Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-x5gtn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-07T09:43:18.467Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Unpacking constitutional literacy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 October 2023

Maartje De Visser*
Affiliation:
Yong Pung How School of Law, Singapore Management University, 55 Armenian St, Singapore 197743
Brian Christopher Jones
Affiliation:
School of Law and Social Justice, University of Liverpool, Chatham Street, Liverpool, L69 7ZR, United Kingdom
*
Corresponding author: Maartje De Visser; Email: mdevisser@smu.edu.sg
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The contemporary crisis in relation to constitutional literacy relates not to the lack of knowledge that citizens possess about fundamental constitutional texts, but to the considerable lack of development in relation to what constitutional literacy itself entails. This article accordingly unpacks the notion of constitutional literacy: its importance, its characteristics, and its variable nature. Using a comparative lens, the article invites reflection on the role we expect citizens to play in our democracies, and especially the associated knowledge and skills required for successful state performance. We suggest that constitutional literacy is exceptionally multifaceted and fluid in nature, which serves to make its conceptualization and measurement challenging endeavours, and certainly more so than the easy invocation of this notion may assume at first blush. In this regard, engaging with the constitutional text, while an integral component of constitutional literacy, is ultimately only one part of the puzzle.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

I. Introduction

Touting sufficient literacy of civic and political norms among members of the public as essential to a well-functioning state or as a solution to societal ills is a venerable democratic tradition.Footnote 1 At the same time, the idea of such literacy has always been challenging because it asks us to confront a difficult normative question: how much should the people know about public affairs? To be sure, contemporary citizens face vastly different knowledge requirements compared with previous generations. Ancient Greek societies operating on more direct methods of democracy undoubtedly valued public knowledge and participation in government, as (male) citizens performed a range of important roles within the state. While the transition to representative democracy meant a smaller number of people would be performing governmental roles, the idea that the electorate should be engaged with and knowledgeable about public affairs has remained. After all, citizens still possess the power to vote leaders into and out of office, and should accordingly be able to evaluate their performance and what is on offer from potential replacements.

The late mid- to late twentieth and early twenty first centuries brought about a different type of democracy focused around further constraining public power – sometimes termed ‘monitory democracy’Footnote 2 – often through written constitutions and bills of rights. The number of written constitutions expanded dramatically after World War II, and nowadays it is commonplace for countries to possess such documents.Footnote 3 As the dawn of constitutional democracy arrived, constitutions and constitutional norms have been added to the list of topics with which citizens should be familiar.Footnote 4 This is true even in places without a written constitution in place – such as the United Kingdom – as the relevance of constitutional literacy has come into focus in recent years.Footnote 5 For example, in 2020 the UK government set up an independent review to assess the functioning of the Human Rights Act (HRA) 1998 with a view to identifying possible areas for improvement.Footnote 6 Extensive consultations were held to solicit the opinion of parliamentarians, academics, legal experts, public officials, individuals and private organizations. Among others, the interveners were united in calling attention to the need to increase the public’s awareness of the rights protected by the UK Constitution as well as its other features. The report’s very first recommendation stresses that the government should give ‘serious consideration … to developing an effective programme of civic and constitutional education’.Footnote 7 Doing so was thought to be valuable in ensuring public ownership of rights contained in the HRA, as well as in countering misperceptions regarding the functioning of the human rights framework. More generally, the idea of enhancing civic or political knowledge has been an ongoing focus for many governments, NGOs, institutions, societies and individuals around the world.Footnote 8

That individuals ought to have at least a basic understanding of the constitution or texts with an equivalent status can be said to be a fundamental attribute of ‘good citizenship’. As noted above, it may also be intuitively linked to ideas of well-functioning democratic systems. Yet the HRA Review recommendation dovetails with a common view of the situation regarding constitutional literacy around the globe – that it is either ‘in crisis’Footnote 9 or in need of serious improvement, to ensure that citizens are aware of and able to answer certain questions about their nation’s most fundamental legal textFootnote 10 or able to champion the principles and rules enshrined therein in the service of constitutional democracy.Footnote 11 One American philosopher has called the public’s knowledge of government ‘abysmal’.Footnote 12 However, for a state of affairs that has been described as being at crisis levels, there is surprisingly little theoretical research devoted to the notion of constitutional literacy. Much of the literature that is available is focused on the United States,Footnote 13 although there are some exceptions.Footnote 14 But even topics related to constitutional literacy, such as civic education, are not as well developed as social scientists would arguably have expected in this day and age.Footnote 15

Against this backdrop, the purpose of this article is to critically interrogate the notion of constitutional literacy. Our view is that the most pervasive challenge in relation to such literacy lies in a lack of understanding of the notion itself, more than with concerns about citizens’ lack of knowledge of fundamental constitutional texts. Put differently, there is a need to arrive at a better appreciation of the meaning, importance and characteristics of constitutional literacy in order to enhance the role that it can and should play within our democracies. In this regard, we suggest that constitutional literacy is exceptionally multifaceted and goes beyond the constitutional text to also encompass constitutional norms, unwritten behaviours and actions, and different types of knowledge that undergird or supplement the constitutional text, such as constitutional history. Decisions about whether to champion constitutional literacy, and if so, how, may accordingly need to be fashioned with due regard for prevailing political conditions or the ideological preferences of leading state actors. As these will vary across jurisdictions, so too is the approach to constitutional literacy likely to be context-specific.

This article proceeds as follows. Part II explores the importance of constitutional literacy, recognizing that some justifications in favour of this notion overlap with those supporting civic and political knowledge, but also that other arguments go beyond these. Part III offers an overview of the conceptual contours of constitutional literacy, breaking down this notion into the most common and accepted forms it takes – civic, legal and political knowledge. We advocate a broader understanding that also includes constitutional history and, crucially, the behaviour of constitutional actors. In Part IV, we describe the fluid nature of constitutional literacy, demonstrating how this gives it a heavily contextualized character across audiences, space and time. Part V discusses the challenges attendant on measuring constitutional literacy because of this characteristic, while Part VI concludes the article.

II. The importance of constitutional literacy

Overlap in importance with civic and political knowledge

Civic engagement has been described as essential to democracy’s survival,Footnote 16 and political knowledge is said to be ‘one of the most valuable resources that any citizen in a democracy can possess’.Footnote 17 There seems to be no getting around the fact that all theories of democracy – whether direct, electoral or monitory – rely on an informed public, and that adequate civic and political knowledge forms an integral part of that. Among other outcomes, such knowledge has been said to promote democratic ideals, confidence in key governmental institutions and a willingness to participate in public life.Footnote 18 The idea of constitutional literacy similarly connects to arguments centred around the importance of a citizenry that has the requisite understanding and skills to support the functioning and success of constitutional democracy. This is especially true regarding those constitutional rules and values that shape democratic design as well as performance.Footnote 19 Throughout democracy’s sustained development, the public’s capacity for knowledge has been questionedFootnote 20 and anti-democrats have often used a lack of civic or political knowledge amongst the general public to tout alternative forms of government.Footnote 21 Widespread constitutional illiteracy could be used similarly, with some advocating that those with a lack of particular constitutional knowledge should not be able to participate in various civic activities, such as voting.Footnote 22 Conversely, if the people are able to correctly identify and critically evaluate anti-constitutional claims, they could stand up for democratic ideals and institutions and attenuate the ills to which such claims might otherwise give rise.

Another prominent justification for increased civic, political and constitutional knowledge is found in popular sovereignty and social contract ideas. It is modern orthodoxy to understand the constitution as emanating from the people, who are the ultimate source of legitimate power and who have through that document conferred a certain authority to act upon the different branches of government.Footnote 23 If there is widespread ignorance about what the constitution incorporates, then the claim to democratic legitimacy on the part of the government is correspondingly weakened. When such conditions prevail, the supposed agreement between the governed and the governors could, in a sense, be likened to a one-sided contract as the former do not know what they have actually agreed to. One might object that ‘We the People’ and social contract theory rest on legal fictions, and that the law generally is replete with such fictions.Footnote 24 While that may be true, given their foundational importance, it does not seem quite defensible to accept popular sovereignty or the social contract as fictions pure and simple. In fact, there are strands within the constitutional discourse that treat both as ideals that systems ought to strive to realize, with analysis focused on suitable means to give practical effect to the role of the people in the constitutional order.Footnote 25 Improving constitutional literacy would be a valuable means to this end. It could further help to address the so-called ‘dead hand’ problem,Footnote 26 which queries why democratic majorities today ought to observe the rules and principles agreed on by constitutional framers. Tacit consent – that is to say, the absence of popularly led efforts for constitutional reform or other ways of communicating disquiet with the status quo – has been pointed to as one possible answer. Some scholars have suggested that this line of thinking is too minimal and artificial; in contrast, if there would be widespread awareness of the constitution’s content, people’s ‘so-called tacit consent would look much more like informed [and hence real] consent’.Footnote 27

While the rationale and implications for constitutional literacy overlap with those relating to civic and political knowledge in some respects, it also goes beyond these in other ways.

