Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wzw2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-13T04:02:51.943Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Early Jewish Reception of Kantian Philosophy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 October 2020

Ian Hunter*
Affiliation:
Institute for Advanced Studies in the Humanities, University of Queensland
*
*Corresponding author. E-mail: i.hunter@uq.edu.au

Abstract

Current discussions of the early Jewish reception of Kantian philosophy are dominated by two major approaches. According to the first, this reception was governed by a universal Enlightenment rationalism that was present in Judaism no less than in Kantian philosophy. According to the second, it was the fact that Kantianism contained a latent Judaic kabbalistic philosophy that made it attractive to Jewish intellectuals. This paper departs from both approaches by showing that when Jewish intellectuals encountered Kantianism they found neither a universal rationality to which Judaism should conform, nor an esoteric Jewish metaphysics to which Kantian philosophy had already conformed, but something else entirely, namely a hostile philosophical religion that sought to reconstruct Judaism in its own image. As a result of the historical context in which this challenge arose, some Jewish intellectuals accepted this reconstruction as a rational reform, while others repudiated it as a Christian-rationalist assault on Jewish law and tradition. Characterized first by the absence of a defensive Jewish Schulmetaphysik that might combat Kantianism on its own grounds, and second by the preparedness of enlightened intellectuals to extort Jewish acceptance of Christian rationalism by withholding citizenship rights, this context made Kantian philosophy into an offer that was difficult for Jewish intellectuals to refuse, or accept.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 See the important studies by Sorkin, David, The Religious Enlightenment: Protestants, Jews, and Catholics from London to Vienna (Princeton, 2008), 121CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Sorkin, , The Berlin Haskalah and German Religious Thought: Orphans of Knowledge (London, 2000), 1362Google Scholar. See also Feiner, Shmuel, The Jewish Enlightenment, trans. Naor, C. (Philadelphia, 2004), 117CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For a different approach see Breuer, Edward, “Enlightenment and Haskalah,” in Karp, J. and Sutcliffe, A. eds., The Cambridge History of Judaism, vol. 7, The Early Modern World, 1500–1815 (Cambridge, 2017), 652–76Google Scholar. Breuer argues that the Haskalah should be seen as a series of local north German cultural interactions in which Jewish intellectuals responded to Protestant philosophical rationalism through initiatives designed to renew Hebrew language and literature, provide a properly Judaic German translation of the Hebrew Bible, and resist pressure for a Christian-rationalist reform of Judaism,

2 See Schulte, Christoph, Die jüdische Aufklärung: Philosophie, Religion, Geschichte (Munich, 2002), 68–69, 157–71Google Scholar. Schulte, , “Saul Ascher's Leviathan, or the Invention of Jewish Orthodoxy in 1792,” Leo Baeck Institute Yearbook 45/1 (2000), 2534CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Wood, Allen W., Kant and Religion (Cambridge, 2020), 185–209CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Guyer, Paul, Reason and Experience in Mendelssohn and Kant (Oxford, 2020), 276301CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 Habermas, Jürgen, “The German Idealism of the Jewish Philosophers,” in Habermas, Religion and Rationality: Essays on Reason, God, and Modernity (Cambridge MA, 2002), 3759Google Scholar.

4 Franks, Paul W., “Jewish Philosophy after Kant: The Legacy of Salomon Maimon,” in Morgan, M. and Gordon, P. E., eds., The Cambridge Companion to Modern Jewish Philosophy (Cambridge, 2007), 5379CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Franks, , “Inner Anti-Semitism or Kabbalistic Legacy? German Idealism's Relationship to Judaism,” in Rush, F., Stolzenberg, J., and Franks, P., eds., Yearbook of German Idealism, vol. 7, Faith and Reason (Berlin, 2010), 254–79Google Scholar. Franks, , “Rabbinic Idealism and Kabbalistic Realism: Jewish Dimensions of Idealism and Idealist Dimensions of Judaism,” in Adams, N., ed., The Impact of Idealism: The Legacy of Post-Kantian German Thought, vol. 4, Religion (Cambridge, 2013), 219–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 In Franks's account this lost metaphysics originates in a Lurianic or midrashic Kabbalah and is focused in the depiction of the universe emerging from the contraction of an infinite divinity to some kind of point or finite space, in order to be encompassed within the temple and other holy spaces and objects. According to Franks, this metaphysics supports a dialogical morality in which the contracted divine self, through negation, makes room for another self, giving rise to a Kantian-idealist metaphysics of morals based on mutual recognition and respect. See Franks, “Inner Anti-Semitism or Kabbalistic Legacy?”, 269–275.

