in History, Philosophy and Science Teaching. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Kampourakis, K. and Zogza, V. (2007). Students’ preconceptions about evolution: how accurate is the characterization as “Lamarckian” when considering the history of evolutionary thought?Science & Education 16(3–5), 393–422.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kampourakis, K. and Zogza, V. (2008). Students’ intuitive explanations of the causes of homologies and adaptations. Science & Education 17(1), 27–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kampourakis, K. and Zogza, V. (2009). Preliminary evolutionary explanations: a basic framework for conceptual change and explanatory coherence in evolution. Science & Education 18(10), 1313–1340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kampourakis, K., Pavlidi, V., Papadopoulou, M., and Palaiokrassa, E. (2012a). Children’s teleological intuitions: what kind of explanations do 7–8 year olds give for the features of organisms, artifacts and natural objects?Research in Science Education 42(4), 651–671.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kampourakis, K., Palaiokrassa, E., Papadopoulou, M., Pavlidi, V., and Argyropoulou, M. (2012b). Children’s intuitive teleology: shifting the focus of evolution education research. Evolution Education and Outreach 5(2), 279–291.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keil, F. C. (1989). Concepts, Kinds and Cognitive Development. Cambridge, MA and London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Keil, F. C. (1992). The origins of an autonomous biology. In Gunnar, M. R. and Maratsos, M. (Eds.) Modularity and Constraints in Language and Cognition: Minnesota Symposium on Child Psychology, Vol. 25. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 103–138.Google Scholar
Keil, F. C. (1994). The birth and nurturance concepts by domains: the origins of concepts of living things. In Hirschfeld, L. A. and Gelman, S. (Eds.) Mapping the Mind: Domain Specificity in Cognition and Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 234–254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keil, F. C. (1995). The growth of causal understanding of natural kinds. In Sperber, D., Premack, D., and Premack, A. J. (Eds.) Causal Cognition: A Multi-Disciplinary Debate. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 234–262.Google Scholar
Keil, F. C. and Newman, G. E. (2008). Two tales of conceptual change: what changes and what remains the same. In Vosniadou, S. (Ed.) International Handbook of Research on Conceptual Change. New York and London: Routledge, 83–101.Google Scholar
Keil, F. C. and Wilson, R. A. (Eds.) (2000). Explanation and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Keil, F. C., Greif, M. A., and Kerner, R. S. (2007). A world apart: how concepts of the constructed world are different in representation and in development. In Margolis, E. and Laurence, S. (Eds.) Creations of the Mind: Essays on Artifacts and their Representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 231–247.Google Scholar
Kelemen, D. (1999a). Function, goals and intention: children’s teleological reasoning about objects. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 3(12), 461–468.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kelemen, D. (1999b). The scope of teleological thinking in preschool children. Cognition 70, 241–272.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kelemen, D. (1999c). Why are rocks pointy? Children’s preference for teleological explanations of the natural world. Developmental Psychology 35, 1440–1452.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kelemen, D. (2003). British and American children’s preferences for teleo-functional explanations of the natural world. Cognition 88, 201–221.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kelemen, D. (2004). Are children “Intuitive Theists”? Reasoning about purpose and design in nature. Psychological Science 15(5), 295–301.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kelemen, D. (2012). Teleological minds: how natural intuitions about agency and purpose influence learning about evolution. In Rosengren, K., Brem, S., Evans, E. M., and Sinatra, G. M. (Eds.) Evolution Challenges: Integrating Research and Practice in Teaching and Learning About Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 66–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelemen, D. and Carey, S. (2007). The essence of artifacts: developing the design stance. In Margolis, E. and Laurence, S. (Eds.) Creations of the Mind: Theories of Artifacts and their Representation. New York: Oxford University Press, 212–230.Google Scholar
Kelemen, D. and DiYanni, C. (2005). Intuitions about origins: purpose and intelligent design in children’s reasoning about nature. Journal of Cognition and Development 6(1), 3–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelemen, D. and Rosset, E. (2009). The human function compunction: teleological explanation in adults. Cognition 111, 138–143.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Keller, E. F. (2010). The Mirage of a Space Between Nature and Nurture. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keller, E. F. and Lloyd, E. A. (Eds.) (1992). Keywords in Evolutionary Biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Keynes, R. (2001). Darwin, His Daughter and Human Evolution. New York: Riverhead Books.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1981). Explanatory unification. Philosophy of Science 48(4), 507–531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In Kitcher, P. and Salmon, W. C. (Eds.) Scientific Explanation. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 410–505.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (2007). Living with Darwin. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (2011). Militant modern atheism. Journal of Applied Philosophy 28(1), 1–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knoll, A. H. (2011). The multiple origins of complex multicellularity. Annual Review of Earth and Planetary Sciences 39, 217–239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knoll, A. H. and Hewitt, D. (2011). Complex multicellularity: phylogenetic, functional and geological perspectives. In Sterelny, K. and Calcott, B. (Eds.) The Major Transitions in Evolution Revisited. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 251–270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kohn, D. (Ed.) (1985a). The Darwinian Heritage. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kohn, D. (1985b). Darwin’s principle of divergence as internal dialogue. In Kohn, D. (Ed.) The Darwinian Heritage. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 245–257.Google Scholar
Kohn, D. (2009). Darwin’s keystone: the principle of divergence. In Ruse, M. and Richards, R. J. (Eds.) The Cambridge Companion to the “Origin of Species.”Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 87–108.Google Scholar
Koonin, E. V. (2010a). The two empires and three domains of life in the postgenomic age. Nature Education 3(9), 27.Google Scholar
Koonin, E. V. (2010b). The origin and early evolution of eukaryotes in the light of phylogenomics. Genome Biology 11, 209.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Koonin, E. V. (2011). The Logic of Chance: The Nature and Origin of Biological Evolution. Upper Saddle River, NJ: FT Press.Google Scholar
Krug, A. Z., Jablonski, D., and Valentine, J. W. (2009). Signature of the end-Cretaceous mass extinction in the modern biota. Science 323, 767–771.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kuhn, T. S. (1996) [1962]. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (3rd edn.). Chicago, IL and London: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kyte, F. T., Zhou, Z., and Wasson, J. T. (1980). Siderophile-enriched sediments from the Cretaceous–Tertiary boundary. Nature 288, 651–656.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laland, K. N., Sterelny, K., Odling-Smee, F. J., Hoppitt, W., and Uller, T. (2011). Cause and effect in biology revisited: is Mayr’s proximate-ultimate dichotomy still useful?Science 334, 1512–1516.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Laland, K. N., Odling-Smee, F. J., Hoppitt, W., and Uller, T. (2012). More on how and why: cause and effect in biology revisited. Biology & Philosophy, .
Largent, M. A. (2009). Darwin’s analogy between artificial and natural selection in the Origin of Species. In Ruse, M. and Richards, R. J. (Eds.) The Cambridge Companion to the “Origin of Species.”Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 14–29.Google Scholar
Larson, E. J. (2004). Evolution: The Remarkable History of a Scientific Theory. New York: Modern Library.Google Scholar
Laudan, R. (1987). From Mineralogy to Geology: The Foundation of a Science, 1650–1830. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (1992). Teleology. In Lloyd, E. and Keller, E.F. (Eds.) Keywords in Evolutionary Biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 122–127.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (2005). Darwin’s methodological evolution. Journal of the History of Biology 38(1), 85–99.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lennox, J. G. (2010). The Darwin/Gray correspondence 1857–1869: an intelligent discussion about chance and design. Perspectives on Science 18(4), 456–479.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (2013a). Concepts, context and the advance of science. In Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J.G. (Eds.) Concepts and their Role in Knowledge: Reflections on Objectivist Epistemology. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press, 112–133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (2013b). Conceptual development versus conceptual change: response to Burian. In Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J.G. (Eds.) Concepts and their Role in Knowledge: Reflections on Objectivist Epistemology. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press, 201–211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. G. and Kampourakis, K. (2013). Biological teleology: the need for history. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, 421–454.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. G. and Wilson, B. E. (1994). Natural selection and the struggle for existence. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 25(1), 65–80.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Levine, A. T. (2000). Which way is up? Thomas S. Kuhn’s analogy to conceptual development in childhood. Science & Education 9, 107–122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewens, T. (2004). Organisms and Artifacts: Design in Nature and Elsewhere. Cambridge, MA and London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lewens, T. (2007). Adaptation. In Hull, D. L. and Ruse, M. (Eds.) Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1–21.Google Scholar
Lewontin, R. C. (2001). The Triple Helix: Gene, Organism and Environment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lewontin, R. C., Rose, S., and Kamin, L. J. (1984). Not in Our Genes: Biology, Ideology, and Human Nature. New York: Pantheon Books.Google Scholar
Lienau, E. K., DeSalle, R., Allard, M., et al. (2011). The mega-matrix tree of life: using genome-scale horizontal gene transfer and sequence evolution data as information about the vertical history of life. Cladistics 27, 417–427.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lindberg, D. C. (2007). The Beginnings of Western Science: The European Scientific Tradition in Philosophical, Religious, and Institutional Context, Prehistory to A.D. 1450 (2nd edn.). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the Best Explanation. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lipton, P. (2008). Inference to the best explanation. In Psillos, S. and Curd, M. (Eds.) The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science. New York: Routledge, 193–202.Google Scholar