The importance of constitutional literacy beyond civic and political knowledge

In an age of constitutional democracy centred around constitutional supremacy, the idea that citizens should be familiar with the supreme law of the land may be inherently valuable. Leading constitutional theorists have advanced this perspective. For instance, Ackerman notes that, ‘To discover the Constitution is to discover an important part of oneself.’Footnote 28 Other scholars have acknowledged the connection these documents may have to a people’s collective identity.Footnote 29 Improving constitutional knowledge could help actualize the common assumption (or fiction) that one is expected to know the law as a fundamental prerequisite for compliance. In fact, some constitutions even explicitly require members of the polity to abide by and respect the constitution. The 1991 Columbian Constitution states that, ‘It is the duty of citizens and of aliens in Colombia to obey the Constitution and the laws, and to respect and obey the authorities.’Footnote 30 Similar provisions can be found in the constitutions of the Dominican Republic,Footnote 31 Bhutan,Footnote 32 Ethiopia,Footnote 33 Mozambique,Footnote 34 PeruFootnote 35 and Venezuela,Footnote 36 among others.Footnote 37 In some sense, these provisions ‘constitutionalize’ the idea of constitutional literacy, asking citizens to respect or obey the constitution and its contents, which presupposes at least a basic familiarity with this document. Yet, given that empirical evidence shows constitutions have progressively expanded in length and scope, with notably bills of rights becoming longer since the adoption of early modern constitutional texts,Footnote 38 these requirements may be more difficult to meet.

In the specific case of constitutions, moreover, Stephanopoulos and Versteeg have found that ‘making people more knowledgeable (or at least more inclined to say they are knowledgeable) about their constitution’ has a positive effect on the esteem in which this text is held.Footnote 39 It could be theorized that such an attitude of respect may in turn foster what Sternberger terms ‘constitutional patriotism’.Footnote 40 This concept, which Habermas and Müller have developed into a general theory,Footnote 41 denotes a form of civic allegiance based on the basic norms and values (as well as, more indirectly, the procedures) found in liberal democratic constitutions rather than a form of belonging centred on potentially divisive attributes such as ethnicity, religion or culture. On this approach, constitutional literacy would be instrumental in cultivating the shared political morality that must pervade for constitutional patriotism to succeed. This would hold especially in pluralist societies, which are proliferating around the world. Similarly, there is a growing interest among policy-makers and academics in providing people with greater opportunities for direct participation in governance, including in constitutional reform projects,Footnote 42 for legitimacy-enhancing reasons and to ‘inculcate democratic skills, habits and values’.Footnote 43 If we want those outcomes to be realized, citizens should know enough about the relevant constitutional framework in which such participation is to be realized, and they should possess a basic understanding of the substance of the issues on which their views are solicited. Such knowledge could also positively impact expressions of voter preferences during elections and referendums in the sense that there would be fewer manifestations of unconstitutional or even anti-constitutional proclivities.

The rapid post-World War II growth in constitutional and human rights discourse is another feature that distinguishes constitutional literacy from civic and political knowledge. Citizens are now expected to speak and understand developments in constitutional (e.g. whether certain action was ‘constitutional’ or ‘unconstitutional’)Footnote 44 and human rights terms (e.g. whether a certain action was a ‘violation’ or not of particular rights).Footnote 45 This implies that citizens should be familiar with the operation and structure of the state as well as with the rights articulated within the constitution. Being aware of what rights are enumerated in a particular fundament text is important. This is true even if the rights listed in constitutions and bills of rights appear more aspirational than practically feasible.Footnote 46 When it comes to the vindication of constitutional rights, citizens will need to know why, when and how to do this. They will also need to know that rights are often limited, can be curtailed for various reasons and may need to be balanced in view of respect for other rights. Such an awareness regarding the operation of rights often goes beyond the textual articulation of rights present in written constitutions and bills of rights.

New understandings of what is ‘constitutional’ or ‘unconstitutional’ link to the meaningful exercise of public accountability and how citizens may ‘call out’ behaviour that pushes or exceeds constitutional boundaries. Responding to state actions that affect one’s interests requires knowledge of the operation of the institutions capable of offering redress – from litigation in the courts to complaints to bodies like the Ombudsman or human rights commission to using political avenues to make one’s voice heard. As Theodore Roosevelt starkly put it, there should be an expectation incumbent on citizens ‘to denounce, and, so far as may be, to punish crimes against the public on the part of politicians or officials’.Footnote 47 That is, every member of the public can be conceived as a legal-political watchman who must keep the behaviour of officeholders under review. For such popular constitutional guardianship to work a general consensus must be found on the constitutional parameters of governmental power so that transgressions can be properly identified and called out. This argument has acquired strength as realization has dawned that the conventional institutionalized checks on the political branches – notably judicial review – may not work as well as intended in conditions of democratic and/or constitutional erosionFootnote 48 and that the involvement of ‘small-d’ democrats will be necessary to help sustain constitutional democracies.Footnote 49

III. Mapping constitutional literacy

As the above highlights, there are good reasons to be concerned with constitutional literacy among the general public. But what exactly does this notion comprise? The adjective ‘constitutional’ naturally evokes an engagement with the big-C text as being at the heart of such literacy, and the prime object of literacy-boosting endeavours. This also suggests a strong legal dimension to the notion of literacy, given the typical characterization of the constitution as the supreme law of the land. This aligns with how Dreisbach defines it: ‘knowledge of the Constitution sufficient to invoke it properly’.Footnote 50 Fombad offers a wider definition, stating that literacy ‘entails the creation of social awareness and knowledge of the constitution, its values and objectives as well as the rights and duties it confers on the citizen to enable them participate fully in a sustained manner in public affairs’.Footnote 51 However, his version of literacy remains focused on ‘legal and constitutional frameworks’. We suggest, in contrast, that constitutional literacy goes beyond requiring an adequate understanding of a definitive legal-constitutional text. Our conceptualization conceives of such literacy as also intersecting with elements of political and civic knowledge, in line with some of the justifications canvassed earlier, as well as with an awareness of the actions and behaviours of constitutional actors and constitutional history. These different constituent elements of constitutional literacy are elaborated in the sections that follow.

Legal knowledge

Legal knowledge certainly comes into play when considering constitutional literacy, and there will be a natural inclination to focus on the written constitution in this regard. After all, it is common for this text to be considered the highest form of law within the state, while the constitution may even explicitly declare that it possesses this exalted status.Footnote 52 As we know, constitutions devise key state institutions, the structures by which those institutions are governed, who may participate in those institutions and many other elements. Many constitutional texts, moreover, cover the rights bestowed on individuals, including what these are and how they are protected (via the courts or through other administrative procedures). As Levinson points out, it is often these aspects of constitutions that citizens show the most interest in, as opposed to state structures.Footnote 53 This is understandable: aside from self-referential motivations that will be particularly strong for provisions directly addressed to and benefiting them, the length of contemporary constitutions arguably prevents citizens from becoming acquainted with every aspect of these documents.Footnote 54

There are, however, three qualifications that should be borne in mind when thinking about the legal dimension of constitutional literacy as encapsulated in the written constitution. We should first remember that constitutions do not, and cannot, exhaustively regulate all facets of the constitutional order. They may be silent regarding aspects that are of keen practical relevance and interest to individuals, such as elections or the rules as to citizenship. The corollary is that other legal categories emerge as also relevant to imbuing the notion of constitutional literacy with meaning. Court decisions interpret the meaning of constitutions and related principles, but they exist outside the formal text,Footnote 55 and statutes similarly flesh out, operationalize or otherwise complement the large-C document. That document, then, is only one facet of the legal knowledge required as a constitutive element of constitutional literacy.Footnote 56 Moreover, we should not lose sight of the fact that some aspects of written constitutions do not necessarily or entirely have the force of law. Preambles, for example, are part of a written constitution, but usually cannot be relied on in court.Footnote 57 Also, conventions that are implicated in the functioning of constitutional rules may always not formally be acknowledged as ‘legal’ in nature, but instead be seen as belonging to the political realm.Footnote 58 Finally, larger constitutional principles such as separation of powers or the rule of law may not be mentioned explicitly in a written document, even though they undergird the provisions of that document and indeed the constitutional order more generally. In sum, the constitution as legal text is an obvious point of reference in thinking about constitutional literacy, but it should not be seen as exhaustive of that notion.

Political knowledge

Political knowledge should be viewed as another constitutive element of constitutional literacy. Leaving aside the fact that such knowledge can speak to the same pro-democratic aims with which constitutional literacy is concerned, an appreciation of the basic institutions and procedures of government is complementary to knowledge about the written constitution as law. One could even say that this kind of political understanding is necessary for citizens to appreciate how constitutions work – or sometimes fail to work – in practice, and how contentious socio-political questions with a constitutional dimension are deliberated and resolved, including those that are not explicitly recognized in the constitutional text.

