Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-tn8tq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-06T23:05:50.115Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Test of the Scientific Method

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Abstract

A conventional experiment is proposed to resolve the realist/idealist debate by challenging the premise that double blinding and an attitude of objectivity in general deter the corroborative influence which preconceptions exert on perception. The possibility that objectivity enhances corroboration would not contradict empirical findings, and would account for the success of science.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Barrow, J. and Tipler, F. (1988), The Anthropic Cosmological Principle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bell, J. (1987), Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brody, H. (1977), Placebos and the Philosophy of Medicine: Clinical, Conceptual and Ethical Issues. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Bucke, R. (1961), Cosmic Consciousness: A Study on the Evolution of the Human Mind. Secaucus, NJ: The Citadel Press.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1988), “Perceptual Plasticity and Theoretical Neutrality: A Reply to Jerry Fodor”, Philosophy of Science 55: 167187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeWitt, B. and Graham, N. (1973), The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1984), “Observation Reconsidered”, Philosophy of Science 51: 2343.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. (1988), “A Reply to Churchland's ‘Perceptual Plasticity and Theoretical Neutrality‘”, Philosophy of Science 55: 188198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greenwood, J. (1990), “Two Dogmas of Neo-Empiricism”, Philosophy of Science 57: 553578.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
James, W. (1936), The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature. New York: The Modern Library.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. ([1962] 1970), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2d ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Merrell-Wolff, F. (1973a), Pathways Through to Space: A Personal Record of Transformation in Consciousness. New York: Julian Press.Google Scholar
Merrell-Wolff, F. (1973b), The Philosophy of Consciousness Without an Object: Reflections on the Nature of Transcendental Consciousness. New York: Julian Press.Google Scholar
Roberts, J. (1974), The Nature of Personal Reality: A Seth Book. New York: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Shimony, A. (1989), “Conceptual Foundations of Quantum Mechanics”, in Davies, P. (ed.), The New Physics. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, pp. 373395.Google Scholar
White, L.; Tursky, B.; and Schwartz, G. (eds.), (1985), Placebo: Theory, Research and Mechanisms. New York: Guilford Press.Google Scholar