Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T07:35:01.941Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

EXPRESSIBLE SEMANTICS FOR EXPRESSIBLE COUNTERFACTUALS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 September 2010

EMMANUEL CHEMLA*
Affiliation:
Institut Jean Nicod & LSCP
*
*LABORATOIRE DE SCIENCES COGNITIVES ET PSYCHOLINGUISTIQUE, ECOLE NORMALE SUPÉRIEURE, 29 RUE D’ULM, 75005 PARIS, FRANCE. E-mail:chemla@ens.fr

Abstract

Lewis (1981) showed the equivalence between two dominant semantic frameworks for counterfactuals: ordering semantics, which relies on orders between possible worlds, and premise semantics, which relies on sets of propositions (so-called ordering sources). I define a natural, restricted version of premise semantics, expressible premise semantics, which is based on ordering sources containing only expressible propositions. First, I extend Lewis’ (1981) equivalence result to expressible premise semantics and some corresponding expressible version of ordering semantics. Second, I show that expressible semantics are strictly less powerful than their nonexpressible counterparts, even when attention is restricted to the truth values of expressible counterfactuals. Assuming that the expressibility constraint is natural for premise semantics, this result breaks the equivalence between ordering semantics and (expressible) premise semantics. Finally, I show that these results cast doubt on various desirable conjectures, and in particular on a particular defense of the so-called limit assumption.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Ginsberg, M. L. (1986). Counterfactuals. Artificial Intelligence, 30(1), 3579.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kratzer, A. (1979). Conditional necessity and possibility. In Bäuerle, R., Egli, U., & von Stechow, A., editors. Semantics from Different Points of View: With 15 Figures, Berlin: Springer, 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kratzer, A. (1981). Partition and revision: The semantics of counterfactuals. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 10(2), 201216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kratzer, A. (1989). An investigation of the lumps of thought. Linguistics and Philosophy, 12(5), 607653.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1981). Ordering semantics and premise semantics for counterfactuals. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 10(2), 217234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, R. C. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In Rescher, N., editor. Studies in Logical Theory, Volume 2 of American Philosophical Quarterly Monograph Series. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 98112.Google Scholar