The most widely accepted definition of political knowledge comes from Delli Carpini and Keeter, who take it as referring to ‘factual information stored in long-term memory’.Footnote 59 Part of such information derives from the constitution, which encapsulates the political realm to a certain extent. This is notably evident in provisions that establish and regulate the state institutions that operate in this realm, as well as in those that govern the operation of politics or elections. Written constitutions tend to be under-inclusive in this regard, however – for instance, they often ignore the idea of political parties,Footnote 60 even though these are central to the functioning of government and political life. Moreover, they do not explicitly address the many constitutional conventions that also regulate the functioning of governments and parliaments. More generally, it should be clear that political knowledge extends beyond familiarity with legal rules, be it found in the constitution or related texts. Such knowledge also encompasses an understanding of the political system writ large, its processes, the daily functioning of government and current issues and events. For example, a prominent 1989 American survey of political knowledge ranged from the constitutional (e.g. ‘Length of a presidential term’, ‘Describe one First Amendment right’), to current affairs (e.g. ‘Percent unemployed’, ‘Size of federal budget’), to contemporary politics (e.g. ‘Name vice president’, ‘Party control of House’), to the international (e.g. [Who is] Margaret Thatcher, [Who is] Mikhail Gorbachev), to the economic (e.g. ‘Define the effects of a tariff’, ‘Define recession’) and the historical (e.g. ‘Did women always have suffrage’, ‘Date of New Deal’).Footnote 61 Political knowledge is thus concerned with fostering comprehension of how the political realm functions, which helps to give shape to and actualize the notion of constitutional literacy beyond the provisions of the written constitution.

Civic knowledge

Thinking back to the justifications set out earlier in support of constitutional literacy, the image of ‘the people’ that emerges goes beyond a collection of individuals that simply know facts about the particular contents of the constitution and its operation on the political plane. Rather, the expectation, or aspiration, is that people should also be confident and competent to leverage such facts through their behaviour. This is where civic knowledge and education come in. Hargreaves has often been quoted in relation to what civic education means:

Since Aristotle [civic education] has been accepted as an inherently political concept that raises questions about the sort of society we live in, how it came to take its present form, the strengths and weaknesses of current political structures, and how improvements might be made.Footnote 62

Civic knowledge overlaps with and relates to legal and political knowledge, but it forms a distinct part of the constitutional literacy picture. This type of knowledge is concerned with an understanding of how the latter types of knowledge can be activated. Put differently, the civic arena is where citizens make use of their familiarity with the legal and the political to participate in the public square, which explains the emphasis in the civic knowledge literature on skills, engagement and capacity.Footnote 63 These particular civic talents may include ‘the ability to write a letter, attend a meeting and take part in its decisions, plan or chair a meeting, and give a presentation or speech’.Footnote 64 In brief, civic knowledge fits with an action-oriented understanding of constitutional literacy that deliberately goes beyond the mere accumulation of knowledge pertaining to the written text and political system.

Expanding the picture of constitutional literacy

Positioning constitutional literacy at the intersection of legal, political and civic bodies of knowledge appears intuitive and aligned with the justifications discussed in the previous section. However, while those elements are important, they are arguably under-inclusive, which may potentially have stunted the constitutional literacy project more generally. To breathe more life into constitutional literacy, we should look at this notion in broader terms. One important advantage of doing so is that there will be different ways for individuals to be literate beyond the more specialized processes that familiarity with legal texts, methods of adjudication and relevant court cases imply. As such, a broader reading can help democratize the notion beyond legal and political elites.

One element that should be included in such a broader reading is constitutional history.Footnote 65 This is especially to the extent that constitutions and constitutional behaviours are associated with tradition.Footnote 66 As Sir Ivor Jennings notes, constitutional history is the ‘servant of the lawyer and the politician’,Footnote 67 and if we desire a constitutionally animated citizenry, the same prescription seems commendable. Being familiar with the founding and development of the constitutional order would allow people to properly situate the contemporary design and functioning of constitutional governments as well as to better understand the choices made during the drafting, amending and interpretation of their constitutions.

In addition, and taking a cue from the notion of literacy as related to language itself, Gee insists that literacy should go beyond content-focused definitions and take into account the social milieu in which language is used. As such, acquiring literacy is not limited to learning letters, words and phrases; it is also concerned with becoming familiar with the social practice where one would ‘say or write the right thing in the right way while playing the right social role and (appearing) to hold the right values, beliefs and attitudes’.Footnote 68 Transplanting this conceptualization to constitutional literacy, this suggests that we may also wish people to become acquainted with the actual ‘life’ of the constitution as manifested in the actions and behaviour of constitutional actors. Viewing candidates for political office take part in a debate, watching legislators discuss and vote for Bills and hearing judges announce the outcome of their deliberations are all activities that allow citizens to learn and understand the essence of constitutional dynamics.Footnote 69 As Barber notes, ‘in a regime that is both democratic and constitutional, the highest task of political leadership is to educate the public from its initial inclinations to what good faith and full deliberation indicate about the public’s true interests’.Footnote 70In this sense, then, literacy would arise from citizen observation of how constitutional actors and the officials that personify them behave in their constitutional role as opposed to citizens merely consulting and consuming written information. Such observation would help put flesh on the bones of the constitutional framework that is the focus of the legal knowledge component mentioned earlier. It may also help demonstrate to people how grand principles, such as checks and balances, judicial independence or legal-political processes that may otherwise appear indigestible and abstract, are given meaning on a daily basis.

Taken together, constitutional literacy may accordingly be said to be more akin to Figure 1. This conception shows that there is a strong interconnected quality to the notion. Indeed, we suggest that constitutional literacy interacts with a wide variety of forms of knowledge and should accordingly be seen as a dynamic, multifaceted concept that relies on people being exposed to information from a diverse range of sources. Crucially, the understanding of literacy we advocate deliberately goes beyond familiarity with the written constitution, and also beyond a view of those documents as singularly legal texts that are given meaning through supreme or constitutional courts to the exclusion of actors operating within the political domain.Footnote 71

Figure 1. A more complete and dynamic picture of constitutional literacy.

IV. The variable and fluid nature of constitutional literacy

The preceding discussion has hopefully cast light on the meaning of constitutional literacy. A quintessential attribute of this notion is its open-endedness, which extends from its meaning to the application and realization of literacy. Indeed, constitutional literacy is not a single standard that applies uniformly across all members of a given polity, nor would that be necessarily desirable. Its presence and significance may further vary along temporal and geographic lines, also within a single jurisdiction.

Literacy’s audiences and intermediaries

Popular literacy

When thinking about the audiences of constitutional literacy, it seems self-evident that a distinction should be maintained between legal professionals (judges, lawyers, etc.), political office-holders and civil servants on the one hand, and lay persons on the other hand. Legally trained professionals and political office-holders can be expected to be more intimately acquainted with constitutional texts, processes and practices than other individuals, Footnote 72 and can further avail themselves of resources, both financial and human, to augment their constitutional literacy (e.g. aides, external experts, continuing education courses or further professional training), none of which are readily available to laypersons. Our interest in this article is accordingly with the latter and with what can be called popular constitutional literacy.

When it comes to what ordinary individuals should know about constitutional matters, three points should be borne in mind. First, in thinking about the degree of literacy that lay people ought to possess, there are no accepted professional parameters that can guide our thinking about the appropriate standard of literacy in the way that these exist for legal and political elites.Footnote 73 Indeed, while the latter’s professional lives operate within a context that requires regular interaction with aspects of constitutional literacy, the daily lives of most individuals are far removed from this context. On the one hand, it is not always immediately obvious what responsibilities that have a constitutional dimension or underpinning are incumbent on lay individuals.Footnote 74 On the other hand, as the approach to democracy has transitioned from being direct to representative in character, the role of individuals in relation to governance has changed.Footnote 75 Notwithstanding the deliberative wave of recent decades, most people are not regularly or immediately involved in the law-making, executive or judicial features of government that could implicate constitutional questions and therefore necessitate a particular level of constitutional literacy.

Second, looking more closely at ‘the people’, we should not lose sight of the fact that this is a vastly heterogeneous category, meaning that it would be overly simplistic to treat this diverse collection of individuals as a single class for the purposes of constitutional literacy. Popular needs and demands for such literacy are likely to vary depending on a range of markers. These include an individual’s place within society, including whether they hold the status of citizen or are otherwise entitled to participate in the public square or exercise constitutional guardianship roles,Footnote 76 their background and personal identity, their proclivity for political or social engagement and their age. To put it simply, one would neither expect nor require the same degree of literacy of staff working in an NGO dedicated to women’s rights as they would of persons belonging to a vulnerable or marginalized community (e.g. refugees, asylum seekers or citizens without internet access), or even of primary school students. Furthermore, some people will be aware that there are gaps when it comes to their constitutional knowledge and, importantly, exhibit a desire to redress this information deficit by seeking out literacy-boosting information. We can call this the ‘curious public’: individuals who are self-primed or intrinsically motivated to be interested in constitutional issues and who may accordingly (wish to) exhibit higher than average levels of constitutional literacy. For these individuals, there may be an aspirational quality to the notion. In contrast, other people may not be so inclined, and may exhibit a posture of agnosticism, apathy or even antagonism towards the constitutional system. Such individuals may be unconcerned about their respective level of constitutional literacy.Footnote 77 These various situations pose challenging questions about suitable means to positively affect such an attitude of ‘incuriosity’ to buttress the effectiveness of literacy-cultivating initiatives by state entities or other providers.Footnote 78 For present purposes, though, our point is that it would be misguided to assume a ‘one-size-fits-all’ approach in relation to the personal dimension of constitutional literacy. Rather, we should think of this notion as a spectrum, with a series of diverse audiences, each with its own predisposition, motivations and preferences to learn or do more about the various types of knowledge identified as pertinent to such literacy, and this to varying degrees. This means, in other words, that we should be cautious in assuming that there exists a single nationwide standard that is met by all those living within its territory.

