Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-ttngx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-30T16:32:03.528Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Theories and the Transitivity of Confirmation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

Mary Hesse*
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge

Abstract

Hempel's qualitative criteria of converse consequence and special consequence for confirmation are examined, and the resulting paradoxes traced to the general intransitivity of confirmation. Adopting a probabilistic measure of confirmation, a limiting form of transitivity of confirmation from evidence to predictions is derived, and it is shown to what extent its application depends on prior probability judgments. In arguments involving this kind of transitivity therefore there is no necessary “convergence of opinion” in the sense claimed by some personalists. The conditions of application of the limiting transitivity theorem are most perspicuously described in terms of De Finetti's notion of exchangeability, which leads to a suggested revaluation of the function of theories in relation to confirmation and explanation.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1970 The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am grateful to the Editor and the referees for comments which helped me to revise the first draft of this paper.

References

[1] Achinstein, P., “Variety and Analogy in Confirmation Theory,” Philosophy of Science, vol. 30, 1963, p. 216.10.1086/287935CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[2] Achinstein, P., “The Problem of Theoretical Terms,” American Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 2, 1965, p. 193.Google Scholar
[3] Braithwaite, R. B., “On Unknown Probabilities,” in Observation and Interpretation (ed. S. Körner), London, 1957, p. 3.Google Scholar
[4] Brody, B. A., “Confirmation and Explanation,” Journal of Philosophy, vol. 65, 1968, p. 282.10.2307/2024079CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[5] Carnap, R., Logical Foundations of Probability, Chicago and London, 1950.Google Scholar
[6] Carnap, R. and Stegmüller, W., Induktive Logik und Wahrscheinlichkeit, Vienna, 1959.10.1007/978-3-7091-3142-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[7] De Finetti, B., “Foresight: Its Logical Laws, its Subjective Sources,” in Studies in Subjective Probability (eds. H. E. Kyburg and H. E. Smokier), New York, 1964, p. 95.Google Scholar
[8] Edwards, W., Lindman, H., and Savage, L. J., “Bayesian Statistical Inference for Psychological Research,” Psychological Review, vol. 70, 1963, p. 193.10.1037/h0044139CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[9] Hacking, I., “Slightly more Realistic Personal Probability,” Philosophy of Science, vol. 34, 1967, p. 311.10.1086/288169CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[10] Hempel, C. G., “Studies in the Logic of Confirmation,” in Aspects of Scientific Explanation, New York, 1965, p. 3.Google Scholar
[11] Hempel, C. G., “Deductive Nomological vs. Statistical Explanation,” Minnesota Studies in the Philosphy of Science III, (ed. H. Feigl and G. Maxwell), p. 98.Google Scholar
[12] Hempel, C. G., “Aspects of Scientific Explanation,” in Aspects of Scientific Explanation, New York, 1965, p. 331.Google Scholar
[13] Hesse, M., “Analogy and Confirmation Theory,” Philosophy of Science, vol. 31, 1964, p. 319.10.1086/288017CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[14] Hesse, M., “Consilience of Inductions,” in The Problem of Inductive Logic (ed. I. Lakatos), Amsterdam, 1968, p. 232.10.1016/S0049-237X(08)71046-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[15] Hesse, M., “Positivism and the Logic of Scientific Theories,” The Legacy of Logical Positivism (eds. P. Achinstein and S. Barker), Baltimore, 1969, p. 85.Google Scholar
[16] Hesse, M., “Duhem, Quine, and a New Empiricism,” Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures, III, London, 1970, forthcoming.Google Scholar
[17] Hilpinen, R., “Rules of Acceptance and Inductive Logic,” Acta Philosophica Fennica, Fasc. xxii, Amsterdam, 1968.Google Scholar
[18] Jeffrey, R. C., The Logic of Decision, New York, 1965.10.2307/2023748CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[19] Kyburg, H. E., Probability and the Logic of Rational Belief, Middletown, Conn., 1961.Google Scholar
[20] Lakatos, I., “Changes in the Problem of Inductive Logic,” in The Problem of Inductive Logic (ed. I. Lakatos), Amsterdam, 1968, p. 315.10.1016/S0049-237X(08)71048-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[21] Lehrer, K., “Induction, Reason, and Consistency,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 21, 1970, p. 103.10.1093/bjps/21.1.103CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[22] Levi, I., Gambling with Truth, New York, 1967.Google Scholar
[23] Putnam, H., “What Theories are Not,” in Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science (eds. E. Nagel, P. Suppes, and A. Tarski), Stanford, 1962, p. 240.Google Scholar
[24] Savage, L. J., The Foundation of Statistics, New York, 1954.Google Scholar
[25] Shimony, A., “Amplifying Personal Probability,” Philosophy of Science, vol. 34, 1967, p. 326.10.1086/288170CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[26] Skyrms, B., “Nomological Necessity and the Paradoxes of Confirmation,” Philosophy of Science, vol. 33, 1966, p. 230.10.1086/288096CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[27] Smokier, H., “Conflicting Conceptions of Confirmation,” Journal of Philosophy, vol. 65, 1968, p. 300.10.2307/2024080CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[28] Suppes, P., “Concept Formation and Bayesian Decisions,” in Aspects of Inductive Logic (eds. J. Hintikka and P. Suppes), Amsterdam, 1966, p. 21.10.1016/S0049-237X(08)71661-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[29] Todd, W., “Probability and the Theorem of Confirmation,” Mind, vol. 76, 1967, p. 260.10.1093/mind/LXXVI.302.260CrossRefGoogle Scholar