Livingstone, D. (2003). Putting Science in its Place: Geographies of Scientific Knowledge. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Livingstone, D. N. (2009). That Darwin destroyed natural theology. In Numbers, R. L. (Ed.) Galileo Goes to Jail and Other Myths About Science and Religion. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 152–160.Google Scholar
Lombrozo, T. and Carey, S. (2006). Functional explanation and the function of explanation. Cognition 99, 167–204.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Long, J. (2012). Evolution, missing links and climate change: recent advances in understanding transformational macroevolution. In Poiani, A. (Ed.) Pragmatic Evolution: Applications of Evolutionary Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 23–36.Google Scholar
Long, J. A., Young, G. C., Holland, T., Senden, T. J., and Fitzgerald, E. M. (2006). An exceptional Devonian fish from Australia sheds light on tetrapod origins. Nature 444, 199–202.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Losos, J. B. (2010). A tale of two radiations: similarities and differences in the evolutionary diversification of Darwin’s finches and Greater Antillean Anolis lizards. In Grant, P. R. and Grant, B. R. (Eds.) In Search of the Causes of Evolution: From Field Observations to Mechanisms. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 309–331.Google Scholar
Love, A. C. (2002). Darwin and Cirripedia prior to 1846: exploring the origins of the barnacle research. Journal of the History of Biology 35, 251–289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Love, A. C. (2013). Teaching evolutionary developmental biology: concepts, problems, and controversy. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, 323–342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lucas, J. R. (1979). Wilberforce and Huxley: a legendary encounter. The Historical Journal 22(2), 313–330.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lustig, A. J. (2009). Darwin’s difficulties. In Ruse, M. and Richards, R. J. (Eds.) The Cambridge Companion to the “Origin of Species.”Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 109–128.Google Scholar
Lyell, C. (1832). Principles of Geology, Vol. 2. London: John Murray.Google Scholar
Macdougall, D. (2008). Nature’s Clocks: How Scientists Measure the Age of Almost Everything. San Diego, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Machamer, P., Darden, L., and Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science 67(1), 1–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mallet, J. (2008). Hybridization, ecological races, and the nature of species: empirical evidence for the ease of speciation. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, B Biological Sciences 363, 2971–2986.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mallet, J., Meyer, A., Nosil, P., and Feder, J. L. (2009). Space, sympatry and speciation. Journal of Evolutionary Biology 22, 2332–2341.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Margulis, L. (1998). Symbiotic Planet: A New Look at Evolution. London: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Margulis, L. and Sagan, D. (2002). Acquiring Genomes: A Theory of the Origins of Species. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Margulis, L. and Sagan, D. (2009). Endosymbiotic origin of eukaryotes. In Ruse, M. and Travis, J. (Eds.) Evolution: The First Four Billion Years. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 534–541.Google Scholar
Marshall, C. R. and Ward, P. D. (1996). Sudden and gradual molluscan extinctions in the latest Cretaceous of western European Tethys. Science 274(5291), 1360–1363.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Matthen, M. and Ariew, A. (2002). Two ways of thinking about fitness and natural selection. Journal of Philosophy 99, 55–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maynard Smith, J. and Szathmáry, E. (1995). The Major Transitions in Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Maynard Smith, J. and Szathmáry, E. (2000). The Origins of Life: From the Birth of Life to the Origin of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. (1961). Cause and effect in biology. Science 131, 1501–1506.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayr, E. (1982). The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution and Inheritance. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. (2002). What Evolution Is. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson.Google Scholar
McGhee, G. R. (2011). Convergent Evolution: Limited Forms Most Beautiful. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McLaughlin, P. (2001). What Functions Explain: Functional Explanation and Self-Reproducing Systems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMullin, E. (2008). The virtues of a good theory. In Psillos, S. and Curd, M. (Eds.) The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science. New York: Routledge, 498–508.Google Scholar
McShea, D. W. and Brandon, R. N. (2010). Biology’s First Law: The Tendency for Diversity and Complexity to Increase in Evolutionary Systems. Chicago, IL and London: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, J. D., Scott, E. C. and Okamoto, S. (2006). Public acceptance of evolution. Science 313(5788), 765–766.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, K. (2007). Finding Darwin’s God: A Scientist’s Search for Common Ground Between God and Evolution. New York: Harper Perennial.Google Scholar
Millstein, R. L. (2002). Are random drift and natural selection conceptually distinct?Biology & Philosophy 17 (1), 33–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millstein, R. L. (2005). Selection vs. drift: a response to Brandon’s reply. Biology & Philosophy 20(1), 171–175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millstein, R. L. (2013). Environmental ethics. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, 723–744.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millstein, R. L., Skipper, R. A., and Dietrich, M. R. (2009). (Mis)interpreting mathematical models: drift as a physical process. Philosophy & Theory in Biology 1, e002, .CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mindell, D. P. (2007). The Evolving World: Evolution in Everyday Life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Minelli, A. (2009). Forms of Becoming: The Evolutionary Biology of Development. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Minelli, A. (2010). Evolutionary developmental biology does not offer a significant challenge to the neo-Darwinian paradigm. In Ayala, F. J. and Arp, R. (Eds.) Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Biology. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 213–226.Google Scholar
Minelli, A. (2011). Development, an open-ended segment of life. Biological Theory 6, 4–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Minelli, A. and Fusco, G. (2012). On the evolutionary developmental biology of speciation. Evolutionary Biology 39, 242–254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Minelli, A. and Fusco, G. (2013). Homology. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, 289–322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, D. S. (2002). The Dependent Gene: The Fallacy of “Nature vs. Nurture.”New York: Times Books/Henry Holt and Co.Google Scholar
Moore, D. S. (2013). Current thinking about nature and nurture. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, 629–652.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, J. (2009). That evolution destroyed Charles Darwin’s faith in Christianity – until he reconverted on his deathbed. In, Numbers, R. L. (Ed.) Galileo Goes to Jail and Other Myths About Science and Religion. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 142–151.Google Scholar
Moreira, D. and López-García, P. (2009). Ten reasons to exclude viruses from the tree of life. Nature Reviews Microbiology 7, 306–311.Google ScholarPubMed
Müller, G. B. (2007). Evo-devo: extending the evolutionary synthesis. Nature Reviews Genetics 8, 943–949.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Müller, G. B. (2008). Evo-devo as a discipline. In Minelli, A. and Fusco, G. (Eds.) Evolving Pathways: Key Themes in Evolutionary Developmental Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 3–29.Google Scholar
Müller, G. and Pigliucci, M. (Eds.) (2010). Evolution: The Extended Synthesis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Nersessian, N. J. (2008). Creating Scientific Concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Numbers, R. (2006). The Creationists: From Scientific Creationism to Intelligent Design. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Numbers, R. (2009a). That Creationism is a uniquely American phenomenon. In Numbers, R. (Ed.) Galileo Goes to Jail, and Other Myths About Science and Religion. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 215–223.Google Scholar
Numbers, R. (Ed.) (2009b). Galileo Goes to Jail, and Other Myths About Science and Religion. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Numbers, R. (2011). Clarifying Creationism: five common myths. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 33, 129–139.Google ScholarPubMed
O’Malley, M. A. (2012). When integration fails: prokaryote phylogeny and the tree of life. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, .
Officer, C. B. and Drake, C. L. (1985). Terminal cretaceous environmental events. Science 227(4691), 1161–1167.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ogg, J. G., Ogg, G., and Gradstein, F. M. (2008). The Concise Geologic Time Scale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Okasha, S. (2002). Philosophy of Science: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Okasha, S. (2006). Evolution and the Levels of Selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. (1996). Hume and the argument for biological design. Biology and Philosophy 11, 519–534.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ospovat, D. (1981). The Development of Darwin’s Theory: Natural History, Natural Theology and Natural Selection, 1838–1859. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Owen, R. (1860). [Review of Origin and other works.] Edinburgh Review 111, 487–532.
Pace, N. R. (2009). Mapping the tree of life: progress and prospects. Microbiology and Molecular Biology Reviews 73(4), 565–576.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Paley, W. (2006) [1802]. Natural Theology or Evidence of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity, Collected from the Appearances of Nature. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Papadopulos, A. S. T., Baker, W. J., Crayn, D., et al. (2011). Speciation with gene flow on Lord Howe Island. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 108, 13188–13193.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Peeters, M., Courgnaud, V., Abela, B., et al. (2002). Risk to human health from a plethora of simian immunodeficiency viruses in primate bushmeat. Emerging Infectious Diseases 8, 451–457.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pennock, R. T. (2000). The Tower of Babel: The Evidence Against the New Creationism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Piaget, J. (1960) [1929]. The Child’s Conception of the World. Savage, MD: Littlefield, Adams, Patterson.Google Scholar
Piaget, J. (2013) [1947]. La Représentation du Monde chez l’enfant. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pigliucci, M. (2002). Denying Evolution: Creationism, Scientism, and the Nature of Science. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates.Google Scholar
Pigliucci, M. (2008). Is evolvability evolvable?Nature Reviews Genetics 9, 75–82.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pigliucci, M. (2009). Phenotypic plasticity. In Müller, G. and Pigliucci, M. (Eds.) Evolution: The Extended Synthesis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 355–378.Google Scholar