Finally, and building on the previous points, we recognize that many states do put forward minimum levels for the state ‘knowledge’ that is required of new citizens. These often come in the form of citizenship tests, which must be passed before citizenship is granted or before the naturalization process proceeds further.Footnote 79 At first blush, such tests could perhaps be seen as markers of what a society considers as minimally constitutionally literate. The content of these tests, however, often covers or focuses on elements that do not squarely fall within the understanding of literacy as advocated above: think of practical knowledge regarding daily living (e.g. how to apply for benefits), widespread moral values (e.g. towards things like sexuality or gender roles) and prominent cultural information (e.g. famous musicians, artists or athletes). Elements more closely related to our understanding, such as constitutional history, may be contentious. Indeed, there can be significant differences in the iterations of the tests from one government to another, including what constitutional aspects are emphasized throughout.Footnote 80 The way the tests are used also varies significantly among countries.Footnote 81 Although citizenship tests can thus be important in articulating shared values and connecting to constitutional identity, and can get new citizens ‘up to speed’ on not just state structures, but a wide range of cultural and practical information – similar to what citizens already living in these countries would encounter during schooling and in their daily lives – looking at them as minimal gauges for constitutional literacy is problematic for a variety of reasons, especially when considering the picture of literacy that we present above.

Intermediaries

Let us next consider how popular constitutional literacy can be operationalized – that is, how lay individuals would partake of information regarding the various components of knowledge and behaviours that are constitutive of constitutional literacy. In this regard, there are intermediaries at work, who help to explain legal texts, political norms or public actions to ordinary citizens so that the latter can perform the roles outlined in Part II above. Such intermediaries may also act as interpreters of such constitutional materials and conduct. Those intermediaries include actors working within state institutions. Sometimes, their efforts are legally or constitutionally mandated; at other times they are engaged in by way of extension of public functions. Examples include civil servants involved in delivering government-sponsored civic education programmes,Footnote 82 judges creating brochures explaining to citizens what purpose constitutional adjudication serves in a democracy and members of parliament engaging with constituents regarding the latter’s constitutionally derived entitlements vis-à-vis the state. Other intermediaries can make a valuable contribution to conveying facets of constitutional literacy as well, and though performing a public-facing role, operate more in the private sphere. Political parties have traditionally been particularly effective in this regard, by helping to orient and influence citizens’ responsibilities as voters or more generally as public participants in political processes. To this end, they have an interest in conveying information about laws and regulations pertaining to political campaigns and electoral processes. They also do so through articulating different approaches to realize the principles, objectives and values articulated or implied in the constitution.Footnote 83 Moreover, notably in parliamentary systems, opposition parties are specifically responsible for role-modelling constitutional notions of checks and balances, accountability and responsible government (e.g. through the idea of the ‘loyal opposition’).Footnote 84 Civil society can also be a constructive intermediary, mainly by leveraging its role in overseeing how public officials use their competences, but also by providing citizens with an arena to hone and apply their legal, political and civic knowledge. Finally, the media play an increasingly significant role in communicating the constitution and associated knowledge through reporting on the behaviour of constitutional actors, including other intermediaries. This is also true for the new types of media present in our societies, such as blogs, vlogs, microblogs, social networking and other types of communications.

In keeping the people abreast of important constitutional issues, these intermediaries not only augment popular constitutional literacy, but may also provide necessary correctives at times. For example, in March 2021, several UK business owners decided to defy COVID-19 restrictions by putting statements in their shop windows invoking clause 61 of the Magna Carta, which they claimed provided a right to dissent to laws if they felt they were being governed unjustly.Footnote 85 In fact, clause 61 was repealed in 1216, just one year after the original Magna Carta was sealed. In the end, the upheavals regarding whether Magna Carta could protect business owners against further coronavirus restrictions were short-lived, with the media, together with the police, helping to quell misconceptions regarding the rights protected under the UK constitutional framework. Taken together, we should accordingly recognize the valuable role that intermediaries – which tend to be non-constitutional experts – play in the constitutional literacy project. As conduits of information, they may help highlight the salience of such literacy and undertake to improve the various types of knowledge associated with it. At the same time, we should realize that if their own understanding and practice of all things constitutional is deficient or characterized by disinterest, constitutional literacy may conversely be suppressed.

Literacy across time and place

Constitutional literacy is contingent in other aspects, too. In particular, the quantum and focus of such literacy will vary spatially as well as temporally. This is perhaps seen most dramatically during or in the immediate aftermath of moments of constitutional change. If popular participation in the adoption of the new text is envisaged,Footnote 86 the occasion of formal change tends to result in the increased dissemination of constitutional information. It may also trigger interest in the constitutional status quo ante to better appreciate the nature and significance of the envisaged change. Literacy further acquires prominence in transitional settings or in other situations where the constitution has been drastically overhauled. In such cases, prior governance practices and ideologies may be at odds with the normative precepts associated with a country’s new constitution, while this text may also introduce novel power-sharing mechanisms. A classic example is South Africa’s confrontational post-Apartheid constitution that sought to deliberately reshape the country’s social and political institutions in line with a new set of basic values, alongside the establishment of a range of new democracy-protecting bodies, such as the constitutional court or human rights commission.Footnote 87 Likewise, several states in the Asia-Pacific region have long privileged elders, nobility or traditional chiefs in decision-making, in a manner that did not comport with the equal (in the libertarian) sense of participation in expressing the collective will as provided for in their constitutions following extensive reform efforts.Footnote 88 Under such conditions, literacy becomes important to instruct citizens and others on the fresh commitments enshrined in the constitution and associated behavioural expectations at a particular moment in time. But these literacy-enhancing efforts are not easy, as the South African case demonstrates.Footnote 89

In addition, times of crisis may place constitutional literacy in sharp relief. This was seen, for example, in societal debates regarding the decision not to invoke emergency powers during the COVID-19 pandemicFootnote 90 and the permissibility of curbs on basic fundamental rights, from free movement to the exercise of religious beliefs. Thus, in the Netherlands for instance, the government’s attempt to restrict such rights through decentralized emergency regulations led to a growing awareness of the constitution’s relevance in providing the appropriate legal basis and conditions for rights limitations.Footnote 91 High-profile political developments or scandals may generate similar focal points, such as the removal from office of Korean President Park in 2017, which awakened many ordinary citizens both to the rules on impeachment and to the existence of the country’s constitutional court and its role in enforcing constitutional law.Footnote 92

Next, interpretations by courts or political institutions of constitutional provisions may overrule or drastically adjust the meaning previously ascribed thereto, often in response to extra-legal developments. Think, for instance, of the ‘separate but equal doctrine’ initially accepted in Plessy v Ferguson Footnote 93 as a legitimate reading of the Fourteenth Amendment to the US Constitution that was famously rejected in Brown v Board of Education,Footnote 94 or the recent decision in Dobbs,Footnote 95 which reversed an earlier Supreme Court ruling, Roe v Wade, that provided stronger protections for abortion.Footnote 96 The same type of changes can be observed in the Japanese Cabinet Legislation Bureau accepting that Article 9 of the Constitution – the so-called peace clause – no longer prevents participation in collective self-defence missions in response to rising global security threats.Footnote 97 In the immediate aftermath of such evolved understandings, there is an obvious need to update constitutional understandings. In an optimistic scenario, the presence of such instances could moreover become a catalyst for citizens to become more interested in procuring or acting on constitutional knowledge.

Finally, there can be intra-jurisdictional variation in literacy standards. Differences may obtain on account of the country’s size, but may also be influenced by aspects such as separatist tendencies in certain parts thereof. Those living in such regions and agitating in favour of self-determination may be more well-versed in existing and alternative vertical separation of powers arrangements than their compatriots in other areas. The situation in the United Kingdom seems especially instructive here, as citizens in devolved entities – such as Scotland, Wales and Northern Ireland – may be more aware of the powers (or limitations) under these arrangements than citizens in England, who do not have a devolved legislature. Conversely, they may also have a distinct view of constitutional operation, in that they may emphasize or pay attention to certain features of the constitution but downplay or ignore others. Again, Scotland seems like a good example here, as the main tenet of the UK constitution – parliamentary sovereignty – is not as readily accepted in Scotland.Footnote 98

Constitutional literacy, then, is heavily context-dependent.Footnote 99 Like constitutional meaning, it may fluctuate over time and across space. This reality cautions against easy statements about the choice of what would constitute appropriate mechanisms for its realization or the extent to which it should be present within the population at large.

