Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-g7rbq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-29T21:26:20.007Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Darwin and Disjunction: Foraging Theory and Univocal Assignments of Content

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Lawrence A. Shapiro*
Affiliation:
University of Pennsylvania

Extract

According to Jerry Fodor, “[h]uffing and puffing and piling on the teleology just doesn’t help with the disjunction problem; it doesn’t lead to univocal assignments of intentional content” (1990, p. 72). That Fodor separates these two claims with only a semicolon is unfortunate, for each merits individual scrutiny. First, there is the claim that appeals to the theory of evolution by natural selection will not help with the disjunction problem. I will argue that the truth of this claim depends upon how we characterize the relation between a representational state and that which it is about Fodor assumes this relation must be a causal one, and this assumption leads inevitably to the disjunction problem.

Type
Part XII. Issues in the Philosophy of Psychology
Copyright
Copyright © 1992 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

In writing this paper I have benefitted from many useful discussions with Gary Hatfield. Thanks also go to Gary Ebbs.

References

Charnov, E. (1976), “Optimal Foraging: Attack Strategy of a Mantid”, The American Naturalist 110:141-151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. (1987), “Styles of Mental Representation”, in The Intentional Stance, D., Dennett (ed.). Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 213-225.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. (1988), Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Elner, R.W. and Hughes, R.N. (1978), “Energy Maximization in the Diet of the Shore Crab, Carcinus maenas”. Journal of Animal Ecology 47:103-116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. (1974), “Special Sciences”, Synthese 28:77-115.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1981), Representations: Philosophical Essays on the Foundations of Cognitive Science. Cambridge:MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1987), Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. (1990), “A Theory of Content, I: The Problem”, in A Theory of Content and Other Essays, Fodor, J. (ed.). Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 51-87.Google Scholar
Gould, S.J. and Lewontin, R. (1978), “The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme”, Proceedings of the Royal Society B205:581-598.Google Scholar
Hatfield, G. Representation and Content in Some (Actual) Theories of Perception”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 19:175-214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harfield, G. (1991), “Representation in Perception and Cognition: Connectionist Affordances”, in Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, Ramsey, W., Stich, S. and , Rummelhart (eds.). Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, pp. 163-195.Google Scholar
Haugeland, J. (1978), “The Nature and Plausibility of Cognitivism”, The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1: 215-226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jaeger, R. and Barnard, D. (1981), “Foraging Tactics of a Terrestrial Salamander: Choice of Diet in Structurally Simple Environments”, The American Naturalist 117: 639-664.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kosslyn, S. M. and Hatfield, G. (1984), “Representation Without Symbol Systems”, Social Research 51: 1019-1045.Google Scholar
Krebs, J.R. and Davies, N.B. (1987), An Introduction to Behavioural Ecology, 2nd ed. Oxford:Blackwell Scientific Publications.Google Scholar
Lewontin, R. (1978), “Adaptation”, Scientific American 293: 213-230.Google Scholar
Marr, D. (1982), Vision. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman and Co.Google Scholar
Matthen, M. (1988), “Biological Functions and Perceptual Content”, The Journal of Philosophy 85: 5-27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maynard Smith, J., (1978), “Optimization Theory in Evolution”, Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 9: 31-56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pittendrigh, C. (1958), “Adaptation, Natural Selection, and Behavior”, in Behavior and Evolution, Roe, A. and Simpson, G. (eds.). New Haven: Yale University Press, pp. 390-416.Google Scholar
Pyke, G., Pulliam, H. and Charnov, E. (1977), “Optimal Foraging: A Selective Review of Theory and Tests”, The Quarterly Review of Biology 52:137-154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rozin, P. and Schull, J. (1988), “The Adaptive-Evolutionary Point of View in Experimental Psychology”, in Stevens’ Handbook of Experimental Psychology, 2nd ed., Volume 1, Atkinson, R.C.,Herrnstein, R.J., Lindzey, G. and Luce, R.D. (eds.). Toronto: John Wiley and Sons, Inc., pp. 503-546.Google Scholar
Stephens, D.W. and Krebs, J.R. (1986), Foraging Theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Tinbergen, N. (1951), The Study of Instinct. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Werner, E.E. and Hall, D.J. (1974), “Optimal Foraging and Size Selection of Prey by the Bluegill Sunfish (Lepomis mochrochirus)”. Ecology 55:1042-1052.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, G. (1966), Adaptation and Natural Selection. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar