Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-m9kch Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-05T02:23:52.795Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Science in a Democratic Republic

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

I. C. Jarvie*
Affiliation:
York University
*
Send requests for reprints to the author, York University, Department of Philosophy, 4700 Keele Street, Toronto, Ontario M3J 1P3; email: jarvie@yorku.ca.

Abstract

Polanyi's and Popper's defenses of the status quo in science are explored and criticized. According to Polanyi, science resembles a hierarchical and tradition-oriented republic and is necessarily conservative; according to Popper's political philosophy the best republic is social democratic and reformist. By either philosopher's lights science is not a model republic; yet each claims it to be so. Both authors are inconsistent in failing to apply their own ideals. Both underplay the extent to which science depends upon the wider society; and neither makes sufficient allowance for the ways it can disrupt the social order. Polanyi even demands extraterritorial exemption for science from the scrutiny of incompetent outsiders. In their different ways, each minimizes the problems of institutionalized science and fails to consider the value, even the long-term necessity, for science of democratic criticism and control. Transnational control of science is an open challenge for democratic polities.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 2001

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Crombie, A. C. (ed.) (1963), Scientific Change. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fuller, Steve (1997), Science. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Fuller, Steve (2000a), The Governance of Science. Buckingham: The Open University Press.Google Scholar
Fuller, Steve (2000b), Thomas Kuhn: A Philosophical History for Our Time. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Gellner, Ernest (1974), Legitimation of Belief. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gellner, Ernest (1987), Culture, Identity, and Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hacohen, Malachi (1999), Karl Popper: The Formative Years, 19021945. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hall, John A. (1999), “The Sociological Deficit of The Open Society, Analyzed and Remedied”, in Jarvie and Pralong 1999, 8396.Google Scholar
Jarvie, Ian (2001), The Republic of Science: The Emergence of Popper's Social View of Science 19351945. Amsterdam: Rodopi.10.1163/9789004495838CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jarvie, Ian and Pralong, Sandra (eds.) (1999), Popper's Open Society After 50 Years. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1962), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Merton, Robert K. (1942), “A Note on Science and Democracy”, Journal of Legal and Political Sociology 1: 115126. Reprinted as “Science and Democratic Social Structure” in Merton [1949] 1957 and as “The Normative Structure of Science” in Merton 1973.Google Scholar
Merton, Robert K. ([1949] 1957), Social Theory and Social Structure, 2nd ed. Glencoe, IL: Free Press.Google Scholar
Merton, Robert K. (1973), The Sociology of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart (1859), On Liberty. London: J. W. Parker.Google Scholar
Moore, Walter (1989), Schrödinger. Life and Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511600012CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polanyi, Michael ([1945] 1964), Science, Faith and Society, 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. First edition published by Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Polanyi, Michael (1951), The Logic of Liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Polanyi, Michael (1958), Personal Knowledge. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Polanyi, Michael (1962), “The Republic of Science: Its Political and Economic Theory”, Minerva 1: 5473. Reprinted in Polanyi 1969, Ch. 3, 49–72.10.1007/BF01101453CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polanyi, Michael (1963), “Commentary by Michael Polanyi”, in Crombie 1963, 377382.Google Scholar
Polanyi, Michael (1969), Knowing and Being. Edited by Marjorie Grene. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. (1940), “What is Dialectic?”, Mind 49: 403426.10.1093/mind/XLIX.194.403CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. R. (1943), “Are contradictions embracing?”, Mind 52: 4750.10.1093/mind/LII.205.47CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. R. ([1944–1945] 1957), The Poverty of Historicism. London: Routledge. Original appeared as “The Poverty of Historicism I, II, III”, Economica 11: 86–103; 11: 119–137; 12: 69–89.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. ([1945] 1962), The Open Society and Its Enemies. London: Routledge. Fourth edition 1962.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. (1949), “Towards a Rational Theory of Tradition”, in Watts, F. (ed.), The Rationalist Annual for the Year 1949. London: Watts and Co., 3655. Reprinted in Popper 1963, Ch. 4.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. ([1935] 1959), The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. (1963), Conjectures and Refutations. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. (1994), The Myth of the Framework. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Schrödinger, Erwin (1944), What is Life? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shils, Edward (1954), “The Scientific Community: Thoughts After Hamburg”, Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, 10(5): 151–55. Reprinted in Edward Shils, The Intellectuals and the Powers and Other Essays (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1972), Chapter 9.Google Scholar