Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-8bljj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-22T23:55:55.306Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Anthropic Principle: A Primer for Philosophers

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Frank J. Tipler*
Affiliation:
Tulane University

Extract

Let's begin with a

Definition: The Anthropic Principle is the drawing of scientific inferences from a consideration of Man's Place in Nature.

There are various versions of the Anthropic Principle. The most conservative version of the Anthropic Principle is nothing but a systematic working out of the fact that the astrophysical (and other scientific) data we have is self-selected due to the fact that Homo sapiens is a particular type of intelligent being. This conservative version of the Anthropic Principle is called the

Weak Anthropic Principle (WAP): The observed values of all physical quantities are not equally probable, but rather take on values restricted by the fact that these quantities are measured by a carbon-based intelligent life-form which spontaneously evolved on an earthlike planet around a G2 type star.

Again, the Weak Anthropic Principle is just a warning to take into account a grandiose type of selection bias when interpreting data.

Type
Part III. Natural Philosophy
Copyright
Copyright © 1989 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

I am grateful to Frank Birtel, Michael Heller, Wolfhart Pannenberg, and John Wheeler for their comments on an earlier version of this paper. This work was supported in part by the National Science Foundation under grant number PHY-86-03130.

References

Abramowicz, M. and Ellis, G.F.R. (1989), “The Elusive Anthropic Principle”, Nature 337:411412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alder, H.L. and Roessler, E.B. (1964), Introduction to Probability and Statistics. San Francisco: Freeman.Google Scholar
Barrow, J. D. (1989), “Anthropic Principle”, Nature 339: 196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barrow, J. D. and Tipler, F.J. (1986), The Anthropic Cosmological Principle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Carter, B. (1989) in The Anthropic Principle, Curi, U. (ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Feller, W. (1968), An Introduction to Probability Theory and Its Applications, Volumes I & II. New York: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Flew, A. (ed.) (1964), Body, Mind, and Death. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Flew, A. (1984), God, Freedom and Immortality: A Critical Analysis. Buffalo: Prometheus.Google Scholar
Flew, A. (1987), The Logic of Mortality. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hawking, S. W. and Ellis, G.F.R. (1973), The Large Scale Structure of Space-Time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. (1977), Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. Smith, Norman Kemp (ed.). Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Hofstadter, D. R. and Dennett, D.C. (1981), The Mind's I. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1986), On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Linde, A.D. (1989), “Particle Physics and Cosmology”, In Proceedings of the XXIV International Conference on High Energy Physics, Kotthaus, R. and Kühn, J. (ed.). Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag.Google Scholar
Lovejoy, A.O. (1936), The Great Chain of Being. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. (1974), The Nature of Necessity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1931), Principles of Mathematics. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Tipler, F.J. (1976), “Singularities in Universes with Negative Cosmological Constant”, The Astrophysical Journal 209:1215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tipler, F.J. (1979), “General Relativity, Thermodynamics, and the Poincaré Cycle.Nature 280: 203205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tipler, F.J. (1980), “General Relativity and the Eternal Return.” In Essays in General Relativity, Tipler, F.J. (ed.). New York: Academic Press, pp. 2137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tipler, F.J. (1986), “Cosmological Limits on Computation.International Journal of Theoretical Physics 25: 617661.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tipler, F.J. (1988), “The Omega Point Theory.” In Physics, Philosophy, and Theology: A Common Quest for Understanding, by Russell, R.J., Stoeger, W. and Coyne, G., pp. 313331. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Tipler, F.J. (1989), “The Omega Point as Eschaton: Answers to Pannenberg's Questions for Scientists”, to appear in the July issue of Zygon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weinberg, S. (1987), “Anthropic Bounds on the Cosmological Constant”, Physical Review Letters 59: 26072610.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weinberg, S. (1989), “The Cosmological Constant Problem”, Reviews of Modern Physics 61: 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolfson, H. (1965), “Immortality and Resurrection in the Philosophy of the Church Fathers”, in Immortality and Resurrection, Stendahl, K. (ed.). New York: Macmillan, pp 5496.Google Scholar