6 For a sceptical discussion see Mack, Michael, German Idealism and the Jew: The Inner Anti-Semitism of German Philosophy and some Jewish Responses (Chicago, 2003), 2341CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 See Sparn, Walter, “Vernünftiges Christentum: Über die geschichtliche Aufgabe der theologischen Aufklärung im 18. Jahrhundert in Deutschland,” in Vierhaus, R., ed., Wissenschaften im Zeitalter der Aufklärung (Göttingen, 1985), 1857Google Scholar.

8 See Altmann, Alexander, Moses Mendelssohn: A Biographical Study (Oxford, 1984), 603–37Google Scholar.

9 Hunter, Ian, “Kant's Religion and Prussian Religious Policy,” Modern Intellectual History 2/1 (2005), 127CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 See Karl Aner, Die Theologie der Lessingzeit (Halle, 1929). Cf. also Beutel, Albrecht, Kirchengeschichte im Zeitalter der Aufklärung: Ein Kompendium (Göttingen, 2009), 112–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

11 See, for example, Häfner, Ralph, “Das Menschengeschlecht im Zeitalter des Heiligen Geistes: Eine Hypothese zu Ursprung und Gestalt von Lessings Anthropologie,” in Bultmann, C. and Vollhardt, F., eds., Gotthold Ephraim Lessings Religionsphilosophie im Kontext: Hamburger Fragmente und Wolfenbütteler Axiomata (Berlin, 2011), 126–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

12 Mulsow, Martin, Enlightenment Underground: Radical Germany, 1680–1720 (Charlottesville, 2015), 175205Google Scholar. Dietrich Klein, “Aus lauter dunkelen Begriffen der Kabbalisten und Platonisch Juden …: Herman Samuel Reimarus als Ausleger des Johannesprologs,” in Bultmann and Vollhardt, Gotthold Ephraim Lessings Religionsphilosophie, 73–87.

13 See Kant, Immanuel, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Pluhar, Werner S. (Indianapolis, 1996), A568–642/B596–670Google Scholar.

14 See Kant, Immanuel, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, in Immanuel Kant: Practical Philosophy, ed. and trans. Gregor, M. J. (Cambridge, 1996), 4960CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Kant, Immanuel, Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, in Kants Gesammelte Schriften (Berlin, 1902–), 4: 393–405Google Scholar. The Akademie edition of Kant's Gesammelte Schriften will hereafter by cited as AA, followed by volume and page numbers.

15 For evidence of Kant's familiarity with Lutheran metaphysical constructions of divine and human nature see the passages on these topics in Kant's metaphysics Nachlass, all dating from the 1780s. See AA 18: §6041, 431–2; §§6051–63, 438–41; §§6071–4, 442–3. For commentary on the manner in which Protestant Schulmetaphysik informs Kant's construction of subjectivity and divinity see Kanterian, Edward, Kant, God and Metaphysics: The Secret Thorn (London and New York, 2018), 345–97Google Scholar. For important papers identifying Abraham Calov as a key point of transmission between seventeenth-century Lutheran metaphysics, the teaching of metaphysics at eighteenth-century Königsberg, and Kant's conception of transcendental philosophy see Sgarbi, Marco, “Metaphysics in Königsberg Prior to Kant (1703–1770),” Trans/Form/Ação 33/1 (2010), 3164CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Sgarbi, , “The Historical Genesis of the Kantian Concept of ‘Transcendental’,” Archiv für Begriffsgeschichte 53 (2011), 97117Google Scholar.

16 For the seventeenth-century metaphysical architecture and debates see Sparn, Walter, Wiederkehr der Metaphysik: Die ontologische Frage in der lutherischen Theologie des frühen 17. Jahrhunderts (Stuttgart, 1976), 3661Google Scholar. See also Haga, Joar, Was There a Lutheran Metaphysics? The Interpretation of Communicatio Idiomatum in Early Modern Lutheranism (Göttingen, 2012), 2190CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 See Cross, Richard, Communicatio Idiomatum: Reformation Christological Debates (Oxford, 2019), 189225CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

18 See Sparn, Walter, “Kant's Doctrine of Atonement as a Theory of Subjectivity,” in Rossi, P. J. and Wreen, M., eds., Kant's Philosophy of Religion Reconsidered (Indianapolis, 1991), 103–12Google Scholar.

19 Kant, Groundwork, 66–7; AA 4: 413–14.

20 Kant, Immanuel, Opus postumum, ed. Förster, Eckart, trans. Förster, Eckart and Rosen, Michael (Cambridge, 1993), 229–30CrossRefGoogle Scholar (translation modified); AA 21: 25.

21 See Sparn, “Kant's Doctrine of Atonement.” See also Hunter, Ian, “The Morals of Metaphysics: Kant's Groundwork as Intellectual Paideia,” Critical Inquiry 28 (2002), 908–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

22 Kant, Immanuel, Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason, trans. Pluhar, Werner S. (Indianapolis, 2009), 12Google Scholar; AA 6: 3–4.

23 Immanuel Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, in Immanuel Kant: Practical Philosophy, 206; AA 5: 82, original emphasis.

24 Kant, Religion, 31–50; AA 6: 28–44.

25 Kant, Religion, 74–87; AA 6: 66–78.

26 Kant, Religion, 66–8, 80–87, 142–3; AA 6: 60–62, 70–78, 128–9.

27 Kant, Religion, 185–205; AA 6: 167–85.

28 Kant, Religion, 138–41; AA 6: 124–7.

29 Kant, Immanuel, The Conflict of the Faculties, in Wood, A. W. and di Giovanni, G., eds., Religion and Rational Theology (Cambridge, 1996), 233–328, at 275–6CrossRefGoogle Scholar; AA 7: 53.

30 Kant, Religion, 113–19; AA 6: 103–9.

31 Kant, Religion, 120–27; AA 6: 109–14.

32 Kant, Religion, 118; AA 6: 107–8. See also, Kant, Conflict of the Faculties, 276; AA 7: 53.

33 Sorkin, Religious Enlightenment, 169–72.

34 For a brief but informative overview see Schindling, Anton, “Schulen und Universitäten im 16. und 17. Jahrhundert: Zehn Thesen zu Bildungsexpansion, Laienbildung und Konfessionalisierung nach der Reformation,” in Brandmüller, W., Immenkötter, H., and Iserloh, E., eds., Ecclesia Militans: Studia zur Konzilien- und Reformationsgeschichte Remigius Bäumer zum 70. Geburtstag gewidmet (Paderborn, 1988), 561–70Google Scholar.

35 For indispensable surveys of the building of rival scholasticisms in defence of antagonistic confessional religions see Blum, Paul Richard, “Grundzüge der katholischen Schulphilosophie,” in Holzhey, H. and Schmidt-Biggemann, W., eds., Die Philosophie des 17. Jahrhunderts, vol. 4, Das heilige Römische Reich deutscher Nation, Nord- und Ostmitteleuropa (Basle, 2001), 302–30Google Scholar. Wilhelm Schmidt-Biggemann and Wolfgang Rother, “Die Schulphilosophie in den reformierten Territorien,” in Holzhey and Schmidt-Biggemann, Die Philosophie des 17. Jahrhunderts, 392–474; and Walter Sparn, “Die Schulphilosophie in den lutherischen Territorien,” in Holzhey and Schmidt-Biggemann, Die Philosophie des 17. Jahrhunderts, 475–97.

36 Schwarz, Yossef, “Kabbalah and Conversion: Caramuel and Ciantes on Kabbalah as a Means for the Conversion of the Jews,” in Sabaino, D. and Pissavino, P. C., eds., Un'altra modernità. Juan Caramuel Lobkowitz (1606–1682): enciclopedia e probabilismo (Pisa, 2012), 175–88Google Scholar.

