Hostname: page-component-6d856f89d9-xkcpr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-16T06:31:09.371Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Allan Franklin’s Transcendental Physics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

Michael Lynch*
Affiliation:
Boston University

Extract

Does Allan Franklin’s study of atomic parity-violation experiments provide convincing evidence against social constructivism? According to Franklin (1990a, p. 2), “when questions of theory choice, confirmation, or refutation are raised they are answered on the basis of valid experimental evidence… [and] there are good reasons for belief in the validity of that evidence.” Franklin asserts that social constructivists take the opposite position: “They would say that it is not the experimental results, but rather the social and/or cognitive interests of the scientists, that must be used in the explanation.” Having set up the contrasting positions, he then asks the reader, “which of us is telling the more plausible story?” (Franklin 1990b, p. 163). Consistent with his evidence model, he proposes to discriminate between the two opposed positions by consulting historical evidence. He describes the results of two different sets of experiments on atomic parity-violations, and assesses the extent to which the experimental data match predictions based on the Weinberg-Salam unified theory of electroweak interactions.

Type
Part XII. Three Views of Experiment
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1991

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ackerman, R. (1989), “The New Experimentalism,British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 40: 185-90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, B. (1974), Scientific Knowledge and Sociological Theory. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Barnes, B. (1983), “On the conventional character of knowledge and cognition,” in Science Observed: Perspectives on the Social Study of Science, Knorr-Cetina, K. and Mulkay, M. (eds.). London: Sage, pp. 1951.Google Scholar
Bloor, D. (1976), Knowledge and Social Imagery. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Collins, H. (1985), Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice. London: Sage.Google Scholar
Elliot, J., Dunham, E., and Millis, R. (1977), “Discovering the Rings of Uranus,Sky and Telescope 53(6): 412-16.Google Scholar
Franklin, A. (1986), The Neglect of Experiment. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Franklin, A. (1990a), Experiment Right or Wrong. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Franklin, A. (1990b), “Do mutants have to be slain, or do they die of natural causes? The case of atomic parity-violation experiments,” Chapter Eight of Experiment Right or Wrong. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 162192. (An abbreviated version of this chapter appears under the same title in PSA 1990, Volume 2.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garfinkel, H., Lynch, M., and Livingston, E. (1981), “The work of a discovering science construed with materials from the optically discovered pulsar,Philosophy of the Social Sciences 11: 131-58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garfinkel, H., Lynch, M., Livingston, E., Lynch, M., MacBeth, D., and Robillard, A. (1988), “Respecifying the natural sciences as discovering sciences of practical action, I & II: Doing so ethnographically by administering a schedule of contingencies in discussions with laboratory scientists and by hanging around their laboratories,” unpublished paper, Department of Sociology, UCLA.Google Scholar
Galison, P. (1987), How Experiments End. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Gooding, D. (1988), “How do scientists reach agreement about novel observations?Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 17: 205-30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hacking, I. (1983), Representing and Intervening. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hesse, M. (1974), The Structure of Scientific Inference. London: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knorr-Cetina, K. and Mulkay, M. (1983), “Introduction: Emerging principles in social studies of science,” in Science Observed: Perspectives on the Social Study of Science, Knorr-Cetina, K. and Mulkay, M. (eds.). London: Sage, pp. 118.Google Scholar
Mannheim, K. (1936), Ideology and Utopia. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Pickering, A. (1984), Constructing Quarks. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Pinch, T. (1986), Confronting Nature. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapin, S., and Schaffer, S. (1985), Leviathan and the Air Pump. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Turner, S. (1981), “Interpretive charity, Durkheim, and the ‘strong programme’ in the sociology of science,Philosophy of the Social Sciences 11: 231-44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1969), On Certainty, Anscombe, G.E.M. and von Wright, G.H. (eds.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar