We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
This chapter investigates Grotius’s broader intellectual involvement with the doctrine of predestination. Grotius deliberately renounced the religious importance of predestination as he called for religious concord in a time of fierce inter-confessional strife in the United Provinces - an endeavour that almost cost him his life. Considering his abhorrence for religious dogmas about divine predestination and human free will, two of his writings, Meletius and Ordinum pietas, display a remarkable restraint on Grotius’s part on the matter. Social and political order was not to be found in unrelenting dogmatic questions of certainty about what Grotius’s viewed as theologically non-essential religious principles. Rather it required a commitment to religious toleration. This chapter argues that Grotius’s involvement in the Dutch predestination debates reveals important philosophical connections between his religious and political ideas and allows for further explication of two central aspects of Grotius’s political theory: natural sociability and the impious hypothesis. From a careful contextualisation of predestination in Grotius’s religious oeuvre, emerges an account of socialisation independent of the predestination question, and establishes the infamous ‘etiamsi daremus’ statement as an obligation device that served his pursuit for religious and political accord.
Vattel stands among the principal jurists of modern international relations. Yet the balance of power – a policy at the heart of the theory and practise of international relations, and which Edmund Burke, for example, declared central to the ‘common law of Europe’1 – hardly figures at all in Vattel’s magnum opus. The question thus arises: why does it play a relatively insignificant role in his writings, and what role exactly does he think it plays? There is no doubt that he recognises it as an important element of policy in European relations. While the condition of a balance of power ideally maintains peace and harmony among states, it also carries within itself a powerful justification for preventive war. Balance of power is defined by the principle of collective security that prevents any states from attaining a preponderance of power and constituting a danger to the rest. Yet while this dynamic may ultimately limit the occurrence of war, as just war theory more generally seeks to do,2 any attempt to wage war to preserve the balance of power is predicated on the institutionalisation of war as an instrument of policy. Vattel is thus sceptical of its efficacy as a reliable mechanism for the limitation of war. Whoever ‘entertains a true idea of war … and considers its terrible effects’, Vattel writes, would surely agree that it should not be undertaken unless for the best of reasons (LN, III-iii-24).
Recommend this
Email your librarian or administrator to recommend adding this to your organisation's collection.