Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-nmvwc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-17T05:53:28.974Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

More on the Falsification Challenge1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2008

J. Kellenberger
Affiliation:
Assistant Professor of Philosophy, San Fernando State College, California

Extract

Flew's challenge to the religious believer asks him to specify what would count as a disproof for, e.g. ‘There is a God’. A statement of such a specifiable condition I called an ‘empirical denial’. In my earlier paper I was concerned to show that a statement is a statement whether or not it has such an empirical denial. I was not particularly concerned to show that there are some statements which do not have an empirical denial; my concern was to show that it is not essential that they do. It was in connection with this point that the statement ‘John loves Mary’ was discussed. But this very same example may indeed serve as an example of a statement for which, in certain complex situations, there is no empirical denial. That is, in some circumstances, no matter what empirical conditions are specified, when the statement ‘John loves Mary’ is made (if they are not merely necessary conditions), they could obtain and still John might love Mary, as the developing situation would make clear. If the condition specified is that John is cruel to Mary and shows no concern for her, details could always emerge in such a situation to explain why, even though he loved her, he was cruel and showed no concern. And so on.

Type
Section II: Christian Philosophy and Ethics
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1969

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 244 note 1 I have been helped greatly here by conversations with Donald F. Henze, although I am sure that he would not agree with all that I say.

page 246 note 1 The problem of God predication at this point looms large in the minds of many, no doubt. For, they would want to point out, this analysis allows that ‘loves’ is predicated of God in the same sense it is predicated of men. To be brief, so it does, but then so it is. If it were not, then truly we would be lost in our understanding of what we are being told when we are told that God is concerned for us and loves us as a Father.

page 246 note 2 In what follows I do not reply to McPherson's point that I do not distinguish between saying that p and ˜˜p are equivalent in meaning and saying that ˜˜p gives the meaning of p. The distinction McPherson is pointing up is valid: often something equivalent in meaning does not give the meaning of what one says to someone else. Thus while ‘Au secours!’ is equivalent in meaning to ‘Help’! it would not give the meaning of ‘Help!’ to one who speaks only German. However I do not think that any confusion regarding this distinction undercuts the argument I propounded to support the idea that assertions must have an empirical denial. If it does, so much the worse for the argument, which of course was not one I advocated as sound, but one I examined as a possible argument a proponent of Flew's views might advance to support the falsification challenge.

page 247 note 1 He says that ‘the view that reasons for religious belief are internal to the belief has been persuasively presented by such writers as Professor Peter Winch and Mr D. Z. Phillips. From such a view it could be said that there is, in a sense, evidence for religious belief…’