Pigliucci, M. (2012). Answers for Aristotle: How Science and Philosophy Can Lead Us to a More Meaningful Life. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Pigliucci, M. (2013). The nature of evolutionary biology: at the borderlands between historical and experimental science. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer87–100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pigliucci, M. and Boudry, M. (2011). Why machine-information metaphors are bad for science and science education. Science & Education 20, 453–471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pigliucci, M. and Kaplan, J. (2006). Making Sense of Evolution: The Conceptual Foundations of Evolutionary Biology. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pigliucci, M. and Müller, G. (Eds.) (2010). Evolution: The Extended Synthesis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Poiani, A. (Ed.) (2012). Pragmatic Evolution: Applications of Evolutionary Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Posner, G. J., Strike, K. A., Hewson, P. W., and Gertzog, W. A. (1982). Accommodation of a scientific conception: toward a theory of conceptual change. Science Education 66, 211–227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Potochnik, A. (2013). Biological explanation. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, 49–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prothero, D. R. (2007). Evolution: What the Fossils Say and Why it Matters. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Psillos, S. (2007). Philosophy of Science A–Z. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Ptacek, M. B. and Hankinson, S. J. (2009). The pattern and process of speciation. In Ruse, M. and Travis, J. (Eds.) Evolution: The First Four Billion Years. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 177–207.Google Scholar
Radick, G. (2009). Is the theory of natural selection independent of its history? In Hodge, J. and Radick, G. (Eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Darwin (2nd edn.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 147–172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raff, R. A. (2000). Evo-devo: the evolution of a new discipline. Nature Reviews Genetics 1, 74–79.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Raff, R. A. (2007). Written in stone: fossils, genes, and evo-devo. Nature Reviews Genetics 8, 911–920.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rambaut, A., Posada, D., Crandall, K. A., and Holmes, E. C. (2004). The causes and consequences of HIV evolution. Nature Reviews Genetics 5, 52–61.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ravetz, J. R. (1996). The Copernican revolution. In Olby, R. C., Cantor, G. N., Christie, J. R. R., and Hodge, M. J. S. (Eds.) Companion to the History of Modern Science. London and New York: Routledge, 201–216.Google Scholar
Reeve, H. K. and Sherman, P. W. (1993). Adaptation and the goals of evolutionary research. Quarterly Review of Biology 68(1), 1–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reiss, J. O. (2009). Not by Design: Retiring Darwin’s Watchmaker. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Restif, O. (2009). Evolutionary epidemiology 20 years on: challenges and prospects. Infection, Genetics and Evolution 9(1), 108–123.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Reuter, M. A., Pecora, N. D., Harding, C. V., Canaday, D. H., and McDonald, D. (2010). Mycobacterium tuberculosis promotes HIV trans-infection and suppresses MHC-II antigen processing by dendritic cells. Journal of Virology 84(17), 8549–8560.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Richards, R. A. (2010). The Species Problem: A Philosophical Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richards, R. J. (1992). The Meaning of Evolution: The Morphological Construction and Ideological Reconstruction of Darwin’s Theory. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roger, A. J., Sandblom, O., Doolittle, W. F., and Philippe, H. (1999). An evaluation of elongation – factor-1α as a phylogenetic marker for eukaryotes. Molecular Biology Evolution 16(2), 218–233.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rogers, A. R. (2011). The Evidence for Evolution. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rokas, A. and Carroll, S. B. (2006). Bushes in the Tree of Life. PLoS Biology 4, e352.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rosenberg, A. (2005). Philosophy of Science: A Contemporary Introduction (2nd edn.). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, A. and McShea, D. W. (2008). Philosophy of Biology: A Contemporary Introduction. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Rosengren, K. S., Gelman, S. A., Kalish, C. W., and McCormick, M. (1991). As time goes by: children’s early understanding of growth in animals. Child Development 62(6), 1302–1320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosengren, K. S., Brem, S. K., Evans, E. M., and Sinatra, G. M. (Eds.) (2012). Evolution Challenges: Integrating Research and Practice in Teaching and Learning About Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rughinis, C. (2011). A lucky answer to a fair question: conceptual, methodological, and moral implications of including items on human evolution in scientific literacy surveys. Science Communication 33(4), 499–530.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, M. (1975a). Charles Darwin and artificial selection. Journal of the History of Ideas 36(2), 339–350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, M. (1975b). Darwin’s debt to philosophy: an examination of the influence of the philosophical ideas of John F.W. Herschel and William Whewell on the development of Charles Darwin’s theory of evolution. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 6, 159–181.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ruse, M. (1999). Mystery of Mysteries: Is Evolution a Social Construction?Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ruse, M. (2000). Darwin and the philosophers: epistemological factors in the development and reception of the Origin of Species. In Creath, R. and Maienschein, J. (Eds.) Biology and Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 3–26.Google Scholar
Ruse, M. (2001). Can a Darwinian be a Christian? The Relationship between Science and Religion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ruse, M. (2004). The argument from design: a brief history. In Dembski, W.A. and Ruse, M. (Eds.) Debating Design: From Darwin to DNA. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 13–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, M. (2005).The Evolution/Creation Struggle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, M. (2009). Monad to Man: The Concept of Progress in Evolutionary Biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ruse, M. (2010). Science and Spirituality: Making Room for Faith in the Age of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, M. (2012). Science and the humanities: Stephen Jay Gould’s quest to join the high table. Science & Education 22(9), 2317–2326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, M. (Ed.) (2013). The Cambridge Encyclopedia of Darwin and Evolutionary Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, M. and Richards, R. J. (Eds.) (2009). The Cambridge Companion to the “Origin of Species.”Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ruse, M. and Travis, J. (Eds.) (2009). Evolution: The First Four Billion Years. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. C. (1989). Four decades of scientific explanation. In Kitcher, P. and Salmon, W. C. (Eds.) Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 13. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 3–219.Google Scholar
Sansom, R. S., Gabbott, S. E., and Purnell, M. A. (2010). Non-random decay of chordate characters causes bias in fossil interpretation. Nature 463, 797–800.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sarkar, S. (2007). Doubting Darwin? Creationist Designs on Evolution. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sato, A., Tichy, H., O’Huigin, C., Grant, P. R., Grant, B. R., and Klein, J. (2001). On the origin of Darwin’s finches. Molecular Biology and Evolution 18(3), 299–311.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schweber, S. S. (1980). Darwin and the political economists: divergence of character. Journal of the History of Biology 13(2), 195–289.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Scriven, M. (1959). Explanation and prediction in evolutionary theory. Science 130, 477–482.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Scriven, M. (1969). Explanation in biological sciences. Journal of the History of Biology 2(1), 187–198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sears, K. E., Behringer, R. R., Rasweiler, J. J., and Niswander, L. A. (2006). Development of bat flight: morphologic and molecular evolution of bat wing digits. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 103(17), 6581–6586.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Secord, J. A. (1985). Darwin and the breeders: a social history. In Kohn, D. (Ed.) The Darwinian Heritage. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 519–542.Google Scholar
Secord, J. A. (2000). Victorian Sensation: The Extraordinary Publication, Reception, and Secret Authorship of Vestiges on Natural History of Creation. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Sereno, P. C. (2005). The logical basis of phylogenetic taxonomy. Systematic Biology 54(4), 595–619.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Shapin, S. (1996). The Scientific Revolution. Chicago, IL and London: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shtulman, A. (2006). Qualitative differences between naive and scientific theories of evolution. Cognitive Psychology 52, 170–194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shtulman, A. and Schulz, L. (2008). The relationship between essentialist beliefs and evolutionary reasoning. Cognitive Science 32, 1049–1062.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shubin, N. (2008). Your Inner Fish: The Amazing Discovery of our 375-Million-Year-Old Ancestor. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Shubin, N. H., Daeschler, E. B., and Jenkins, F. A. (2006). The pectoral fin of Tiktaalik roseae and the origin of the tetrapod limb. Nature 440, 764–771.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Shubin, N., Tabin, C., and Carroll, S. (2009). Deep homology and the origins of evolutionary novelty. Nature 457, 818–823.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sinatra, G. M., Southerland, S. A., McConaughy, F., and Demastes, W. (2003). Intentions and beliefs in students’ understanding and acceptance of biological evolution. Journal of Research in Science Teaching 40(5), 510–528.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skipper, R. A. (2006). Stochastic evolutionary dynamics: drift versus draft. Philosophy of Science 73(5), 655–665.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skoglund, P., Götherström, A., and Jakobsson, M. (2011). Estimation of population divergence times using non-overlapping genomic sequences: examples from dogs and wolves. Molecular Biology and Evolution 28(4), 1505–1517.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Smit, J. and Hertogen, J. (1980). An extraterrestrial event at the Cretaceous–Tertiary boundary. Nature 285, 198–200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, M. U. (2010). Current status of research in teaching and learning evolution: II. Pedagogical issues. Science & Education 19(6), 539–571.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. (1993) [1984]. The Nature of Selection: Evolutionary Theory in Philosophical Focus. Chicago, IL and London: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1997). Two outbreaks of lawlessness in recent philosophy of biology. Philosophy of Science 64(4), 467.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. (2003, November 30). Contingency or inevitability? What would happen if the evolutionary tape were replayed? A review of Simon Conway Morris’s life’s solution – inevitable humans in a lonely universe. New York Times.