V. Measuring constitutional literacy

A corollary of the fluid nature of constitutional literacy is that there are difficulties and ambiguities in assessing its empirical manifestations. An important complication is that there can be such a dizzying array of situations in which individuals leverage constitutional knowledge in the real world that a full translation thereof in quantitative or qualitative terms does not seem quite possible. Thus, any data-collection effort is likely to be under-inclusive and provide only a partial picture of the state of constitutional literacy. Take, for example, the relatively straightforward exercise of using surveys to measure people’s awareness of the existence of the formal constitution or its most pertinent features, such as the number of branches of government or the identification of those rights that are explicitly protected. This is undoubtedly a common approach: news reports that claim to speak to the level of constitutional literacy often refer to surveys that have been designed along those lines.Footnote 100 To be sure, such surveys can tell us something about certain aspects of constitutional literacy in a given jurisdiction, but these may not be the best or most useful indicators of the knowledge that individuals truly possess. Constitutional literacy is a sprawling notion, which should extend beyond a textual understanding of the formal constitution. Knowledge regarding the larger principles that speak to the identity of the constitutional order, or relating to the public role of individuals as citizens, including their sentiments to the constitution, the state, the form of government or other aspects of constitutionalism, are not easily or reliably captured in surveys.Footnote 101 Additionally, a lack of textual constitutional knowledge does not mean that citizens do not hold their own values about justice, fairness, truth, politics and a number of other important elements that relate to the ways in which constitutional democracies operate.

A possible alternative approach is to look to the actual usages of the constitution by members of the public as evidencing their understanding of constitutional matters. Here one could think of the performance of constitutional rights or obligations by individuals in the public square, such as participating in demonstrations, the number of associations dedicated to politics or constitutional issues, or voting in countries where this is not compulsory. Data along these lines would again offer an incomplete proxy for the true amount of constitutional literacy that prevails in society, however. It may also be unclear whether interest should lie primarily or only in uncovering the frequency with which the constitution is used or also the substantive quality of that usage, which would focus attention on the elusive issue of what would constitute a ‘worthy’ display of constitutional literacy.

Additionally, the degree to which citizens pay attention to or ‘watch’ constitutional actors may be difficult to determine, especially in an era where people have access to a variety of media outlets. Other aspects included in our definition of constitutional literacy, such as constitutional history, could play out in books, television shows, movies, plays and other forms of entertainment.Footnote 102 But these markers are, at least to our knowledge, not used when it comes to assessing constitutional literacy. Finally, accumulating and accessing data regarding the actual invocation of constitutional knowledge is much more complicated than merely surveying a small segment of the public on particular aspects of the constitution.

But let us assume for the moment that there is workable data – even if flawed in some respects – that provides an indication of societal levels of constitutional literacy. At that point, literacy advocates will likely also need a yardstick that speaks to what would be a satisfactory, if not an optimal, level of literacy within the jurisdiction. This would enable a determination of the need for and scope, if any, of remedial action to increase literacy levels.Footnote 103 How could such a baseline to be established? We might look to the past for an assessment of the kind of adequate or even high degrees of literacy that have been achieved in society before. Times of significant constitutional (re)making would be a natural candidate for such a baseline, as citizens would be expected to be engage with constitutional questions during such times, which could occur either when formal adoption or amendment processes are initiated or during what Ackerman has referred to as ‘constitutional moments’, those rare occasions outside of normal politics during which national debates regarding higher-order constitutional issues become of acute interest to citizens.Footnote 104 But these ‘moments’ are often focused around a major issue or two, rather than critique of the constitution as a whole. Leaving aside the question of measurement,Footnote 105 the past may not however necessarily be the most suitable marker for achieving future literacy levels. After all, the content of constitutional literacy varies over time, in part on account of formal and informal constitutional change, and any standard ought to be duly cognizant of that fact. An alternative approach would be to attempt to fashion an idealized benchmark that abstracts from real-world levels of constitutional understanding. But there are serious concerns here, one being that the literacy benchmark can be set at an unrealistically high level that would produce unmanageable expectations as to what citizens ought to be familiar with. Another complexity would be the plurality of audiences and their attributes, which could make formulating a single national standard an extremely difficult exercise.

Lastly, attempts to measure constitutional literacy will need to contend with the contested nature of this notion. As is well known, different views exist – including among the constitutional actors whose behaviours may be observed to arrive at a greater degree of constitutional literacy – regarding what constitutes a ‘correct’ understanding of constitutional issues or the method to take in studying these.Footnote 106 For example, even judges, as the typical authoritative interpreters of the written constitution, may proffer multiple readings of the proper meaning to be ascribed to this text (which may also implicate different approaches to the process of constitutional interpretation).Footnote 107 Beyond the courts, different public institutions and their officials perform different roles within the legal order and ‘this makes it likely that they will view the constitution from different viewpoints’,Footnote 108 which in turn will likely influence their conduct in giving effect to the constitution. Such divergences are conducive to the occurrence of constitutional dialogues, both among state institutions and within society.Footnote 109 At the same time, they also serve to complicate assessments of constitutional literacy. This is because any form of literacy measurement will not only be preoccupied with whether and to what extent people possess knowledge about the constitution and its operation, but also with the identification of the accuracy of that knowledge. In other words, those seeking to assess levels of constitutional literacy are typically interested in uncovering the degree to which people ‘correctly’ understand constitutional matters, as opposed to having inaccurate information or relying on mistaken beliefs. However, when there is no consensus about the ‘right’ reading of the constitutional text or the ‘right’ type of constitutional behaviours – which is not an uncommon occurrence - the consequence is that such determinations become very challenging indeed.

VI. Conclusion

Significant concerns abound about the state of constitutional literacy around the world, but generic alarmist statements are of little help to the literacy project. It seems more valuable, in contrast, to reflect on the meaning and characteristics of this notion to see whether it is understood and operationalized in a realistic and constructive manner. In this regard, the idea that constitutional literacy is in crisis because citizens are not well versed in highly legalistic texts (e.g. the constitution, legislation that operationalizes the constitution or major court cases) appears tenuous in that it places an almost impossibly high burden on lay individuals regarding the knowledge required of them. In our view, constitutional literacy should go beyond overly legalistic indicators and take a wider view of how such individuals may become constitutionally literate. Thus, a more complete and dynamic understanding of literacy should conceive of this notion as developing not merely from consultation of (a small sub-set of) written texts, but also as an observed form of knowledge or act of doing. Indeed, textual constitutional literacy may be only a small part of good citizenship. Citizens have finite resources to spend on literacy efforts, and using those to develop other forms of constitutional engagement may better serve their states, societies or local communities.Footnote 110 While some citizens may choose to put their energies into learning more about the written constitution or constitutional history, others may partake in civic engagement activities, and yet others may invest time and energy in improving their political knowledge and observing political leaders. All these citizens should be considered constitutionally literate, but each in different styles. As such, this article lays the foundation for thinking about constitutional literacy in different light, where a break from the text-centric approach may further enhance the role this notion plays within our democracies. Moving beyond text-driven knowledge matters because, as Crick notes, ‘The old routines of learning about “the constitution” in a non-discussive, un-problematic, and therefore dead boring manner (often called Civics) are now generally recognized as at least useless, at worst counter-productive to encouraging democratic spirit.’Footnote 111

At the same time, we do not pretend that the view of constitutional literacy presented here encapsulates the full extent of what this complicated concept may entail or require. As such, further theoretical and empirical research will be necessary to address at least three interrelated questions. The first is how a clearer conceptualization of constitutional literacy can help the practice and effectiveness of literacy-boosting initiatives for the benefit of participation in, and the defence, of a constitutional order. Such initiatives may be deployed by state institutions, but non-state actors (including knowledge institutions like universities, the free press or NGOs) may have an important role in this regard as well,Footnote 112 suggesting that we should be concerned to ensure that they are properly equipped to discharge this role. Regardless of who is the author of the literacy-boosting initiative, they will need to move beyond a focus on acquainting citizens with an entrenched ‘master text’ through top-down brochures or public campaigns. They may instead wish to think about leveraging the emerging literature on legal design, which advocates the adoption of a human-centred approach and suggests the use of technology and visual aids to present information a manner that is comprehensible for people and catered to their needs and capabilities.Footnote 113 It may further be worthwhile to identify and celebrate individuals or state institutions that are positive role-models of constitutional literacy and related virtues. Constitutional history, meanwhile, could perhaps profitably be disseminated through the arts. Second, we need to think carefully about how constitutional literacy can be better captured in terms of its measurement to enable us to make reasonable claims about the state of such literacy in a given country at a given point in time and chart a desirable way forward. Going beyond randomized surveys about constitutional architecture or the naming of apex judges would seem a suitable way forward. This includes recognising that literacy may consist of observational or even participatory learning. If so, we need to think carefully about the types of observation to include, and the manner in which these can be appropriately accounted for. As for the recent turn to make more use of participatory mechanisms, there is an unfolding debate about whether, and how much, such mechanisms improve constitutional-legal literacy that needs to be pursued more fully.Footnote 114 Third, future research may also need to reckon with the possible downsides of constitutional literacy, such as increased constitutional idolatry,Footnote 115 a potential reckoning with problematic or unfortunate aspects of a state’s constitutional historyFootnote 116 or a disparity between constitutional text and constitutional practice.Footnote 117 From a practical perspective, these downsides may potentially affect the way future constitutions are written or brought into effect.

References

1 See, for example, Carpini, and Keeter, S, What Americans Know About Politics and Why It Matters (Yale University Press, New Haven, CT, 1996) 39, 218–67Google Scholar; Pateman, C, Participation and Democratic Theory (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1970)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; MacPherson, CB, The Life and Times of Liberal Democracy (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1977)Google Scholar Ch 5.

2 Keane, J, The Life and Death of Democracy (WW Norton, New York, 2009) 585 Google Scholar.

3 Comparative Constitutions Project, ‘Data Visualizations’, available at <https://comparativeconstitutionsproject.org>.

4 See Part II of this article, which demonstrates that some written constitutions now even ‘constitutionalise’ the idea of constitutional literacy.

5 Constitutional literacy has come into play in national referendums on the voting system (2011) and European Union membership (2016), in addition to referendums at the sub-national level – for example, the referendum on Scottish independence in 2014.

6 ‘Independent Human Rights Act Review: Terms of Reference’, available at <https://www.gov.uk/guidance/independent-human-rights-act-review>.

7 Secretary of State for Justice, The Independent Human Rights Act Review: Full Report CP 586, (December 2021) 21.

8 For example, the United States has been a haven for experiments in civic, political and constitutional education. The Jack Miller Center, CIRCLE, the Center for Civic Education, the American Civics Center and the Marshall-Brennan Constitutional Literacy Project are just a snippet of the sprawling civic education programmes, centres and institutions found in the United States. Prominent individuals, such as former US Supreme Court justice Sandra Day O’Connor, have even devoted their lives, or an important part of their lives, to the endeavour of helping make citizens more constitutionally literate. Many civic education or constitutional literacy programs have laudable goals and ambitions. For example, the ABA’s Civil Rights Civics Institute (CRCI) believes that fostering civic education will decrease divisiveness in the United States.

9 J Silverbrook and C Stetson, ‘Constitutional Literacy: Introduction – the Need for a National Constitutional Literacy Campaign’, Washington Times, 8 September 2015; D Davenport, ‘The Civic Education Crisis’ (Hoover Institution, Washington, DC, 5 April 2019), available at <https://www.hoover.org/research/civic-education-crisis>; BK Whittenbury, ‘The State of Civic Education in America’ (2022) 47 Human Rights Magazine, available at <https://www.americanbar.org/groups/crsj/publications/human_rights_magazine_home/the-state-of-civic-education-in-america>.

10 Studies show that approximately 20–35 per cent of citizens have often never heard of a country’s founding documents: ‘Magna Carta 800th Anniversary Survey’, Magna Carta, 20 February 2015, available at <https://magnacarta800th.com/projects/international-poll>. See also C Cillizza, ‘Americans Know Literally Nothing About the Constitution’, CNN, 13 September 2017.

11 If need be, with the help of knowledge institutions such as universities, the free press and NGOs as intermediaries to ensure that the people have access to good quality information to perform public scrutiny of the conduct and output of those in, or running for, office. See Jackson, V, ‘Knowledge Institutions in Constitutional Democracies: Preliminary Reflections’ (2021) 7 Canadian Journal of Comparative and Contemporary Law 156 Google Scholar.

12 Goldman, A, Knowledge in a Social World (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1999) 317 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 Two major books on the subject have been published: Massaro, T, Constitutional Literacy: A Core Curriculum for a Multicultural Nation (Duke University Press, Durham, NC, 1993)Google Scholar and Dreisbach, C, Constitutional Literacy: A Twenty-First Century Imperative (Palgrave, New York, 2016)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. However, there have also been works in journals and other places throughout the years. A prominent example comes from the Denver University Law Review, which devoted a whole issue to public constitutional literacy in 2013 (see Hart, M, ‘Foreword: Public Constitutional Literacy; A Conversation’ (2013) 90 Denver University Law Review 825 Google Scholar). The American University’s Journal of Gender, Social Policy, and the Law did something similar in 2019, but focusing on the Marshall-Brennan Constitutional Literacy Project. See Wermiel, SJ, ‘The Marshall-Brennan Constitutional Literacy Project: An Introduction’ (2019) 27 American University Journal of Gender, Social Policy, and the Law 5 Google Scholar.

14 Fombad, C, ‘Constitutional Literacy in Africa: Challenges and Prospects’ (2018) 44 Commonwealth Law Bulletin 492 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Singh, A et al, ‘Constitutional Literacy in India’ (2021) 10 International Journal of Modern Agriculture 348 Google Scholar.

15 Campbell, D, ‘What Social Scientists Have Learned About Civic Education: A Review of the Literature’ (2019) 94 Peabody Journal of Education 32 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

16 Maiello, C, Oser, F and Biederman, H, ‘Civic Knowledge, Civic Skills and Civic Engagement’ (2003) 2 European Educational Research Journal 384 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Galston, WA, ‘Political Knowledge, Political Engagement, and Civic Education’ (2001) 4 Annual Review of Political Science 217 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 Klienberg, M and Lau, R, ‘The Importance of Political Knowledge for Effective Citizenship: Difference between the Broadcast and Internet Generations’ (2019) 83 Public Opinion Quarterly 338 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

18 Galston (n 16); Delli Carpini and Keeter (n 1).

19 See, for example, Foweraker, J and Landman, T, ‘Constitutional Design and Democratic Performance’ (2010) 9(2) Democratization 43 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Nwokora, Z, ‘Constitutional Design for Dynamic Democracies: A Framework for Analysis’ (2022) 20(2) International Journal of Constitutional Law 580 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

20 Keane, J, The Shortest History of Democracy (The Experiment, New York, 2022) 5458 Google Scholar.

21 Ibid. It has also been noted that ‘Critics of democracy – starting with Plato – have almost always argued that it means rule by the ignorant. Or worse, rule by the charlatans that the ignorant people fall for’: D Runciman, How Democracy Ends (Profile Books, London, 2018) 179. But see arguments from other scholars about why political ignorance should lead to other outcomes, such as smaller government: Somin, I, Democracy and Political Ignorance: Why Smaller Government is Smarter (2nd ed., Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA, 2016)Google Scholar.

22 For example, Brennan, J, Against Democracy (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 2016)Google Scholar; Caplan, B, The Myth of the Rational Voter: Why Democracies Choose Bad Policies (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Bell, D, The China Model: Political Meritocracy and the Limits of Democracy (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 2016)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

23 Tushnet, M and Bugaric, B, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in an Age of Populism (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2021)Google Scholar.

24 Morgan, E, Inventing the People: The Rise of Popular Sovereignty in England and America (WW Norton, New York, 1988)Google Scholar; Weale, A, The Will of the People: A Modern Myth (Polity Press, New York, 2018)Google Scholar.

25 For example, Landemore, H, Open Democracy: Reinventing Popular Rule for the Twenty-First Century (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 2020)Google Scholar; Espejo, P Ochoa, The Time of Popular Sovereignty: Process and the Democratic State (Penn State University Press, University Park, PA, 2011)Google Scholar; Beckman, L, Gover, K and Mörkenstam, U, ‘The Popular Sovereignty of Indigenous Peoples: A Challenge in Multi-people States’ (2021) 26 Citizenship Studies 1 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

26 For example, Pettys, TE, ‘Popular Constitutionalism and Relaxing the Dead Hand: Can the People be Trusted’ (2008) 86(2) Washington University Law Review 313 Google Scholar.

27 P Beck, ‘We (the People) Need an Annotated Pocket Constitution’ SSRN (19 June 2019) 9, available at <https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3402518>.

28 Ackerman, B, We the People, Volume I: Foundations (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1991) 37 Google Scholar. Ackerman (1991: 36) also notes that ‘the narrative we tell ourselves about our Constitution’s roots is a deeply significant act of collective self-definition; its continual re-telling plays a critical role in the ongoing construction of national identity’.

29 Weiler, J, ‘On the Power of the Word: Europe’s Constitutional Iconography’ (2005) 3 International Journal of Constitutional Law 173, 184CrossRefGoogle Scholar. ‘Our national constitutions are perceived by us as doing more than simply structuring the respective powers of government and the relationships between public authority and individuals or between the state and other agents. Our constitutions are said to encapsulate fundamental values of the polity and this, in turn, is said to be a reflection of our collective identity as a people, as a nation, as a state, as a community or as a union.’

30 Columbia Constitution 1991, Title 1.

31 Dominican Republic Constitution 2015, Title II.

32 Bhutan Constitution, Art 8(11).

33 Ethiopia Constitution 1994, Art 9.

34 Mozambique Constitution 2004, Art 46.

35 Peru Constitution 1993, Title I.

36 Venezuela Constitution 1999, Title III.

37 TG Daly, ‘Designing the Democracy-Defending Citizen’ (2020) 6 Constitutional Studies 189, 203 notes that tendency to codify constitutional literacy provisions seems mainly confined to countries that are not full liberal democracies.

38 Ginsburg, T, ‘Constitutional Specificity, Unwritten Understandings and Constitutional Agreement’ in Sajó, A and Uitz, R (eds), The Constitutional Topography: Values and Constitutions (Eleven Publishing, The Hague, 2010)Google Scholar.

