Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-vpsfw Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-17T09:16:36.342Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

14 - Retributivism in a World of Scarcity

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 July 2009

Mark D. White
Affiliation:
City University of New York
Get access

Summary

In the philosophy of law, the two primary justifications and/or motivations for criminal punishment are deterrence and retributivism. Deterrence is a consequentialist concept, linking punishment to a reduction in the future crime rate through its effects on criminal behavior. Stated this way, it is easy to see why economists who study the criminal law adopt deterrence as its goal: mainstream economics is essentially consequentialist itself, emphasizing the efficiency of outcomes above all other considerations, and it also has an elaborate (though imperfect) theory of rational choice and behavior. Provided that criminal penalties are interpreted as material disincentives similar to market prices, that the harm from criminal activity can be quantified, and that current models of rational decision making are sufficiently precise and accurate – all controversial claims outside the economic approach to law – economists can, in theory, design penalties optimally to minimize the sum of harm from crime and the costs of punishment itself.

On the other hand, retributivism would seem to stand in opposition to these specialized tools of the economist. Though scholars interpret the basic concept differently, at its core retributivism has a deontological component that justifies the punishment of wrongdoers as a matter of justice or right, based on desert and guilt. Retributivism is usually divided into two varieties: negative, or weak, retributivism sees wrongdoing as a necessary but not sufficient condition for punishment, whereas positive, or strong, retributivism holds wrongdoing to be both necessary and sufficient for punishment.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Becker, Gary S., 1968, “Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach,” Journal of Political Economy, 76, pp. 169–217CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bentham, Jeremy, 1781/1988, The Principles of Morals and Legislation, Buffalo: Prometheus Books; Cesare Beccaria, 1764/1986Google Scholar
Acton, H. B., ed., 1969, The Philosophy of Punishment: A Collection of Papers, New York: St. Martin's Press
Duff, R. A., 2001, Punishment, Communication, and Community, Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Ten, C. L., 1987, Crime, Guilt, and Punishment, Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Braithwaite, John and Pettit, Philip, 1990, Not Just Deserts: A Republican Theory of Criminal Justice, Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Duff, R. A., 2004, “Legal Punishment,” in the Stanford Encyclopedia of PhilosophyGoogle Scholar
White, Mark D., “Criminal Justice: Punishment and Retributivism” in O'Hara, P. A., ed., 2008, International Encyclopedia of Public Policy – Governance in a Global Age, vol. 4, GPERU: PerthGoogle Scholar
Cahill, Michael T., 2007, “Real Retributivism,” Washington University Law Review, 85, pp. 815–870, 822Google Scholar
Posner, Richard A., 1980, “Retribution and Related Concepts of Punishment,” Journal of Legal Studies, 9, p. 92Google Scholar
Mercuro, Nicholas and Medema, Steven G., 2006, Economics and the Law: From Posner to Post-modernism and Beyond, 2nd ed., Princeton: Princeton University Press, p. 94)Google Scholar
Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven, 2002, Fairness versus Welfare, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Coleman, Jules, 2003, “The Grounds of Welfare,” Yale Law Journal, 112, pp. 1511–1543CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ferzan, Kimberly, 2004, “Some Sound and Fury from Kaplow and Shavell,” Law and Philosophy, 23, pp. 73–102Google Scholar
White, Mark D., 2004, “Preaching to the Choir: A Response to Kaplow and Shavell's Fairness versus Welfare,” Review of Political Economy, 16, pp. 507–515CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parisi, Francesco and Smith, Vernon L., eds., The Law and Economics of Irrational Behavior, Stanford: Stanford University Press, pp. 339–357)
Wittman, Donald, 1974, “Punishment as Retribution,” Theory and Decision, 4, pp. 209–237CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miceli, Thomas J., 1990, “Optimal Prosecution of Defendants Whose Guilt Is Uncertain,” Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 6, pp. 189–201Google Scholar
Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven, 1994, “Accuracy in the Determination of Liability,” Journal of Law and Economics, 37, pp. 1–15CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Avio, Kenneth L., 1993, “Economic, Retributive, and Contractarian Conceptions of Punishment,” Law and Philosophy, 12, pp. 249–286CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, H. L. A., 1968, Punishment and Responsibility: Essays in the Philosophy of Law, Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. D., 1930, The Right and the Good, Indianapolis: HackettGoogle Scholar
Mabbott, J. D., 1939, “Punishment,” Mind, 48, pp. 152–167CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John, 1955, “Two Concepts of Rules,” Philosophical Review, 64, pp. 3–32CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benn, S. I., 1958, “An Approach to the Problems of Punishment,” Philosophy, 33, pp. 325–341CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrd, B. Sharon, 1989, “Kant's Theory of Punishment: Deterrence in Its Threat, Retribution in Its Execution,” Law and Philosophy, 8, pp. 151–200CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheid, Don E., 1983, “Kant's Retributivism,” Ethics, 93, pp. 262–282CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphy, Jeffrie G., 1987, “Does Kant Have a Theory of Punishment?Columbia Law Review, 87, pp. 509–532CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hill, Thomas E., 1999, “Kant on Wrongdoing, Desert, and Punishment,” Law and Philosophy, 18, pp. 407–441Google Scholar