Sober, E. (2007). What is wrong with Intelligent Design?Quarterly Review of Biology 82(1), 3–8.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sober, E. (2009). Did Darwin write the Origin backwards?Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 106, 10048–10055.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sober, E. (2011). Did Darwin Write the Origin Backwards? Philosophical Essays on Darwin’s Theory. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
Soshnikova, N., Dewaele, R., Janvier, P., Krumlauf, R., and Duboule, D. (2013). Duplications of hox gene clusters and the emergence of vertebrates. Developmental Biology 378, 194–199.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Spencer, N. (2009). Darwin and God. London: SPCK.Google Scholar
Springer, K. (1999). How a naive theory of biology is acquired. In Siegal, M. and Peterson, C. (Eds.) Children’s Understanding of Biology and Health. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 45–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stamos, D. N. (2008). Evolution and the Big Questions. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
Stauffer, R. C. (Ed.) (1975). Charles Darwin’s Natural Selection: Being the Second Part of His Big Species Book Written From 1856 to 1858. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sterelny, K. (2005). Another view of life (essay review). Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 36, 585–593.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, K. and Calcott, B. (Eds.) (2011). The Major Transitions in Evolution Revisited. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sterelny, K. and Griffiths, P. E. (1999). Sex and Death: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Biology. Chicago, IL and London: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Stern, D. L. (2011). Evolution, Development, and the Predictable Genome. Greenwood Village, CO: Roberts and Company Publishers.Google Scholar
Strevens, M. (2009). Depth: An Account of Scientific Explanation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Szathmáry, E. (2005). Life’s solution: inevitable humans in a lonely universe: Simon Conway Morris. Biology & Philosophy 20, 849–857.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tattersall, I. (1998). Becoming Human: Evolution and Human Uniqueness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tattersall, I. (2009). Human origins: out of Africa. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 106(38), 16018–16021.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Taylor, R. S. and Ferrari, M. (Eds.) (2011). Epistemology and Science Education: Understanding the Evolution vs. Intelligent Design Controversy. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Thagard, P. (1978). The best explanation: criteria for theory choice. Journal of Philosophy 75(2), 76–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thagard, P. (1992). Conceptual Revolutions. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Thagard, P. (2012). The Cognitive Science of Science: Explanation, Discovery, and Conceptual Change. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Thagard, P. and Findlay, S. (2010). Getting to Darwin: obstacles to accepting evolution by natural selection. Science & Education 19, 625–636.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thewissen, J. G., Cohn, M. J., Stevens, L. S., Bajpai, S., Heyning, and J., Horton, W. E. (2006). Developmental basis for hind-limb loss in dolphins and origin of the cetacean bodyplan. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 103(22), 8414–8418.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Trut, L. N. (1999). Early canid domestication: the farm-fox experiment. American Scientist 87, 160–169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turner, J. S. (2007). The Tinkerer’s Accomplice: How Design Emerges from Life Itself. Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
UNAIDS (2012). UNAIDS Report on the Global Aids Epidemic 2012. Geneva: UNAIDS.Google Scholar
Van Dijk, E. and Reydon, T. (2010). A conceptual analysis of evolutionary theory for teacher education. Science & Education 19, 655–677.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Wyhe, J. (2007). Mind the gap: did Darwin avoid publishing his theory for many years?Notes and Records of the Royal Society 61, 177–205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Wyhe, J. and Pallen, M. J. (2012). The “Annie Hypothesis”: did the death of his daughter cause Darwin to “give up Christianity”?Centaurus 54(2), 105–123.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Van Wyhe, J. and Rookmaaker, K. (2012). A new theory to explain the receipt of Wallace’s Ternate Essay by Darwin in 1858. Biological Journal of the Linnean Society 105, 249–252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vermeij, G. (2010). The Evolutionary World: How Adaptation Explains Everything from Seashells to Civilization. New York: Thomas Dunne Books, St. Martin’s Press.Google Scholar
Vilà, C., Savolainen, P., Maldonado, J. E., et al. (1997). Multiple and ancient origins of the domestic dog. Science 276, 1687–1689.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Virgin, H. W. and Walker, B. D. (2010). Immunology and the elusive AIDS vaccine. Nature 464, 224–231.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Von Holdt, B. M., Pollinger, J. P., Lohmueller, K. E., et al. (2010). Genome-wide SNP and haplotype analyses reveal a rich history underlying dog domestication. Nature 464, 898–902.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vorzimmer, P. (1969). Darwin, Malthus and the theory of natural selection. Journal of the History of Ideas 30(4), 527–542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vosniadou, S. (Ed.) (2008). International Handbook of Research on Conceptual Change. New York and London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Vosniadou, S. (2012). Reframing the classical approach to conceptual change: preconceptions, misconceptions and synthetic models. In Fraser, B. J., Tobin, K. G., and McRobbie, C. J. (Eds.) Second International Handbook of Science Education. Dordrecht: Springer, 119–130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wagner, G. (2007). The developmental genetics of homology. Nature Reviews Genetics 8, 473–479.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wagner, G. P. and Draghi, J. (2009). Evolution of evolvability. In Müller, G. and Pigliucci, M. (Eds.) Evolution: The Extended Synthesis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 379–399.Google Scholar
Wake, D. B. (1997). Incipient species formation in salamanders of the Ensatina complex. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 94, 7761–7767.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wake, D. B., Wake, M. H., and Specht, C. D. (2011). Homoplasy: from detecting pattern to determining process and mechanism of evolution. Science 331, 1032–1035.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walsh, D. (2006). Evolutionary essentialism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57(2), 425–448.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walsh, D. (2008). Teleology. In Ruse, M. (Ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 113–137.Google Scholar
Walsh, D. M. (2007). The pomp of superfluous causes: the interpretation of evolutionary theory. Philosophy of Science 74, 281–303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walsh, D. M., Lewens, T., and Ariew, A. (2002). The trials of life: natural selection and random drift. Philosophy of Science 69, 452–473.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walters, S. M. and Stow, E. A. (2002). Darwin’s Mentor: John Stevens Henslow, 1796–1861. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Waters, C. K. (2009). The arguments in The Origin of Species. In Hodge, J. and Radick, G. (Eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Darwin (2nd edn.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 120–143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wayne, R. K., Leonard, J. A., and Vilà, C. (2006). Genetic analysis of dog domestication. In Zeder, M. A., Decker-Walters, D., Bradley, D., and Smith, B.D. (Eds.) Documenting Domestication: New Genetic and Archaeological Paradigms. Los Angeles, CA and London: University of California Press279–293.Google Scholar
West-Eberhard, M. J. (1992). Adaptation: current usages. In Keller, E. F. and Lloyd, E. A. (Eds.) Keywords in Evolutionary Biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 13–18.Google Scholar
West-Eberhard, M. J. (2005). Developmental plasticity and the origin of species differences. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 102(1), 6543–6549.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
White, T. D., Asfaw, B., Beyene, Y., et al. (2009). Ardipithecus ramidus and the paleobiology of early hominids. Science 64, 75–86.Google Scholar
Whiteside, A. (2008). HIV/AIDS: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
WHO (2012). Global Tuberculosis Report. Geneva: WHO.Google Scholar
Wilberforce, S. (1860). [Review of] On the Origin of Species, by means of Natural Selection; or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. By Charles Darwin, M. A., F.R.S. London, 1860. Quarterly Review 108, 225–264.
Wilkins, J. S. (2009). Species: A History of the Idea. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Wilkins, J. S. (2011). Are Creationists rational?Synthese 178(2), 207–218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilkins, J. S. (2013). Essentialism in biology. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, 395–420.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, G. C. (1996) [1966]. Adaptation and Natural Selection: A Critique of Some Current Evolutionary Thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, G. C. (2001) [1996]. Plan and Purpose in Nature: The Limits of Darwinian Evolution. London: Phoenix.Google Scholar
Wilmut, I., Schnieke, A. E., McWhir, J., Kind, A. J., and Campbell, K. H. S. (1997). Viable offspring derived from fetal and adult mammalian cells. Nature 385, 810–813.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wilson, D. S. (2002). Darwin’s Cathedral: Evolution, Religion and the Nature of Society. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, E. O. (1975). Sociobiology: The New Synthesis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Winslow, M. W., Staver, J. R., and Scharmann, L. C. (2011). Evolution and personal religious belief: Christian university biology-related majors’ search for reconciliation. Journal of Research in Science Teaching 48(9), 1026–1049.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woese, C. (1998). The universal ancestor. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 95, 6854–6859.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Woese, C. R., Kandler, O., and Wheelis, M. L. (1990). Towards a natural system of organisms: proposal for the domains Archaea, Bacteria, and Eucarya. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 87, 4576–4579.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wood, B. (2005). Human Evolution: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wood, B. (2010). Reconstructing human evolution: achievements, challenges, and opportunities. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 107(2), 8902–8909.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Woodward, J. (2003). Making Things Happen: A Theory of Causal Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Woodward, J. (2008). Explanation. In Psillos, S. and Curd, M. (Eds.) The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science. New York: Routledge, 171–181.Google Scholar
Woodward, J. (2011). Scientific explanation. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. .

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Kostas Kampourakis, Université de Genève
  • Book: Understanding Evolution
  • Online publication: 05 June 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139542357.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Kostas Kampourakis, Université de Genève
  • Book: Understanding Evolution
  • Online publication: 05 June 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139542357.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Kostas Kampourakis, Université de Genève
  • Book: Understanding Evolution
  • Online publication: 05 June 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139542357.011
Available formats
×