39 Stephanopoulos, N and Versteeg, M, ‘The Contours of Constitutional Approval’ (2016) 94 Washington University Law Review 1 Google Scholar.

40 Sternberger, D, Lebende Verfassung. Studien über Koalition und Opposition (Verlag Anton Hein, Meisenheim am Glan, 1956)Google Scholar; Molt, P, ‘Dolf Sternbergers Verfassungspatriotismus’ (2006) 16 Zeitschrift für Politikwissenschaft 875 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Datemsch, A, Verfassungspatriotismus – eine vergleichende Darstellung der Begriffsbestimmung bei Dolf Sternberger und Jürgen Habermas (GRIN Publishing, Munich, 2010)Google Scholar.

41 Müller, J-W, Constitutional Patriotism (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 2007)Google Scholar; Habermas, J, The Inclusion of the Other (MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 1998) 105–54Google Scholar; J Habermas, ‘Eine Art Schadensabwicklung’ (1986) 29 Der Zeit, available at <https://www.zeit.de/1986/29/eine-art-schadensabwicklung?utm_referrer=https%3A%2F%2Fwww.google.com%2F>.

42 For example, Bobbio, L, ‘Designing Effective Public Participation’ (2018) 38 Policy and Society 41 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ginsburg, T, Blount, J and Elkins, Z, ‘The Citizen as Founder: Public Participation in Constitutional Approval’ (2008) 81 Temple Law Review 361 Google Scholar. International actors are similarly committed to involving the people in constitution (re)making processes, among others: E Houlihan and S Bisarya, ‘Practical Considerations for Public Participation in Constitution-Building: What, When, How and Why?’ International IDEA Policy Paper No. 24, 2021; B Boutros-Ghali, ‘An Agenda for Democratization’ (United Nations, New York, 1996).

43 Blount, J, ‘Participation in Constitutional Design’ in Ginsburg, T and Dixon, R (eds), Comparative Constitutional Law (Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, 2011) 39 Google Scholar.

44 Jones, BC, ‘Preliminary Warnings on “Constitutional” Idolatry’ (2016) Public Law 74, 78–83Google Scholar. It has been noted that we should be wary of employing the ‘unconstitutional’ label too frequently, as ‘there is a risk that the term “unconstitutional” comes to include everything we subjectively do not like’: McLean, J, ‘The Unwritten Political Constitution and Its Enemies’ (2016) 14 International Journal of Constitutional Law 119, 136CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

45 For example, Gordon, N and Berkowitz, N, ‘Human Rights Discourse in Domestic Settings: How Does It Emerge?’ (2007) 55 Political Studies 243 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

46 Although we acknowledge that some recent scholarship has examined the downsides of rights – see, for example, Greene, J, How Rights Went Wrong: Why Our Obsession with Rights is Tearing America Apart (Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, Boston, 2021)Google Scholar; Ford, R Thompson, Rights Gone Wrong: How Law Corrupts the Struggle for Equality (Farrar, Straus and Giroux, New York, 2012)Google Scholar.

47 T Roosevelt, ‘The Duties of American Citizenship’, 26 January 1883, available at <https://glc.yale.edu/duties-american-citizenship>.

48 See generally Graber, M, Levinson, S and Tushnet, M (eds), Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2018)Google Scholar; Ginsburg, T and Huq, A, How to Save a Constitutional Democracy (University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 2020)Google Scholar; Daly, TG, ‘Democratic Decay: Conceptualising an Emerging Research Field’ (2019) 11 Hague Journal on the Rule of Law 9 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Belasvusau, U and Gliszczynska-Gabrias, A (eds), Constitutionalism Under Stress (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2020)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

49 Loughlin, M, ‘The Contemporary Crisis of Constitutional Democracy’ (2019) 39(2) Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 435 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, arguing that while important, institutional or constitutional solutions alone may not be sufficient to address anti-democratic challenges and concerns. More generally, on a role for the people, see Daly (n 37).

50 Dreisbach (n 13) 11.

51 Fombad (n 14) 495.

52 For example, Canada Constitution Part VII, Ecuador Constitution Title IX, Ghana Constitution Art 1(2); Japan Constitution Chapter X; Malaysia Constitution Art 4; Mexico Constitution Title Seven; South Africa Constitution Chapter 1.

53 Levinson, S, ‘Do Constitutions have a Point?’ in Paul, E, Miller, F and Paul, J (eds), What Should Constitutions Do? (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 2011) 152 Google Scholar.

54 For instance, the Indian Constitution is over 145,000 words in length. On this, see BC Jones, ‘Perhaps the Only Thing Worthy of Veneration: Brevity’, Balkinization,12 June 2022, available at <https://balkin.blogspot.com/2022/06/perhaps-only-thing-worthy-of-veneration.html>.

55 Amar, AR, America’s Unwritten Constitution: The Precedents and Principles We Live By (Basic Books, New York, 2012)Google Scholar.

56 More generally, we should remember that constitutional knowledge is only one facet of legal knowledge. For example, a typical law degree covers much more than constitutional law, including topics such as contract, tort, property, criminal, trusts and estates, and ethics.

57 For example, see Frosini, J, Constitutional Preambles at a Crossroads between Politics and Law (Maggioli Editore, Milan, 2012)Google Scholar; Orgad, L, ‘The Preamble in Constitutional Interpretation’ (2010) 8 International Journal of Constitutional Law 714 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

58 Although they were once thought to be relevant only to the political realm, conventions have increasingly been adjudicated in the courts: Ahmed, F, Albert, R and Perry, A, ‘Judging Constitutional Conventions’ (2019) 17 International Journal of Constitutional Law 787 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

59 Delli Carpini and Keeter (n 1).

60 Daly, TG and Jones, BC, ‘Parties versus Democracy: Addressing Today’s Political Party Threats to Democratic Rule’ (2020) 18 International Journal of Constitutional Law 509 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Khaitan, T, ‘Political Parties in Constitutional Theory’ (2020) 73 Current Legal Problems 89 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

61 Delli Carpini and Keeter (n 1) 158–60.

62 D Hargreaves, ‘The Mosaic of Learning: Schools and Teachers for the Next Century’ (1994) Demos 32–33.

63 Galston, WA, ‘Civic Knowledge, Civic Education, and Civic Engagement: A Summary of Recent Research’ (2007) 30 International Journal of Public Administration 623 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Maiello, Oser and Biederman (n 16).

64 Levine, P, ‘Civic Knowledge’ in Edwards, M (ed), The Oxford Handbook of Civil Society (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2011) 364 Google Scholar.

65 Biagi, F, Frosini, J and Mazzone, J (eds), Comparative Constitutional History: Principles, Developments, Challenges (Brill, Leiden, 2020)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Tan, K and Bui, NS (eds), Constitutional Foundings in Southeast Asia (Bloomsbury, Oxford, 2019)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

66 Think for instance of constitutional provisions that aim to safeguard national cultural traditions, including those of members belonging to indigenous groups or minorities, or an interpretative approach to constitutional provisions that attaches significant weight to the views of the drafters thereof.

67 Sir I Jennings, Cabinet Government (3rd ed, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2009).

68 Gee, JP, ‘Literacy, Discourse, and Linguistics: Introduction’ (1989) 171 Journal of Education 5, 6CrossRefGoogle Scholar. He refers to literacy as ‘discourse’.

69 On the role of courts as constitutional role-models, see De Visser, , ‘Promoting Constitutional Literacy: What Role for Courts?’ (2022) 23 German Law Journal 1121 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. More critical about the ability of governments to act accordingly is Daly (n 37) 205.

70 S Barber, Constitutional Failure (Kansas University Press, Lawrence, KS, 2014) 59.

71 On the role of non-judicial actors in giving meaning to the constitution, see M De Visser and J Neo, ‘What Would a Pluralist Institutional Approach to Constitutional Interpretation Look Like? Some Methodological Implications’ (2022) 20 International Journal of Constitutional Law 1884; G Appleby, V MacDonnell and E Synot, ‘The Pervasive Constitution: The Constitution Outside the Courts’ (2020) 48 Federal Law Review 437.

72 This holds true even if their constitutional knowledge may be lacking, outdated or otherwise defective as a matter of reality.

73 We cover ‘knowledge’ tests targeted at new citizens below but believe that these come with a host of problems when considering them a baseline or minimal form of literacy for both new and birthright citizens alike.

74 Generally, see A Miller, ‘Toward a Concept of Constitutional Duty’ [1968] The Supreme Court Review 199.

75 Galligan, DThe People, the Constitution, and the Idea of Representation’ in Galligan, D and Versteeg, M (eds), Social and Political Foundations of Constitutions (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2013)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

76 On the political rights of non-citizens, see for example, Rodríguez, CM, ‘Noncitizen Voting and the Extraconstitutional Construction of the Polity’ (2010) 8 International Journal of Constitutional Law 30 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kayran, EN and Nadler, A-L, ‘Non-citizen Voting Rights and Political Participation of Citizens: Evidence from Switzerland’ (2022) 14 European Political Science Review 206 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

77 Campbell, A, ‘The Passive Citizen’ (1962) 6 Acta Sociologica 9 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Such an attitude may be more prevalent among birthright citizens than naturalized citizens, who may not be able to affect uncuriosity, as they may be required to take tests that assess aspects of constitutional knowledge.

