Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-vpsfw Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-22T13:25:11.394Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Appendix: Mathematical Background

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 January 2010

John C. Reynolds
Affiliation:
Carnegie Mellon University, Pennsylvania
Get access

Summary

Here we describe a variety of general mathematical concepts and notations that are used in this book. (Concepts that are more advanced, or are particular to programming-language theory, are explained in the main text when they are first used.) Even though most of these concepts may be familiar, readers are advised to scan this material, especially since some of the notations are novel.

In fact, modern mathematics gives the writer a surprising degree of freedom in defining its fundamental concepts, as long as the definitions are consistent and lead to entities with appropriate properties. In this book, I have made the following choices:

  • Pairs are taken to be a primitive notion rather than being defined in terms of sets.

  • Relations are defined as sets of pairs, functions as a special kind of relation, sequences as a special kind of function, and pairs as a special kind of sequence. Since a pair, however, cannot be a set containing itself, we break the inconsistent circle by distinguishing between the pairs 〈x,y) that are sequences and the primitive pairs [x,y] that are members of relations.

  • We define relations (including functions) to be sets of primitive argument-result pairs, rather than calling such a set the “graph” of the relation and defining the relation itself to consist of a domain, a codomain, and a graph. Thus, for example, the function on the integers that increases its argument by one is both a function from integers to integers and a function from integers to reals, and also a partial function from reals to reals. (This view of functions is taken by Gleason [1966, Sections 3–4.1 to 3–4.11]. It is a special case of the view that, in category theory, the morphism sets of a category need not be disjoint.)

  • […]

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1998

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×