37 Mulsow, Martin, “A German Spinozistic Reader of Cudworth, Bull, and Spencer: Johann Georg Wachter and His Theologia Martyrum (1712),” in Ligota, C. R. and Quantin, J.-L., eds., History of Scholarship (Oxford, 2006), 357–83Google Scholar.

38 Mulsow, Martin, “Bisterfields ‘Cabala’,” in Mulsow, ed., Spätrenaissance-Philosophie in Deutschland 1570–1650/Late Renaissance Philosophy in Germany 1570–1650 (Berlin, 2007), 1142Google Scholar.

39 For an indispensable overview see Levitin, Dmitri, “From Sacred History to the History of Religion: Paganism, Judaism, and Christianity in European Historiography from Reformation to ‘Enlightenment’,” Historical Journal 55 (2012), 1117–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

40 See Schulte, Marion, Über die bürgerlichen Verhältnisse der Juden in Preussen: Ziele und Motive der Reformzeit (1787–1812) (Berlin, 2014), 398476Google Scholar.

41 For an illuminating discussion in these terms see Rose, Sven-Erik, Jewish Philosophical Politics in Germany, 1789–1848 (Waltham, MA, 2014)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Navon, Ephraim, “The Encounter of German Idealists and Jewish Enlighteners: 1760–1800,” Jahrbuch des Instituts für Deutsche Geschichte 3 (1980), 225–41Google Scholar.

42 Maimon, Salomon, Essay on Transcendental Philosophy, trans. Somers-Hall, H., Welchman, A., and Reglitz, M. (London, 2010), 11–18, 3543Google Scholar.

43 Ibid., 89.

44 Bendavid, Lazarus, Vorlesungen über die Critik der Practischen Vernunft: Nebst einer Rede über den Zweck der critischen Philosophie, und doppletem Register (Vienna, 1796), 111Google Scholar.

45 Ibid., 11–19.

46 Ibid., 19–25.

47 Ibid., 25–30.

48 Kant, Conflict of the Faculties, 275; AA 7: 53.

49 Bendavid, Lazarus, Etwas zur Characteristick der Juden (Leipzig, 1793), 45Google Scholar.

50 Cf. Rose, Jewish Philosophical Politics, 14–43.

51 For an illuminating overview of Mendelssohn's many-sided contributions to Berlin-centered cultural, political, and religious discussions see Sorkin, Religious Enlightenment, 165–214. And for a remarkable study of Mendelssohn's life and works see Altmann, Moses Mendelssohn. For philosophical discussions of Mendelssohn's writings see Gottlieb, Michah, Faith and Freedom: Moses Mendelssohn's Theological–Political Thought (Oxford, 2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Guyer, Reason and Experience.

52 For a rich reading of Jerusalem in these terms see Altmann, Moses Mendelssohn, 514–52.

53 For some recent examples see Guyer, Reason and Experience, 276–301. Gottlieb, Faith and Freedom, 31–58. Wood, Kant and Religion, 190–209.

54 Cf. Mendelssohn's comment: “To be sure, I am a great admirer of demonstrations in metaphysics … But nevertheless my conviction in the truth of the tenets of [natural] religion is not so entirely dependent upon metaphysical arguments that it is compelled to stand or fall with them.” Mendelssohn, Moses, “To the Friends of Lessing (1786),” in Moses Mendelssohn: Last Works (Urbana, 2012), 139–76, at 157Google Scholar.

55 For a similar approach to Jerusalem see David Sorkin, Moses Mendelssohn and the Religious Enlightenment (Berkeley, 1996), Ch. 9. See also Breuer, “Enlightenment and Haskalah,” 665–9.

56 Mendelssohn, Moses, Jerusalem, or On Religious Power and Judaism, trans. Arkush, Allan, commentary Alexander Altmann (Hanover, 1983), 3145Google Scholar.

