Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-qlrfm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T22:14:18.274Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

“Securing the Rational Foundations of Human Living:” The Pedagogical Nature of Human Law in St. Thomas Aquinas

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2024

Brian Jones*
Affiliation:
University of St. Thomas, Philosophy, 3800 Montrose, Houston Texas, United States, 77006-4626, Houston, Texas

Abstract

Every form of government, whether by its action or inaction, encourages certain forms of behavior and discourages others. The moral well being of a society necessitates its consideration of civil law's legitimate role in shaping moral character. In this paper, I will attepmt to argue that the Thomistic account of civil law is not merely negative, but entails a positive pedagogy that seeks to nurture the moral virtue of its citizens, for both the viciously inclined and those who are already good. Furthermore, Aquinas’ theory of the common good is such that its role is not merely limited, i.e., through establishing some form of civic tranquility and providing basic goods of the material or economic order with little worry of the moral habits thus cultivated.

The treatment of Thomas’ teaching on human law will not be fully exhausted in this paper. However, from examining the texts from the Summa Theologiae and the De Regno, it will appear evident that St. Thomas has provided a concise and intelligent framework for seeing and actualizing the necessary relationship between human law and moral virtue.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2014 The Author. New Blackfriars

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aristotle. The Complete Works of Aristotle. Revised Oxford translation, 2 vols. Ed. Barnes, Jonathan. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984.Google Scholar
Brock, Stephen. “Legal Character of Natural Law According to Thomas Aquinas.” Ph.D diss., University of Toronto, 1988.Google Scholar
Brock, StephenNatural Inclination and the Intelligibility of the Good in Thomistic Natural Law.” Vera Lex, VI. 1–2 (Winter, 2005): 5778.Google Scholar
Brown, Benjamin J.The Integration of Law and Virtue: Obedience in Aquinas’ Moral Theology.” Irish Theological Quarterly 67 (2002): 333–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Budziszewski, J.Playing Dumb: The Natural Consequences of Violating the Natural Law.” American Journal of Jurisprudence 44 (1999): 7588.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carl, Maria. “Law, Virtue, and Happiness in Aquinas’ Moral Theory.” Thomist 61 (1997): 425448.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cotta, Sergio. “Positive Law and Natural Law.” The Review of Metaphysics 37, no. 2 (1983): 265–85.Google Scholar
Degnan, Daniel A.Two Models of Positive Law in Aquinas: A Study of the Relationship of Positive Law and Natural Law.” Thomist 46 (1982): 132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dewan, Lawrence. “St. Thomas, Our Natural Lights, and the Moral Order.” Angelicum 67 (1990): 285307.Google Scholar
Di Blasi, Fulvio. “Natural Law as Inclination to God.” Nova et Vetera, Eng. Edition, Vol. 7, No. 2 (2009): 327–60.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1977.Google Scholar
Flippen, Douglas. “Natural Law and Natural Inclinations.” The New Scholasticism 60, no. 3 (1986): 284316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, H.L.A. The Concept of Law. 2nd ed. New York: Oxford Univ. Press, 1994.Google Scholar
Hibbs, Thomas. “The Pedagogy of Law and Virtue in the Summa Theologiae,’’ Ph.D diss., University of Notre Dame, 1987.Google Scholar
Hittinger, Russell. “Liberalism and the American Natural Law Tradition.” Wake Forest Law Review 25, no. 3 (1990): 429499.Google Scholar
Hittinger, RussellNatural Law in the Positive Laws: A Legislative or Adjudicative Issue?” The Review of Politics 55, no. 1 (Winter, 1993): 534.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, John. The Second Treatise of Government, ed. Laslett, Peter. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, New American Library edition, 1965.Google Scholar
Lewis, John U.The Power of Law: Mill, Devlin, and Aquinas on the Relation between Law and Morality.” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 53 (1979): 141–49.Google Scholar
Keys, Mary. “Aquinas’ Two Pedagogies: A Reconsideration of the Relation between Law and Moral Virtue.” American Journal of Political Science 45, no. 3 (2001): 519531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacCormick, Neil. “Natural Law and the Separation of Law and Morals.” In Natural Law Theory, edited by George, Robert P., 105–33. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992.Google Scholar
MacIntryre, Alasdair. After Virtue. 2nd ed. Notre Dame: Univ. of Notre Dame Press, 1984.Google Scholar
Maritain, Jacques. Natural Law: Reflections on Theory and Practice, edited by Sweet, William, 4347. South Bend: St. Augustine's Press, 2001.Google Scholar
McCoy, Charles N. R.St. Thomas and Political Science.” In On the Intelligibility of Political Philosophy: Essays of Charles N. R. McCoy, edited by Schall, James V. and Schrems, John J., 2438. Washington, D. C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1989.Google Scholar
McInerny, Ralph. “The Case for Natural Law.” Modern Age (Spring, 1982): 168–74.Google Scholar
McInerny, RalphThe Principles of Natural Law,” in Readings in Moral theology: Natural Law and Theology, no. 7, edited by Curran, Charles E. and McCormick, Richard A., S.J. New York: Paulist Press, 1991.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. “On Liberty.” In Essays on Politics and Society, edited by Robinson, J.M., 276310. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1977.Google Scholar
Pakaluk, Michael. “Is The Common Good of Political Society Limited and Instrumental?” The Review of Metaphysics 55 (2001): 5794.Google Scholar
Porter, Jean. Nature as Reason. A Thomistic Theory of Natural Law. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 2005.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press, 1993.Google Scholar
Schall, James V.The Totality of Society: From Justice to Friendship.” In The Mind That is Catholic: Philosophical and Political Essays. Washington, D.C: Catholic University of America Press, 2008): 114127.Google Scholar
Simon, Yves. Philosophy of Democratic Government. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1951.Google Scholar
Simon, Yves A General Theory of Authority. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1962.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles. “Justice After Virtue.” In After MacIntyre, edited by Horton, John and Mendus, Susan. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1994.Google Scholar
Thomas Aquinas, St. De Regno. Translated by Phelan, G.B.. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1949.Google Scholar
Thomas Aquinas, St. Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita, t. 42: De regno ad regem Cypri. Editori di San Tommaso, Roma, 1979.Google Scholar
Thomas Aquinas, St. Opera omnia iussu impensaque Leonis XIII P. M. edita, t. 6–7: Prima secundae Summae theologiae. Ex Typographia Polyglotta S. C. de Propaganda Fide, Romae, 1891–1892.Google Scholar
Thomas Aquinas, St. Treatise on Law: The Complete Text. Translated by Freddoso, Alfred. South Bend: St. Augustine's Press, 2009.Google Scholar
Tonneau, Jean. “The Teaching of the Thomist Tract on Law.” Thomist 34 (1970): 1383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolfe, Christopher. “Can (and Should) We Legislate Morality?” Paper presented at the Ralph McInerny Center for Thomistic Studies, Washington, D.C., 2009.Google Scholar