Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-gvh9x Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-17T01:52:29.810Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Finite Axiomatizability using additional predicates

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

W. Craig
Affiliation:
University of Notre Dame and Pennsylvania State University
R. L. Vaught
Affiliation:
University of Amsterdam and University of Washington

Extract

By a theory we shall always mean one of first order, having finitely many non-logical constants. Then for theories with identity (as a logical constant, the theory being closed under deduction in first-order logic with identity), and also likewise for theories without identity, one may distinguish the following three notions of axiomatizability. First, a theory may be recursively axiomatizable, or, as we shall say, simply, axiomatizable. Second, a theory may be finitely axiomatizable using additional predicates (f. a.+), in the syntactical sense introduced by Kleene [9]. Finally, the italicized phrase may also be interpreted semantically. The resulting notion will be called s. f. a.+. It is closely related to the modeltheoretic notion PC introduced by Tarski [16], or rather, more strictly speaking, to PCACδ.

For arbitrary theories with or without identity, it is easily seen that s. f. a.+ implies f. a.+ and it is known that f. a.+ implies axiomatizability. Thus it is natural to ask under what conditions the converse implications hold, since then the notions concerned coincide and one can pass from one to the other.

Kleene [9] has shown: (1) For arbitrary theories without identity, axiomatizability implies f. a.+. It also follows from his work that : (2) For theories with identity which have only infinite models, axiomatizability implies f. a.+.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1958

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

[1]Asser, G., Das Repräsentantenproblem im Prädikatenkalkül der ersten Stufe mit Identität, Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, vol. 1 (1955), pp. 252263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[2]Church, A., Introduction to mathematical logic, vol. 1, Princeton (Princeton Univ. Press), 1956.Google Scholar
[3]Craig, W., On axiomatizability within a system, this Journal, vol. 18 (1953), pp. 3032.Google Scholar
[4]Craig, W., Further remarks on finite axiomatizability using additional predicates, Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 62 (1956), p. 411.Google Scholar
[5]Ehrenfeucht, A., Two theories with axioms built by means of pleonasms, this Journal, vol. 22 (1957), pp. 3638.Google Scholar
[6]Gödel, K., Die Vollständigkeit des logischen Funktionenkalküls, Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik, vol. 37 (1930), pp. 349360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[7]Henkin, L., On a theorem of Vaught, Indagationes mathematicae, vol. 17 (1955), pp. 326328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[8]Kleene, S. C., Introduction to metamathematics, Amsterdam (North Holland) Groningen (Noordhoff), New York and Toronto (Van Nostrand), 1952.Google Scholar
[9]Kleene, S. C., Finite axiomatizability of theories in the predicate calculus using additional predicate symbols, Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society, no. 10 (Two papers on the predicate calculus), Providence, 1952, pp. 2768.Google Scholar
[10]Łoś, J., On the categoricity in power of elementary deductive systems and some related problems, Colloquium mathematicum, vol. 3 (1955), pp. 5862.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[11]Mostowski, A., Concerning a problem of H. Scholz, Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, vol. 2 (1956), pp. 210214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[12]Scholz, H., Ein ungelöstes Problem in der symbolischen Logik, this Journal, vol. 17 (1952), p. 160, Problem 1.Google Scholar
[13]Tarski, A., Der Wahrheitsbegriff in den formalisierten Sprachen, Studio philosophica, vol. 1 (1936), pp. 261405; English translation in Logic, semantics, metamathematics, Oxford (Oxford University Press) 1956, pp. 152–278.Google Scholar
[14]Tarski, A., A problem concerning the notion of definability, this Journal, vol. 13 (1948), pp. 107111.Google Scholar
[15]Tarski, A., Some notions and methods on the borderline of algebra and metamathematics, Proceedings of the International Congress of mathematicians, (Cambridge, Mass. USA, Aug. 30-Sept. 6, 1950), 1952, vol. 1, pp. 705720.Google Scholar
[16]Tarski, A., Contributions to the theory of models, Parts I and II, Indagationes mathematicae, vol. 16 (1954), pp. 572588.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[17]Tarski, A., A general theorem concerning the reduction of primitive notions, this Journal, vol. 19 (1954), p. 158.Google Scholar
[18]Tarski, A., Mostowski, A., and Robinson, R. M., Undecidable theories, Amsterdam (North Holland Pub. Co.), 1953.Google Scholar
[19]Vaught, R. L., Applications of the Löwenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorem to problems of completeness and decidability. Indagationes mathematicae, vol. 16 (1954), pp. 467472.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[20]Vaught, R. L., Finite axiomatizability using additional predicates, I and II, Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 62 (1956), pp. 412413.Google Scholar