Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-ttngx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-12T06:05:31.038Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Heritage From Logical Positivism: A Reassessment

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Lindley Darden*
Affiliation:
University of Maryland, College Park

Extract

Stephen Toulmin, in assessing the legacy of logical positivism, remarked: “Yet, even though we slay our intellectual parents, we cannot help but inherit from them…. While many of us whose philosophical careers began after 1946 reject the positivism of our forebears, it would be presumptuous for us to deny our inheritance entirely. At the very least, we share with our analytic predecessors a common stock of questions and problems about whose answers and solutions we disagree” ([28], p. 51).

In biological evolution organisms cannot choose which genes to retain, nor can they strive to introduce particular new genes. However, we, as philosophers, can choose which things we wish to inherit from our intellectual parents and which things we wish to eliminate as nonadaptive in our current environment.

Type
Part IV. Logical Positivism, Its Origins and Critics
Copyright
Copyright © 1977 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

I would like to thank my colleagues at the University of Maryland as well as Nancy Maull and David Hull for their comments on earlier drafts of this paper. This work was supported in part by a Summer. Stipend from the National Endowment for the Humanities.

References

[1] Achinstein, Peter. “Inference to Scientific Laws. In Historical and Philosophical Perspectives of Science. (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science Vol. V.) Edited by Stuewer, Roger. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1970. Pages 87111.Google Scholar
[2] Achinstein, Peter. Law and Explanation. Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1971.Google Scholar
[3] Darden, Lindley. “Reasoning in Scientific Change: The Field of Genetics at Its Beginnings.” Ph.D. Dissertation, The University of Chicago, 1974.Google Scholar
[4] Darden, Lindley. “Reasoning in Scientific Change: Charles Darwin, Hugo de Vries, and the Discovery of Segregation.” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 7(1976): 127169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[5] Darden, Lindley. “William Bateson and the Promise of Mendelism.” Journal of the History of Biology, forthcoming 1977.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[6] Darden, Lindley and Maull, Nancy. “Interfield Theories.” Philosophy of Science 44(1977): 4364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[7] Fisher, R.A.Has Mendel's Work Been Rediscovered?Annals of Science 1(1936): 115137. (As reprinted in Stern, Curt and and Sherwood, Eva (eds.). The Origins of Genetics, A Mendel Source Book. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman and Company, 1966. Pages: 139-172).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[8] Hanson, Norwood Russell. “Is There a Logic of Scientific Discovery?The Australian Journal of Philosophy 38(1960): 91106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[9] Hempel, Carl. Philosophy of Natural Science. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, 1966.Google Scholar
[10] Hull, David. Philosophy of Biological Science. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, 1974.Google Scholar
[11] Kemeny, John G. and Oppenheim, Paul. “On Reduction.” Philosophical Studies 7(1956): 619. (As reprinted in Brody, Baruch, A. (ed.). Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, 1970. Pages 307-318).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[12] Kuhn, Thomas. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd ed. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1970.Google Scholar
[13] Lakatos, Imre. “Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes.” In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Edited by Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, Alan. Cambridge, England: The University Press, 1970. Pages 91195.Google Scholar
[14] Maull Roth, Nancy. “Progress in Modern Biology: An Alternative to Reduction.” PhD Dissertation, University of Chicago, 1974.Google Scholar
[15] McMullin, Ernan. “The History and Philosophy of Science: A Taxonomy.” In Historical and Philosophical Perspectives of Science. (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science vol. V). Edited by Stuewer, Roger. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1970. Pages 1267.Google Scholar
[16] Mendel, Gregor. “Versuche uber Pflanzen-Hybriden.” Verhandlungen des naturforschen den Vereines in Brunn 4, Abhandlungen (1865): 347. (As reprinted as “Experiments on Plant Hybrids.” in Stern, Curt and Sherwood, Eva (eds.). The Origins of Genetics, A Mendel Source Book. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman and Company, 1966. Pages 1-48).Google Scholar
[17] Morgan, Thomas Hunt. The Theory of the Gene. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1926.Google Scholar
[18] Nagel, Ernest. The Structure of Science. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc., 1961.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[19] Olby, Rober C. Origins of Mendelism. New York: Schocken Books, 1966.Google Scholar
[20] Oppenheim, Paul, and Putnam, Hilary. “Unity of Science as a Working Hypothesis.” In Concepts, Theories and the Mind-Body Problem. (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science Vol. II). Edited by Feigl, Herbert, Scriven, Michael and Maxwell, Grover. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1958. Pages 336.Google Scholar
[21] Popper, Karl. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1960.Google Scholar
[22] Schaffner, Kenneth. “Logic of Discovery and Justification in Regulatory Genetics.” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 4(1974): 349385.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
[23] Schaffner, Kenneth. “The Peripherality of Reductionism in the Development of Molecular Biology.” Journal of the History of Biology 7(1974): 111139.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
[24] Shapere, Dudley. “Scientific Theories and Their Domains.” In The Structure of Scientific Theories. Edited by Suppe, Frederick. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1974. Pages 518565.Google Scholar
[25] Shapere, Dudley. “On the Relations Between Compositional and Evolutionary Theories.” In Studies in the Philosophy of Biology. Edited by Ayala, F.J. and Dobzhansky, T.. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1974. Pages 187204.Google Scholar
[26] Suppe, Frederick. “The Search for Philosophic Understanding of Scientific Theories.” In The Structure of Scientific Theories. Edited by Suppe, F.. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1974. Pages 3241.Google Scholar
[27] Suppe, Frederick. “Post World-War II Developments in American Philosophy of Science.” Ruch Filozoficzny 38(1975): 135168. And in “Afterword—1976.” Forthcoming in the 2nd edition of Structure of Scientific Theories. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1977.Google Scholar
[28] Toulmin, Stephen. “From Logical Analysis to Conceptual History.” In The Legacy of Logical Positivism. Edited by Achinstein, Peter and Barker, Stephen. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins Press, 1969. Pages 2553.Google Scholar
[29] Toulmin, Stephen Human Understanding Vol. I. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1972.Google Scholar
[30] Wright, Sewell. “Mendel's Ratios.” In The Origin of Genetics, A Mendel Source Book. Edited by Stern, Curt, and Sherwood, Eva. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman and Company, 1966. Pages 173175.Google Scholar