Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-m8s7h Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-23T21:20:54.543Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Temporality, Secondary Qualities, and the Location of Sensations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Paul Fitzgerald*
Affiliation:
Baruch College/City University of New York

Extract

Several philosophers in recent years, e.g., Baker (1974-5, 1979), Grünbaum (1971), Rescher (1973) and Salmon (1974) have argued that something they call “temporal becoming” is mind-dependent. They see the issue as analogous to the traditional one about the mind-dependence of secondary qualities. Do directly seen colors, felt coldness, and salty taste exist in the mind-independent world? Or only within experience? We know how the dialectic dances around that question….

“Roses are red, violets are blue, in the same way that some of our afterimages and sense-data are.”

“No, roses and violets don't really have colors. Roses only have the property of selectively reflecting light in the 7200 Å region. That makes them look red to us. But they aren't really red. Science shows that.“

Type
Part VII. Tachyons, Temporal Becoming, and Thermodynamics
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1982

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Armstrong, David M. (1978). Universals and Scientific Realism, 2 Vols. London: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Baker, Lynne Rudder. (1974-5). “Temporal Becoming: The Argument from Physics.” The Philosophical Forum 6: 218236.Google Scholar
Lynne Rudder, Baker. (1979). “On the Mind-Dependence of Temporal Becoming.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 39: 341357.Google Scholar
Bradley, M.C. (1963). “Sensations, Brain Processes, and Colours.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 41: 385393.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Butchvarov, Panayot. (1980). “Adverbial Theories of Consciousness.” In Studies in Epistemology. (Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Volume 5.) Edited by French, Peter A., et al. Minneapolis, Minn.: University of Minnesota Press. Pages 261280.Google Scholar
Campbell, Keith. (1971). Body and Mind. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Chisholm, Roderick. (1957). Perceiving, A Philosophical Study. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Chisholm, Roderick. (1977). Theory of Knowledge. 2nd ed. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Clark, Romane. (1975). “The Sensuous Content of Perception.” In Action, Knowledge, and Reality. Edited by Castañeda, Hector-Neri. Indianapolis, Ind.: Bobbs-Merrill. Pages 109127.Google Scholar
Cornman, James W. (1975). Perception, Common Sense, and Science. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Dawes Hicks, G. (1917). “Are the Materials of Sense Affections of the Mind.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 17: 434445. (Symposium with G.E. Moore, W.E. Johnson, J.A. Smith, and James Ward.)Google Scholar
Ducasse, Curt J. (1951) Nature, Mind, and Death. LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court Press.Google Scholar
Fitzgerald, Paul. (1978). Review of Mundle (1971). Philosophy of Science 45: 165169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitzgerald, Paul. (1979). Review of Jackson (1977). International Philosophical Quarterly 19: 103113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitzgerald, Paul. (1980). “Is Temporality Mind-Dependent?In PSA 1980. Volume 1. Edited by Asquith, Peter D. and Giere, Ronald N.. East Lansing, Mich.: Philosophy of Science Association. Pages 283291.Google Scholar
Gale, Richard. (1968). The Language of Time. New York: Humanities Press.Google Scholar
Grossmann, Reinhardt. (1976). Review of Cornman (1975). International Studies in Philosophy 8: 210213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grünbaum, Adolf. (1967). Modern Soienoe and Zeno's Paradoxes. Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan University Press.Google Scholar
Grünbaum, Adolf. (1971). “The Meaning of Time.” In Basic Issues in the Philosophy of Time. Edited by Freeman, E. and Sellars, W.. LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court Press. Pages 195228.Google Scholar
Jackson, Frank. (1977). Perceptions A Representative Theory. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mundle, C.W.K. (1971). Perception: Facts and Theories. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Noren, S.J. (1970). “Smart's Materialism, The Identity Theory, and Translation.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 48: 5466.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rescher, Nicholas. (1973). Conceptual Idealism. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Salmon, Wesley. (1974). “Memory and Perception in Human Knowledge.” In Bertrand Russell's Philosophy. Edited by Nakhnikian, George. London: Gerald Duckworth & Co. Pages 139167.Google Scholar
Schaffer, Jerome. (1968). Philosophy of Mind. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Sellars, Wilfrid. (1968). Science and Metaphysics. New York: Humanities Press.Google Scholar
Sellars, Wilfrid. (1975). “The Adverbial Theory of the Objects of Sensation.” Metaphilosophy 6: 144—160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smart, J.J.C. (1963). Philosophy and Scientific Realism. New York: Humanities Press.Google Scholar