Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-7drxs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-16T12:26:17.247Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

James Hutton and the Philosophy of Geology*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 June 2012

Get access

Extract

As a river in its seaward course gathers volume and momentum from its tributaries, so does a science, from its inception to its attainment of maturity and beyond, increase its strength, scope and depth by incorporating into itself its historical past, built up by the contributions of those scientists and philosophers whose work marks stages in its progress. A history of science, to fulfil its purpose, must unravel the intricate strands of ideas and facts which form the fabric of modern science and trace them back to their inspiration and source. Such a history would be almost beyond the bounds of human endeavour, and its only practicable substitute tends to degenerate into a mere collection of names of scientists, combined with a review of their individual contributions to the development of science. Science, however, is neither an assemblage of facts nor of ideas. It is a co-ordinated system of facts linked by theories—with the emphasis, generally speaking, on the ideas—and within our limited capacity it can best be interpreted by reconstructing the lives and reliving the thoughts of those men who have done most to fashion it. Such a man was Isaac Newton and such also was James Hutton. It is of little profit to argue as to which was the greater mind. What Newton achieved in the field of astronomy and mathematics Hutton achieved in the field of geology. It was he who provided geology with a theory: and here we must take theory, not as something remote and opposed to fact, but in its original meaning in Greek, namely, comprehension.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Royal Society of Edinburgh 1949

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

Reprinted by kind permission from Trans. Edin. Geol. Soc., XIV, Part II, 1948.

References

References to Literature

Boué, A., 1823. Edin. Phil. Journ., IX, 128.Google Scholar
Cuvier, G., 1798. Leçons d'anatomie comparée, Paris, An. VIII, I, 5.Google Scholar
Hutton, J., 1792. Dissertations on Different Subjects in Natural Philosophy, Edinburgh.Google Scholar
Osborn, H. F., 1894. From the Greeks to Darwin, New York And London, P. 105—quotation from J. B. Lamarck's Hydrogeologie.Google Scholar
Page, D., 1863. The Philosophy Of Geology, P. 4.Google Scholar
Playfair, J., 1822. Illustrations of the Huttonian Theory. Reprinted in The Works of John Playfair, Esq., I, 128.Google Scholar
Pope, A., 1733. An Essay on Man, Epistle I.Google Scholar
Robinet, J. B., 1767. Considerations philosophiques de la gradation naturelle des formes de l'être, ou des essais de la nature qui apprend à faîre l'homme, Amsterdam, p. 8.Google Scholar
Thomson, J., 1727. The Seasons. Summer.Google Scholar
Tomkeieff, S. I., 1946. “James Hutton's Theory of the Earth, 1795”, Proc. Geol.Assoc., LVII, 326.Google Scholar
Toulmin, G. H., 1780. Antiquity and Duration of the World.Google Scholar
Toulmin, G. H., 1783. The Antiquity of the World.Google Scholar
Toulmin, G. H., 1785. The Eternity of the World.Google Scholar
All quotations from Toulmin in the present article are taken from The Antiquity of the World, 1783.Google Scholar