Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-vpsfw Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-23T20:30:27.111Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Bayesian Argument in Favor of Randomization

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Zeno G. Swijtink*
Affiliation:
Stanford University

Extract

The theory of personal probability must be explored with circumspection and imagination. For example, applying the theory naively one quickly comes to the conclusion that randomization is without value to statistics. This conclusion does not sound right; and it is not right.

L. J. Savage (1961, p. 585).

Randomization is a generally accepted principle of sound experimental design and common practice among working scientists. But many philosophers and some theoretical statisticians have rejected it. Bayesians have most often stated their opposition to randomization in terms of a decision theoretic argument. Not all Bayesians, however, could go along with that argument, as the above quotation by Leonard Savage testifies.

In this paper I will examine the Bayesian decision theoretic argument against randomization and show why it fails. By means of an example I will then give a partial justification of randomization in Bayesian terms.

Type
Part IV. Probability and Statistical Inference
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1982

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bennett, C.A. and Lumsdaine, A. (eds.). (1975). Evaluation and Experiment: Some Critical Issues in Assessing Social Programs. New York: Academic Press, Inc.Google Scholar
Campbell, D.T. and Borueh, R.F. (1975). “Making the Case for Randomized Assignment to Treatments by Considering the Alternatives: Six Ways in which Quasi-Experimental Evaluations in Compensatory Education Tend to Underestimate Effects.” In Bennett and Lumsdain. (1975). Pages 195296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fisher, R.A. (1935). The Design of Experiments. Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd.Google Scholar
Fisher, R.A. (1955). “Statistical Methods and Scientific Induction.” Journal of the Roval Statistical Society Series B, 17: 6978.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. and Harper, W.L. (1978). “Counterfactuals and Two Kinds of Expected Utility.” In Foundations and Applications of Decision Theory, Volume 1. (University of Western Ontario Series in the Philosophy of Science. Volume 13.) Edited Hooker, C.A., et al. Dordrecht: Reidel. Pages 125162.Google Scholar
Lindley, D.V. (1971). Bavesian Statistics, A Review. Philadelphia: Society for Industrial and Applied Mathematics.Google Scholar
Rosenthal, R. (1976). Experimenter Effects in Behavioral Research. 2nd enlarged ed. New York: Irvington Publishers, Inc.Google Scholar
Rubin, D.B. (1978). “Bayesian Inference for Causal Effects: The Role of Randomization.” Annals of Statistics 6: 3458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Savage, L.J. (1954). The Foundations of Statistics. New York: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Savage, L.J. (1961). “The Foundations of Statistics Reconsidered.” In Proceedings of the Fourth Berkeley Symposium on Mathematics and Probability, Volume I. Edited by Neyman, Jerzy. Berkeley: University of California Press. Pages 575586.Google Scholar
Savage, L.J. et al. (eds.). (1962). The Foundations of Statistical Inference. New York: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.Google Scholar
Wald, A. (1950). Statistical Decision Functions. New York: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.Google Scholar