Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-pfhbr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T11:27:02.429Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

14 - Unity of substance

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 September 2009

Get access

Summary

We are accustomed to sum up the Christian doctrine of the Trinity in the Latin formula derived from Tertullian, three Persons in one substance. Greek theologians confess three hypostases but one ousia. The last two words, whatever their precise meaning, are clearly authorized by the Nicene Creed – both the original version of 325 and the customary version attributed to the Council of 381 – which states that the Son is homoousios with the Father; the word can be rendered in Latin form either as ‘consubstantial’ or as ‘coessential’. But problems arise from the fact that the Latin word essentia, which is the exact equivalent of ousia, fell out of use. Latin theologians therefore translated ousia by substantia which is etymologically equivalent to the Greek ‘hypostasis’. The Latins thus used substantia to express the divine unity; the Greeks used the corresponding word to confess three hypostases: Father, Son and Spirit. Consequently the Greeks were liable to suppose that the Latin una substantia (like ‘one hypostasis’) denies the Trinity. The Latins, conversely, could suspect the Greeks of preaching ‘three substances’, three distinct or different Godheads. Nor was this merely a difference of technical terms; both sides were to some extent influenced by their own terminology, so that at important moments the Latins were inclined to put their main emphasis on divine unity, the Greeks on a clearly articulated Trinity.

The word homoousios has been much discussed; but the traditional explanations are unreliable. We begin by considering its constituent parts. First, the prefix homo- suggests unity or togetherness; but its sense is not perfectly constant.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1994

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×