Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-m42fx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-22T05:52:23.070Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On the Nature and Use of Dialectic

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

Edward G. Ballard*
Affiliation:
Tulane University

Extract

Dialectic, like love, has a good and a bad reputation. This ambivalence may be illustrated in different ways in almost every period of philosophical history. One may even suspect that this richness borders upon confusion. And yet, the attempt to orientate oneself in this jungle of meanings can be expected to be profitable, for the term “dialectic” has always referred, although often obscurely, to notions and processes of the first importance. The definition, illustration, and evaluation of the uses of this term should, accordingly, be a task promising some value.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1955

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 This translation of the causal relation into the relation of material implication has not infrequently been expressed. Cf. J. M. Johnson, “Rival Principles of Explanation,” Psychological Review, 46, no. 6, Nov. 1939, p. 493 ff; and A. W. Burks, “The Logic of Causal Relations,” Mind, LX, 1951, pp. 363–382.

2 Cf. H. A. Simon, “On the Definition of the Causal Relation,” J. of Philos. XLIX, no. 16, July, 1952, 517–528.

3 Cf. H. M. Johnson, article cited.

4 Human Knowledge, N. Y., 1948, p. 468.

5 Many analogies of this sort between self-regulating machines and organisms, already evident in the terminology associated with Cybernetics, are developed and discussed by K. W. Deutsch, in “Mechanism, Organism, and Society,” Phil. of Science, 18, no. 3, July, 1951, pp. 230–252.

6 K. W. Deutsch, Op Cit. p. 243.