White, Mark D., 2004, “A Kantian Critique of Neoclassical Law and Economics,” Review of Political Economy, 18, pp. 235–252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, Alan H., 1979, “The Paradox of Punishment,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 9, pp. 42–58Google Scholar
Card, Claudia, 1975, “Retributive Penal Liability,” American Philosophical Quarterly MonographsGoogle Scholar
Hirsch, Andrew, 1976, Doing Justice: The Choice of Punishments, New York: Hill and WangGoogle Scholar
Davis, Michael, 1983, “How to Make the Punishment Fit the Crime,” Ethics, 93, pp. 726–52CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wertheimer, Alan, 1975, “Should Punishment Fit the Crime?,” Social Theory and Practice, 3, pp. 403–423CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bedau, Hugo Adam, 1978, “Retribution and the Theory of Punishment,” Journal of Philosophy, 75, pp. 601–620CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parker, Jeffrey S., 1993, “The Economics of Mens Rea,” Virginia Law Review, 79, pp. 754–756CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, David and Sjostrom, William, 1993, “Hanged for a Sheep: The Economics of Marginal Deterrence,” Journal of Legal Studies, 12, pp. 345–366CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, Herbert, 1968, “Persons and Punishment,” reprinted in 1976, On Guilt and Innocence, Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 31–58Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert, 1981, Philosophical Explanations, Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, pp. 363–365Google Scholar
Fletcher, George, 1978, Rethinking Criminal Law, Boston: Little, Brown, pp. 461–463Google Scholar
Becker, Lawrence C., 1974, “Criminal Attempts and the Theory of the Law of Crimes,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 3, pp. 262–294Google Scholar
Shavell, Steven, 1990, “Deterrence and the Punishment of Attempts,” Journal of Legal Studies, 19, pp. 435–466CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, David D., 1991, “Impossibility, Subjective Probability, and Punishment for Attempts,” Journal of Legal Studies, 20, pp. 179–186CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hylton, Keith N., 2005, “The Theory of Penalties and the Economics of Criminal Law,” Review of Law and Economics, 1, pp. 175–201CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Posner, Richard A. (1985, “An Economic Theory of the Criminal Law,” Columbia Law Review, 85, pp. 1193–1231)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Husak, Douglas N., 1992, “Why Punish the Deserving?,” Noûs, 26, p. 451CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Avio, Kenneth L., 1990, “Retribution, Wealth Maximization, and Capital Punishment: A Law and Economics Approach,” Stetson Law Review, 19, p. 386Google Scholar
Moore, Michael, 1997, Placing Blame: A General Theory of the Criminal Law, Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Moore, Michael (1993, “Justifying Retributivism,” Israel Law Review, 27, pp. 15–49)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dolinko, David, 1997, “Retributivism, Consequentialism, and the Intrinsic Goodness of Punishment,” Law and Philosophy 16, pp. 507–528Google Scholar
Markel, Dan, 2001, “Are Shaming Punishments Beautifully Retributive? Retributivism and the Implications for Alternative Sanctions,” Vanderbilt Law Review, 54, pp. 2157–2242Google Scholar
Robinson, Paul H. and Cahill, Michael T., 2006, Law without Justice: Why Criminal Law Doesn't Give People What They Deserve, Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Kipnis, Kenneth, 1976, “Criminal Justice and the Negotiated Plea,” Ethics, 86, pp. 93–106CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alschuler, Albert W.: 1968, “The Prosecutor's Role in Plea Bargaining,” University of Chicago Law Review, 36, pp. 50–112CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kipnis, Kenneth, 1979, “Plea Bargaining: A Critic's Rejoinder,” Law and Society Review, 13, p. 555, n. 1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christopher, Russell L., 2003, “The Prosecutor's Dilemma: Bargains and Punishments,” Fordham Law Review, 72, pp. 93–168Google Scholar
Reiman, Jeffrey and Haag, Ernest, 1990, “On the Common Saying that It Is Better that Ten Guilty Persons Escape than that One Innocent Suffer: Pro and Con,” in Paul, Ellen Frankel et al., eds., Crime, Culpability, and Remedy, Oxford and Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, pp. 226–248Google Scholar
Alexander, Larry, 1983, “Retributivism and the Inadvertent Punishment of the Innocent,” Law and Philosophy, 2, pp. 233–246CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coleman, Jules L., 1985, “Crimes, Kickers, and Transaction Structures,” in Pennock, J. Roland and Chapman, John W., eds., Criminal Justice: NOMOS XXVII, New York: New York University Press, pp. 313–328Google Scholar
White, Mark D., 2005, “A Social Economics of Crime (Based on Kantian Ethics),” in Oppenheimer, Margaret and Mercuro, Nicholas, eds., Law and Economics: Alternative Economic Approaches to Legal and Regulatory Issues, Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe, pp. 351–373Google Scholar
Robinson, Paul H., 2006, “How Psychology Is Changing the Punishment Theory Debate,” in Freeman, Michael, ed., Law and Psychology (Current Legal Issues Vol. 9), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 94–104CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×