Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c4f8m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-20T02:17:13.077Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A proof of completeness for continuous first-order logic

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

Itaï Ben Yaacov
Affiliation:
Université Claude Bernard- Lyon 1, Institut Camille Jordan, UMR 5208 CNRS, 43 Boulevard DU 11 Novembre 1918, 69622 Villeurbanne Cedex, France, URL: http://math.univ-lyon1.fr/~begnac
Arthur Paul Pedersen
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, PA 15213, USA, E-mail: paulpedersen@cmu.edu URL: http://andrew.cmu.edu/~ppederse

Abstract

Continuous first-order logic has found interest among model theorists who wish to extend the classical analysis of “algebraic” structures (such as fields, group, and graphs) to various natural classes of complete metric structures (such as probability algebras, Hilbert spaces, and Banach spaces). With research in continuous first-order logic preoccupied with studying the model theory of this framework, we find a natural question calls for attention. Is there an interesting set of axioms yielding a completeness result?

The primary purpose of this article is to show that a certain, interesting set of axioms does indeed yield a completeness result for continuous first-order logic. In particular, we show that in continuous first-order logic a set of formulae is (completely) satisfiable if (and only if) it is consistent. From this result it follows that continuous first-order logic also satisfies an approximated form of strong completeness, whereby Σ⊧φ (if and) only if Σ⊢φ ∸2−n for all n < ω. This approximated form of strong completeness asserts that if Σ⊧φ, then proofs from Σ, being finite, can provide arbitrarily better approximations of the truth of φ.

Additionally, we consider a different kind of question traditionally arising in model theory—that of decidability. When is the set of all consequences of a theory (in a countable, recursive language) recursive? Say that a complete theory T is decidable if for every sentence φ, the value φT is a recursive real, and moreover, uniformly computable from φ. If T is incomplete, we say it is decidable if for every sentence φ the real number φTo is uniformly recursive from φ, where φTo is the maximal value of φ consistent with T. As in classical first-order logic, it follows from the completeness theorem of continuous first-order logic that if a complete theory admits a recursive (or even recursively enumerable) axiomatization then it is decidable.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

[BC63] Belluce, L. P. and Chang, C. C., A weak completeness theorem for infinite valued first-order logic, this Journal, vol. 28 (1963), no. 1, pp. 4350.Google Scholar
[Ben03a] Yaacov, Itaï Ben, Positive model theory and compact abstract theories, Journal of Mathematical Logic, vol. 3 (2003), no. 1, pp. 85118.Google Scholar
[Ben03b] Yaacov, Itai Ben, Simplicity in compact abstract theories, Journal of Mathematical Logic, vol. 3 (2003), no. 2, pp. 163191.Google Scholar
[Ben05] Yaacov, Itaï Ben, Uncountable dense categoricity in cats, this Journal, vol. 70 (2005), no. 3, pp. 829860.Google Scholar
[Ben] Yaacov, Itai Ben, On theories of random variables, in preparation.Google Scholar
[BBHU08] Yaacov, Itaï Ben, Berenstein, Alexander, Henson, C. Ward, and Usvyatsov, Alexander, Model theory for metric structures, Model theory with applications to algebra and analysis. Vol. 2 (Chatzidakis, Zoé, Macpherson, Dugald, Pillay, Anand, and Wilkie, Alex, editors), London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series, vol. 350, Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, 2008, pp. 315427.Google Scholar
[BU] Yaacov, Itaï Ben and Usvyatsov, Alexander, Continuous first order logic and local stability, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, to appear.Google Scholar
[Cha58] Chang, C. C., Proof of an axiom of łukasiewicz, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 87 (1958), pp. 5556.Google Scholar
[Cha59] Chang, C. C., A new proof of the completeness of the lukasiewicz axioms, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 93 (1959), pp. 7480.Google Scholar
[CK66] Chang, C. C. and Keisler, H. Jerome, Continuous model theory, Princeton Univ. Press, 1966.Google Scholar
[CDM00] Cignoli, Roberto L. O., d'Ottaviano, Itala M. L., and Mundici, Daniele, Algebraic foundations of many-valued reasoning, Trends in Logic—Studia Logica Library, vol. 7, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, 2000.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[EFT94] Ebbinghaus, H.-D., Flum, J., and Thomas, W., Mathematical logic, second ed., Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1994, Translated from the German by Margit Meßmer.Google Scholar
[EndOl] Enderton, Herbert B., A mathematical introduction to logic, second ed., Harcourt/Academic Press, Burlington, MA, 2001.Google Scholar
[Háj98] Hájek, Petr, Metamathematics of fuzzy logic, Trends in Logic—Studia Logica Library, vol. 4, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, 1998.Google Scholar
[Hay63] Hay, Louise Schmir, Axiomatization of the infinite-valued predicate calculus, this Journal, vol. 28 (1963), no. 1, pp. 7786.Google Scholar
[Hen76] Henson, C. Ward, Nonstandard hulls of Banach spaces, Israel Journal of Mathematics, vol. 25 (1976), pp. 108144.Google Scholar
[Pav79] Pavelka, Jan, On fuzzy logic. I, II and III, Zeitschrift für Mathemattsche Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, vol. 25 (1979), no. 5, pp. 45–52, 119–134, 4474642.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[RR58] Rose, Alan and Rosser, J. Barkley, Fragments of many-valued statement calculi, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 87 (1958), pp. 153.Google Scholar