Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-sh8wx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-18T20:31:31.778Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Phenomenal Experiences, First-Person Methods, and the Artificiality of Experimental Data

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

While philosophical discussions of first-person methods often turn on the veridicality of first-person reports, I argue that more attention should be paid to the circumstances and aims of their experimental production in the science of perception. After pointing to the ‘constructedness’ of first-person reports, I raise questions about the criteria by which to judge whether they illuminate something about the nature of perception. I illustrate this point with a historical debate between Gestalt psychologists and atomists, both of whom used first-person methods to investigate perception, but who disagreed deeply over the epistemic value of their respective first-person data.

Type
Cognitive and Psychological Sciences
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

The author would like to thank audiences at the Tübingen Centre for Integrative Neuroscience (June 2012) and the PSA session “Introspective Evidence in the Scientific Study of Perception” (November 2012) for their feedback. I am especially grateful to Mazviita Chirimuuta for her helpful comments on two previous drafts.

References

Chirimuuta, Mazviita. 2014. “Psychophysical Methods and the Evasion of Introspection.” Philosophy of Science, in this issue.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feest, Uljana. 2012. “Introspection as a Method and Introspection as a Feature of Consciousness.” Inquiry 55 (1): 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feest, Uljana Forthcoming. “Quantifying Gestalt Qualities: Modernism and the Measurement of Experience.” In Science as Cultural Practice, Vol. 2, Modernism in the Sciences, ca. 1900–1940, ed. Moriz Epple and Falk Müller. Berlin: Akademie.Google Scholar
Hatfield, Gary. 2005. “Introspective Evidence in Psychology.” In Scientific Evidence: Philosophical Theories and Applications, ed. Achinstein, Peter, 259–86. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Achinstein, Peter 2014. “Psychological Experiments and Phenomenal Experience in Size and Shape Constancy.” Philosophy of Science, in this issue.Google Scholar
Koffka, Kurt. 1923. “Zu Theorie der Erlebniswahrnehmungen.” Annalen der Philosophie 3:375–99.Google Scholar
Köhler, Wolfgang. 1913/1913. “On Unnoticed Sensations and Errors of Judgment.” In The Selected Papers of Wolfgang Köhler, ed. Henle, Mary. Repr. New York: Liveright.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas. 1977. “Objectivity, Value Judgment, and Theory Choice.” In The Essential Tension, 320–39. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Piccinini, Gualtiero. 2009. “First-Person Data, Publicity and Self-Measurement.” Philosophers Imprint 9 (9): 116.Google Scholar
Robbins, Philip. 2006. “The Ins and Outs of Introspection.” Philosophy Compass 1:617–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schooler, Jonathan. 2002. “Re-presenting Consciousness: Dissociations between Experience and Metaconsciousness.” Trends in Cognitive Science 6 (8): 339–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwitzgebel, Eric. 2011. Perplexities of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tulodziecki, Dana. 2013. “Underdetermination, Methodological Practices, and Realism.” Synthese 190 (17): 3731–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wertheimer, Max. 1912. “Über das Sehen von Bewegungen.” Zeitschrift für Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnesorgane 61:161265.Google Scholar
Wundt, Wilhelm. 1907. “Über Ausfrageexperiments und über die Methoden der Psychologie des Denkens.” Psychologische Studien 3:301–60.Google Scholar