78 Word constraints prevent us from further developing ways to address this concern. We can note, however, that a significant portion of literacy-boosting initiatives may need to be targeted at the youth, in line with the psychological argument that younger minds are more susceptible to new ideas, which holds out the prospect of inculcating pro-constitutional mindsets from an early age that would hopefully be sustained through adulthood (especially with continuous exposure to literacy-boosting information and activities for adults as well).

79 Elias, SB, ‘Testing Citizenship’ (2016) 96 Boston University Law Review 2093 Google Scholar.

80 Elias (n 79). See the examples discussed in the article, such as the United Kingdom (pp 2121–27), the Netherlands (pp 2127–34), Germany (pp 2134–41), and France (pp 2142–48), each of which changed the content and focus of their citizenship knowledge tests at various points.

81 Elias (n 79) 2155–58. For example, they can be used as hurdles to exclude or hinder further naturalization within a given state, or as ‘rewards’ for new citizens in terms of achieving certain levels of integration.

82 Such programmes are constitutionally mandated in, among others, the Constitution of Cape Verde, Art 73; the draft Chile Constitution, Chapter III; the Fiji Constitution, Art 31(4); and the Venezuela Constitution, Title III.

83 This happens irrespective of the form of government to which a country subscribes. For an example in the US presidential system, consider the pledge by the Democratic Party to ‘fight to pass a Constitutional amendment that will go beyond merely overturning Citizens United [a US Supreme Court decision holding that the First Amendment right to free speech means that the government cannot restrict “independent political spending” from corporations and other groups] and related decisions like Buckley v Valeo by eliminating all private financing from federal elections’, available at <https://democrats.org/where-we-stand/party-platform/restoring-and-strengthening-our-democracy>.

84 For a discussion of the application of the idea of the loyal opposition in the context of a presidential system, using the United States as the main example, see Anastaplo, G, ‘Loyal Opposition in a Modern Democracy’ (2003) 35 Loyola University of Chicago Law Journal 1009 Google Scholar.

85 A Colman, ‘COVID Lockdown: Why Magna Carta Won’t Exempt You from the Rules’, BBC News, 6 March 2021, available at <https://www.bbc.co.uk/news/56295261>.

86 This is rapidly becoming the default position. From an abundant literature see, for example, Elkins, Ginsburg and Blount (n 42), V Hart, ‘Constitution Making and the Right to Take Part in a Public Affair’ in L Miller and L Aucoin (eds), Framing the State in Times of Transition (US Institute of Peace Press, New York, 2010).

87 Klare, K, ‘Legal Culture and Transformative Constitutionalism’ (1998) 14 South African Journal of Human Rights 146 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Botha, H, van der Walt, A and van der Walt, J (eds), Rights and Democracy in a Transformative Constitution (Sun Press, Johannesburg, 2003)Google Scholar.

88 See M De Visser and E Perham, ‘Contextualising Participatory Constitution-Making: Insights from the Small State Experience’ (2022) 20 International Journal of Constitutional Law 1216.

89 See BC Jones, Constitutional Idolatry and Democracy: Challenging the Infatuation with Writtenness (Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, 2020) 45; D Bilchitz et al., ‘Assessing the Performance of the South African Constitution’, International IDEA, 20 May 2016, available at <https://www.idea.int/publications/catalogue/assessing-performance-south-african-constitution>.

90 For general discussion, see T Ginsburg and M Versteeg, ‘The Bound Executive: Emergency Powers During the Pandemic’ (2021) 19 International Journal of Constitutional Law 1498; J Grogan, ‘States of Emergency: Analysing Global Use of Emergency Powers in Response to COVID-19’ (2020) 4 European Journal of Law Reform 338.

91 M Julicher, ‘Following the Constitution in Times of Corona: A Path to Redeeming Constitutional Idolatry in the Netherlands?’, IACL Blog, 19 January 2021, available at <https://blog-iacl-aidc.org/2021-posts/2021/1/19/following-the-constitution-in-times-of-corona-a-path-to-redeeming-constitutional-idolatry-in-the-netherlands-t6hky>.

92 See, for example, H-S Lim, ‘A Closer Look at the Korean Constitutional Court’s Ruling on Park Geun-hye’s Impeachment’ (2017) Yale Journal of International Law (Online Supplement), 18 May; M Hee and Y Seongyi, ‘The Role of Social Media and Emotion in South Korea’s Presidential Impeachment Process’ (2019) 55 Issues and Studies – Institute of International Relations 195.

93 Plessy v Ferguson 163 U.S. 537 (1896).

94 Brown v Board of Education of Topeka 347 U.S. 483 (1954).

95 Dobbs v Jackson Women’s Health Organization, No. 19-1392, 597 U.S. ___ (2022).

96 Roe v Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973).

97 ‘New Legislation Bureau Head Eager to Discuss Collective self-defense’, Japan Times, 20 August 2013.

98 The principle has even been questioned in the Scottish courts. For example, in 1953 Lord President Cooper asserted that, ‘The principle of the unlimited sovereignty of Parliament is a distinctively English principle which has no counterpart in Scottish constitutional law.’ MacCormick v Lord Advocate 1953 SC 396.

99 For example, T Ginsburg, ‘Constitutional Knowledge’ (2018) Know: A Journal on the Formation of Knowledge 15, 25.

100 See, for example, Cillizza (n 10).

101 We leave aside here questions regarding the representativeness of the population sample surveyed.

102 For example, the hit Broadway production Hamilton seems to be a perfect illustration in this regard.

103 In a less-optimistic scenario, an ‘established’ deficiency in constitutional literacy might even be relied on by some to argue that people should not be entrusted with a significant role in government.

104 Ackerman (n 28) 263.

105 For an attempt to measure a past constitutional moment, see D Young, ‘How Do You Measure a Constitutional Moment? Using Algorithmic Topic Modelling to Evaluate Bruce Ackerman’s Theory of Constitutional Change’ (2013) 122 Yale Law Journal 1990.

106 Some suggest that familiarity with such diverse views is part and parcel of a high level of constitutional literacy: see Dreisbach (n 13). Apart from making it incredibly taxing for people to achieve such a level of literacy, attempts to do so may also have the effect of turning them off the notion in their entirety, as it could be perceived as too convoluted.

107 See, for example, P Brest, ‘The Misconceived Quest for the Original Understanding’ (1980) 60 Boston University Law Review 204; A Scalia, ‘Originalism: The Lesser Evil’ (1989) 57 Cincinnati Law Review 849.

108 D Feldman, ‘Factors Affecting the Choice of Techniques of Constitutional Interpretation’ in L’interprétation constitutionnelle, edited by F Mélin-Soucramanien (Dalloz, Paris, 2005) 120.

109 For example, see G Sigalet, G Webber and R Dixon (eds), Constitutional Dialogue: Rights, Democracy, Institutions (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 2019); S Sanders, ‘Dignity and Social Meaning: Obergefell, Windsor, and Lawrence as Constitutional Dialogue’ (2018) 87 Fordham Law Review 2069.

110 However, we do not go as far as some, who have suggested that citizens should completely ignore politics and focus on things that really matter, such as local community projects and other forms of virtue. See C Freiman, Why It’s OK to Ignore Politics (Routledge, Abingdon, 2021). In our view, to suggest that one can ignore politics and then act politically is also a troubled notion. If individuals are completely unaware of political issues and problems, then it will be difficult to decide where to put their efforts.

111 Crick, B, Democracy: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2002) 115 Google Scholar.

112 On such institutions, see Jackson (n 11).

113 See, for example, S de Souza, ‘Communicating the Law: Thinking Through Design, Visuals and Presentation of Legal Content’ in Technology, Innovation and Access to Justice, edited by S de Souza and M Spohr (Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh, 2021); S Chung and J Kim, ‘Systematic Literature Review of Legal Design: Concepts, Processes, and Methods’ (2022) The Design Journal, available at <https://arxiv.org/pdf/2303.14336.pdf>.

114 Citizens’ assemblies and other participatory mechanisms can allow the ordinary individuals involved therein to ‘learn by doing’ what the functioning of constitutional democracy entails and requires, while providing other segments of the public with yet another actor whose behaviour can be observed for constitutional learning. When the topics for deliberation have a constitutional flavour, such modalities of what Landemore (n 25) calls ‘open democracy’ can further enable citizens to (better) discern how fundamental rights and institutional structures are expounded upon and concretised for application.

115 Jones (n 87).

116 This is playing out in America at the moment, as the views of the ‘Founders’ have come under increased scrutiny: see, for example, ‘The 1619 Project’, The New York Times, 14 August 2019. However, it may also come about because of the way that certain constitutions have been written (e.g. by outsiders or for other states), or potentially because of the lack of a national referendum on the final text.

117 It has been noted that they are ‘definitely not blueprints’: G Frankenberg, Comparative Constitutional Studies: Between Magic and Deceit (Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, 2018) 14–15.

Figure 0

Figure 1. A more complete and dynamic picture of constitutional literacy.