57 As claimed in Wood, Kant and Religion, 197–9.

58 Mendelssohn, Jerusalem, 40.

59 Ibid., 129.

60 Ibid., 56–66, 69–70, 79.

61 This dilemma was formulated most forcefully in the anonymously published Das Forschen nach Licht und Recht in einem Schreiben an Herrn Moses Mendelssohn auf Veranlassung seiner merkwürdigen Vorrede zu Manasseh Ben Israel (Berlin, 1782), written by August Friedrich Cranz. The same argument was repeated in “enlightened” works by Johann Friedrich Zöllner, Ueber Moses Mendelssohn's Jerusalem (Berlin, 1784), 148–79; and Schulz, Johann Heinrich, Der entlarvte Moses Mendelssohn (Amsterdam, 1786)Google Scholar.

62 Mendelssohn, Jerusalem, 93–4.

63 Ibid., 126–7.

64 As mistakenly claimed in Wood, Kant and Religion, 200; and in Guyer, Reason and Experience, 21–2, 288.

65 Mendelssohn, Jerusalem, 98–9, 127–8.

66 Ibid., 89–90, original emphasis. This conception of the two separate divine paths or dispensations was something that Mendelssohn maintained in his final works. See Mendelssohn, “To the Friends of Lessing,” 156–8.

67 Somewhat surprisingly, modern commentators continue to interpret Mendelssohn in this manner, ignoring his account of the two distinct paths to God, and claiming that Mendelssohn views the revealed positive laws of Judaism as grounded in an underlying universal rational religion. See, for example, Guyer, Reason and Experience, 287–9, 293. Gottlieb, Faith and Freedom, 46–8, 56–8. See also Beiser, Frederick C., The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte (Cambridge, MA, 1987), 92108CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

68 In a letter written in August 1783, in the course of congratulating Mendelssohn on his defence of freedom of conscience in Jerusalem, Kant demonstrates his obliviousness to this crucial point by presuming that, like him, Mendelssohn also views historical scriptural revelation as inimical to this freedom: “For all religious propositions that burden our conscience are based on history; that is, on making salvation contingent on belief in the truth of those historical propositions.” Kant, Immanuel, Correspondence, trans. Zweig, A. (Cambridge, 1999), 204CrossRefGoogle Scholar; AA 10: 347.

69 Kant, Religion, 138–41; AA 6: 125–7.

70 Mendelssohn, Jerusalem, 66–8, 126–8. For a lucid exposition of this crucial feature of Mendelssohn's understanding of Judaism, see Sorkin, Moses Mendelssohn, Ch. 9.

71 Mendelssohn, Jerusalem, 97–8.

72 Ibid., 99–127.

73 Ibid., 129.

74 Ibid., 130.

75 Ibid., 134–5.

76 Kant, Religion, 138–51; AA 6: 125–37.

77 See Altmann, Moses Mendelssohn, 539–43.

78 Mendelssohn, Jerusalem, 95–7.

79 For Kant's censure see the remarks subtitled “Against Moses Mendelssohn” in Immanuel Kant, “On the Common Saying: That May Be Correct in Theory, but It Is of No Use in Practice,” in Immanuel Kant: Practical Philosophy, 304–6; AA 8: 307–8.

80 Mendelssohn, Jerusalem, 138. Cf. Altmann, Moses Mendelssohn, 550–52.

81 For readings of Ascher as a Kantian see Schulte, Die jüdische Aufklärung, 68–9, 184–98. Hiscott, William, Saul Ascher: Berliner Aufklärer. Eine philosophiehistorische Darstellung (Hanover, 2017)Google Scholar. See also the important early anglophone discussion of Ascher in Hess, Jonathan M., Germans, Jews and the Claims of Modernity (New Haven, 2002), 136–67Google Scholar.

82 For this view of Ascher see Schweid, Eliezer, A History of Modern Jewish Religious Philosophy, vol. 1, The Period of the Enlightenment, trans. Levin, Leonard (Leiden, 2011), 205–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

83 Cf. Schulte's claims that “Ascher's Leviathan is the first Kantian philosophy of Judaism,” and that Ascher can be regarded as a forerunner of Reform Judaism. See Schulte, Die jüdische Aufklärung, 184. Similarly Schulte, “Saul Ascher's Leviathan,” 25–6. For a more nuanced discussion of this question see Fischer, Bernd, Ein anderer Blick: Saul Aschers politische Schriften (Vienna, 2016), 2952CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

84 Ascher, Saul, Leviathan oder Ueber Religion in Rücksicht des Judenthums (1792), in Saul Ascher Ausgewählte Werke, ed. Best, R. (Cologne, 2010), 94–182, at 100CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

85 Ibid., 102–3.

86 Ibid., 103–6.

87 Ibid., 106–9. It should already be clear that, despite the borrowed nomenclature, Ascher's distinction between “regulative” and “constitutive” religions is only analogically related to Kant's use of the terms to signify, respectively, the use of reason to govern the understanding, and the use of the understanding to constitute objects of cognition.

88 Ibid., 128–31.

89 As claimed by Schulte, Die jüdische Aufklärung, 68–70.

90 Ascher, Leviathan, 132–4.

91 Ibid., 134–8.

92 Ibid., 139–45.

93 Ibid., 164–5.

94 Ibid., 165.

95 Ibid., 176–7.

96 Ibid., 178–9.

97 Ibid., 179–80.

98 Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, Attempt at a Critique of All Revelation, ed. Wood, A. W., trans. Green, G., 2nd edn (Cambridge, 1978)Google Scholar.

99 Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, Beitrag zur Berichtigung der Urtheile des Publikums über die französische Revolution. Erster Theil: Zur Beurtheilung ihrer Rechtmässigkeit (1793/4), in Johann Gottlieb Fichte Werke 1791–1794, vol. 1, ed. Lauth, R. and Jacob, H. (Stuttgart and Bad Cannstatt, 1964), 193404Google Scholar.

100 Ibid., 290–92.

101 Ascher, Saul, Eisenmenger der Zweite, nebst einem vorangesetzen Sendschrieben an den Herrn Professor Fichte in Jena (Berlin, 1794), 12Google Scholar.

102 Kant, Immanuel, Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der bloßen Vernunft (Königsberg, 1793), 176–80Google Scholar; AA 6: 125–7.

103 Fichte, Critique, 69–73.

104 Ibid., 108–14.

105 Fichte, Beitrag, 292–4.

106 See Rose, Sven-Erik, “Lazarus Bendavid's and J. G. Fichte's Kantian Fantasies of Jewish Decapitation in 1793,” Jewish Social Studies 13 (2007), 73102Google Scholar.

107 Ascher, Eisenmenger, 6–7.

108 Ibid., 44–5.

109 Ibid., 46–8.

110 Ibid., 50.

111 Ibid., 52.

112 For an insightful commentary on Ascher's exposé of Kant's and Fichte's disguised Christian particularism see Hess, Germans, Jews, 137–67. The account presented in the present article differs from Hess's principally in that Hess thinks that Ascher was a Kantian—in fact a better Kantian than Kant. He thus treats Ascher's criticism of Kantian particularism as grounded in a nascent moral universalism, rather than in an anthropological and constitutional pluralism, as argued here.

113 Ascher, Eisenmenger, 53–5.

114 Ibid., 57–9.

115 Ibid., 62–4.

116 Ibid., 67.

117 On this scholarship see Grafton, Anthony, “Christianity's Jewish Origins Rediscovered: The Roles of Comparison in Early Modern Ecclesiastical Scholarship,” Erudition and the Republic of Letters 1 (2016), 1342CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

118 Ascher, Eisenmenger, 68.

119 Ibid., 70–71.

120 Ibid., 73–7.

121 Ibid., 78–9.

122 Ascher, Saul, Die Germanomanie: Skizze zu einem Zeitgemälde (Berlin, 1815), 714Google Scholar.

123 Ibid., 29–40.

124 Ibid., 47–54. See the remarkable account of this milieu by Williamson, George S., “What Killed August von Kotzebue? The Temptations of Virtue and the Political Theology of German Nationalism, 1789–1819,” Journal of Modern History 72 (2000), 890943CrossRefGoogle Scholar.