Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-r5zm4 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-05T14:24:55.367Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kurt Gödel and Phenomenology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Richard Tieszen*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, San Jose State University
*
Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, San Jose State University, One Washington Square, San Jose, CA 95192–0096, USA.

Abstract

Gödel began to seriously study Husserl's phenomenology in 1959, and the Gödel Nachlass is known to contain many notes on Husserl. In this paper I describe what is presently known about Gödel's interest in phenomenology. Among other things, it appears that the 1963 supplement to “What is Cantor's Continuum Hypothesis?”, which contains Gödel's famous views on mathematical intuition, may have been influenced by Husserl. I then show how Gödel's views on mathematical intuition and objectivity can be readily interpreted in a phenomenological theory of intuition and mathematical knowledge.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1992

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I would like to thank Hao Wang for comments, and for discussion and correspondence about Gödel's philosophical interests. I have also benefited from correspondence with Solomon Feferman, John Dawson, Jr., and Cheryl Dawson, and from comments by Lila Luce, Penelope Maddy, Pieranna Garavaso, Steven G. Crowell, J. N. Mohanty, Izchak Miller, and a referee for Philosophy of Science. Parts of this paper were presented to the 1989 Eastern Division meeting of the American Philosophical Association, to the 1989 Spring meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic, and to the Philosophy Department Colloquium at the University of Iowa. I thank members of those audiences for comments.

References

Benacerraf, P. and Putnam, H. (eds.) (1983), Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings. 2d ed. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Boolos, G. (1971), “The Iterative Conception of Set”, in Benacerraf, P. and Putnam, H. (eds.), Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 486529.Google Scholar
Feferman, S., et al. (eds.) (1986, 1990), Collected Works of Kurt Gödel, Vols. I and II. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Volume I was published in 1986, Volume II in 1990.Google Scholar
Gödel, K. (1961), “The Modern Development of the Foundations of Mathematics in the Light of Philosophy”, revision by J. Dawson of an unpublished transcription by H. Wang and E. Köhler. Firestone Library, Princeton University.Google Scholar
Gödel, K. ([1940] 1990), “The Consistency of the Axiom of Choice and of the Generalized Continuum Hypothesis with the Axioms of Set Theory”, in Feferman, S., et al. (eds.), S. Feferman, et al., vol. 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 33101.Google Scholar
Gödel, K. ([1944] 1990), “Russell's Mathematical Logic”, in Feferman, S., et al. (eds.), S. Feferman, et al., vol. 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 119141.Google Scholar
Gödel, K. ([1949] 1990a), “An Example of a New Type of Cosmological Solutions of Einstein's Field Equations of Gravitation”, in Feferman, S., et al. (eds.), S. Feferman, et al., vol. 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 190198.Google Scholar
Gödel, K. ([1949] 1990b), “A Remark about the Relationship between Relativity Theory and Idealistic Philosophy”, in Feferman, S., et al. (eds.), S. Feferman, et al., vol. 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 202207.Google Scholar
Gödel, K. ([1964] 1990), “What is Cantor's Continuum Problem?”, in Feferman, S., et al. (eds.), S. Feferman, et al., vol. 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 254270.Google Scholar
Gödel, K. ([1972] 1990), “On an Extension of Finitary Mathematics Which Has Not Yet Been Used”, in Feferman, S., et al. (eds.), S. Feferman, et al., vol. 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 271280.Google Scholar
Gödel, K. (n.d.), “Is Mathematics Syntax of Language?” in K. Gödel Nachlass. Firestone Library of Princeton University. Princeton, NJ.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. ([1911] 1965), “Philosophy as Rigorous Science”, Logos 1: 289341. English translation by Quentin Lauer published in 1965.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. ([1954] 1970), The Crisis of the European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology: An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy. Translated by D. Carr. (Originally published as Die Krisis der europaischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phänomenologie; eine Einleitung in die phänomenologische Philosophie.) The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. ([1939] 1973). Experience and Judgment: Investigations in a Genealogy of Logic. Translated by J. S. Churchill and K. Ameriks. (Originally published as Erfahrung und Urteil.) Hamburg: Claassen.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. ([1962] 1977). Phenomenological Psychology: Lectures, Summer Semester, 1925. Translated by J. Scanlon. (Originally published as Phänomenologische Psychologie. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.) The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. ([1913] 1983), Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. English translation by W. R. Boyce-Gibson published in 1931, and by F. Kersten published in 1983.Google Scholar
Kac, M.; Rota, G.; and Schartz, J. T. (1986), Discrete Thoughts: Essays on Mathematics, Science and Philosophy. Boston: Birkhaüser.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kreisel, G. (1980), “Kurt Gödel, 28 April 1906–14 January 1978”, Biographical Memoirs of Fellows of the Royal Society 26: 148224.Google Scholar
Maddy, P. (1980), “Perception and Mathematical Intuition”, Philosophical Review 89: 163196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pagels, H. (1988), The Dreams of Reason: The Computer and the Rise of the Sciences of Complexity. New York: Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
Parsons, C. (1983), Mathematics in Philosophy: Selected Essays. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Spiegelberg, H. (1971), The Phenomenological Movement: A Historical Introduction. 2d ed. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Smith, D. W. (1984), “Content and Context of Perception”, Synthese 61: 6187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tieszen, R. (1989), Mathematical Intuition: Phenomenology and Mathematical Knowledge. Boston: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wang, H. (1974), From Mathematics to Philosophy. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Wang, H. (1978), “Kurt Gödel's Intellectual Development”, The Mathematical Intelligencer 1: 182184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wang, H. (1981), “Some Facts about Kurt Gödel”, The Journal of Symbolic Logic 46: 653659.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wang, H. (1987), Reflections on Kurt Gödel. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar