Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-qs9v7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-13T19:27:28.887Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On Values in Science: Is the Epistemic/Non-Epistemic Distinction Useful?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Phyllis Rooney*
Affiliation:
Oakland University

Extract

The debate about values in science in the last decade or so reflects an important shift in what many acknowledge as the “post-positivist” era in philosophy of science. It reflects the erosion of the fact-value distinction in at least one of its more simplistic forms (facts belong in science, values outside), and it marks the path to a more enhanced understanding of the roles of both facts and values in scientific inquiry. This discussion has, above all, contributed to what we might call a revaluation of value: from the point of view of the epistemologist or philosopher of science values are neither uniform nor uniformly “bad”.

Type
Part I. Methodology and Explanation
Copyright
Copyright © 1992 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bleier, R. (1984), Science and Gender: A Critique of Biology and its Theories on Women. New York: Pergamon Press.Google Scholar
Fausto-Sterling, A. (1985), Myths of Gender: Biological Theories About Women and Men. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Haraway, D. (1989), Primate Visions: Gender, Race, and Nature in the World of Modern Science New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hubbard, R. (1982), “Have Only Men Evolved?”, in Discovering Reality, Harding, S. and Hintikka, M.B. (eds.). Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 45-69.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. (1977), “Objectivity, Value Judgment, and Theory Choice”, in his, The Essential Tension. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 320-339.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keller, E.F. (1985), Reflections on Gender and Science. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Keller, E.F. (1990), “From Secrets of Life to Secrets of Death”, in Body/Politics: Women and the Discourses of Science, Jacobus, M., Keller, E. F., and Shuttleworth, S. (eds.). New York: RoutledgeGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1984), Science and Values: The Aims of Science and Their Role in Scientific Debate. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Longino, H.E. (1990), Science as Social Knowledge: Values and Objectivity in Scientific Inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMullin, E. (1983), “Values in Science”, in PSA 1982, Volume 2, Asquith, P.D. and Nickles, T. (eds.). East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 3-28.Google Scholar
McMullin, E.. (1984), “The Rational and the Social in the History of Science”, in Scientific Rationality: The Sociological Turn, J.R. Brown (ed.). Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 127-163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rouse, J. (1991), “The Politics of Postmodern Philosophy of Science”, Philosophy of Science 58:4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, M. (1984), “Biological Science and Feminist Values”, in PSA 1984, Volume 2, Asquith, P.D. and Kitcher, P. (eds.). East Lansing:Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 525-542.Google Scholar