Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wzw2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-30T19:12:56.640Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Robert Stalnaker, Inquiry

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Hartry Field*
Affiliation:
School of Philosophy, University of Southern California

Extract

This is an interesting, well argued, and highly readable book; anyone interested in the central philosophical problems with which it deals will benefit from studying it.

Stalnaker defines inquiry as the process of forming, testing, and revising beliefs. His goal is to lay the groundwork for a theory of inquiry, by elaborating and defending a certain apparatus in terms of which the process of inquiry should be described.

Type
Critical Notice
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association 1986

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Burge, T. (1979), “Individualism and the Mental”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, IV: Studies in Metaphysics. Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Field, H. (1972), “Tarski's Theory of Truth”, Journal of Philosophy 69: 347–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, H. (1977), “Logic, Meaning and Conceptual Role”, Journal of Philosophy 74: 379–409.Google Scholar
Field, H. (1978), “Mental Representation”, Erkenntnis 13: 916. A new postscript was added in a reprinting in N. Block (ed.). Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology, vol. II, pp. 112–14. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. (1975), The Language of Thought. New York: Crowell.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1980), “Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: 6372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grover, D.; Camp, J.; and Belnap, N. (1975), “A Prosentential Theory of Truth”, Philosophical Studies 27: 73125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. (1973), Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. (1982), Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1973), Counterfactuals. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1986), On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Loar, B. (1981), Mind and Meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. (forthcoming), “Tacit Belief”, in Belief, Bogdan, R. (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pollock, J. (1974), Knowledge and Justification. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Schiffer, S. (1980), “Truth and the Theory of Content”, in Meaning and Understanding, Parret, H. and Bouveresse, J. (eds.). Berlin and New York: Gruyter, pp. 204–22.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1976a), “Propositions”, in Issues in the Philosophy of Language, Mackay, A. and Merrill, D. (eds.). New Haven: Yale University Press, pp. 197–214.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1976b), “Possible Worlds”, Noûs 10: 6575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1984), Inquiry. Cambridge: The MIT Press/A Bradford Book.Google Scholar
Stich, S. (1982), “On the Ascription of Content”, in Thought and Object, Woodfield, A. (ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 153–206.Google Scholar
Stich, S. (1983), From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: the Case Against Belief. Cambridge: The MIT Press/A Bradford Book.Google Scholar
Wagner, S. (1981), “Tonk”, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 22: 289–300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar