Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-wxhwt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-11T23:37:57.638Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

‘Abdicate’ and ‘Contract’ Restored

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 February 2009

Thomas P. Slaughter
Affiliation:
Rutgers University

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Communications
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1985

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Miller, John, ‘The Glorious Revolution: “contract” and “abdication” reconsidered’, Historical Journal, XXV (1982), 541–55CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Slaughter, Thomas P., ‘“Abdicate” and “contract” in the Glorious Revolution’, Historical Journal, XXIV (1981), 323–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Kenyon, J. P., Revolution principles: the politics of party, 1689–1720 (Cambridge, 1977)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kenyon, , ‘The Revolution of 1688: resistance and contract’, in McKendrick, Neil (ed.), Historical perspectives (London, 1974)Google Scholar.

3 Miller, p. 543; Slaughter, p. 325.

4 Slaughter, pp. 335–7. See also footnote 45, page 336 of my article for an advocacy of recent works which seem to transcend the silly debate between ‘whigs’ and ‘tories’. These scholars include Western, J. R., Monarchy and revolution (London, 1972)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Jones, J. R., The revolution of 1688 in England (London, 1972)Google Scholar; and Carter, Jenifer, ‘The revolution and the constitution’, in Holmes, Geoffrey (ed.), Britain after the Glorious Revolution, 1689–1714 (London, 1969), pp. 638–58Google Scholar.

5 Miller, p. 543; Slaughter, p. 525; Skinner, Quentin, ‘Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas’, History and Theory, 8 (1969), 353CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Quote from Miller, p. 544, which is a paraphrase of Slaughter, p. 325 and passim.

7 Kenyon, , ‘The revolution of 1688’, p. 57Google Scholar. Miller's implied criticism of Kenyon on this point appears on pp. 546 and 547.

8 A collection of the parliamentary debates in England… (London, 1741), p. 184Google Scholar.

9 Journals of the House of Lords, 5 February, 1688, p. 117.

10 Collection of parliamentary debates, p. 203.

11 Miller persists, à la Kenyon, in citing isolated speeches within commons to support his case. He seems to misunderstand my point that conference debates and successful resolutions the ones ignored by Kenyon – are more representative of the agreements among M.P.s. No counting of references to contract theory or absence of references to contract theory in individual speeches will ever get at the meanings of the Revolution. See Miller, pp. 547–8 and passim; Slaughter, p. 330.

12 The Lords and Commons reasons and justifications for the deprivation and disposal of James a from the imperial throne of England… (London, 1689)Google Scholar. See Slaughter, pp. 336–7 for a discussion of this pamphlet.

13 Collection of parliamentary debates, pp. 191–5.

14 Ibid. p. 191.

15 Ibid. p. 196.

16 Ibid. p. 203.

17 Miller simply misreads and misunderstands my article. Some M.P.s believed and understood that James was deposed and understood ‘abdicate’ to imply deposition. Others, including at least some members of the house of Lords, saw James as having voluntarily renounced or ‘deserted’ the throne. The intentional choice of ambiguous language facilitated these contradictory understandings without confronting them. See Miller, pp. 554 and 555; Slaughter, p. 333.

18 Miller, pp. 554 and 547; Slaughter, pp. 325, 329–37.

19 Miller, pp. 545 and 547; Slaughter, p. 336.

20 M Miller, pp. 546, 551, and passim; Slaughter, pp. 336–7.

21 Miller, p. 542; Slaughter, p. 330.

22 The most personally disturbing dimension of Miller's discussion of my article comes on pp. 554–5, n. 63. In this note Miller seems to impugn my integrity by suggesting that I altered one parliamentary speech to make it conform to my interpretative needs. It was indeed my intention, as Miller avers, to suggest that ‘Holt talked of two different meanings’ of the word abdicate. Miller contends, on the contrary, that ‘by the plain sense of the words he [Holt] discussed only one’. (Miller, p. 554) In fact, Holt's intentions are clear and they were to defend the choice of ‘abdicate’ because it had the two different meanings that I identified in my article. Holt's speech is long and much of it rambling. That is why I shortened it to include only the relevant passage and inserted the word ‘also’ to clarify Holt's obvious meaning. Early in his speech Holt traced the ancient history of the now obsolete meanings of ‘abdicate’. It is important to remember here the context of Holt's speech. He delivered it immediately following Somers' explanation of the meaning of ‘abdicate’ as a word that ‘doth naturally and properly signify entirely to renounce, throw off, disown, relinquish any thing or person, so as to have no farther to do with it’ (Cobbett's parliamentary history of England, v [London, 1809], p. 68Google Scholar). Holt, speaking next, was agreeing with Somers. ‘That it is an ancient word’, he said, ‘appears by the authors that have been quoted, and it is frequently met with in the best of Roman writers, as Cicero, &c. and by the derivation from “dico”, an ancient Latin word. – That now it is a known English word, and of a known and certain signification with us, I will quote to your lordships an English authority, and that is the Dictionary set forth by our countryman Minshew, who hath the word “abdicare” as an English word, and says that it signifies to “renounce” which is the signification the commons would have of it’. (Ibid. p. 71) Thus, here Holt's point is that ‘abdicate’ is an ancient and traditional English word and was chosen by parliament because it implies force and permanence. In the next part of his speech, Holt addressed other objections of the Lords to the choice of this word. ‘Your lordships second Reason, for your first Amendment in changing the word “abdicated “’, Holt observed, ‘is, because in the most common acceptation of the civil law, abdication is a voluntary express act of renunciation. That is the general acceptation of the word, and I think the commons do use the word in this case, because it [also] hath that signification.’ (Ibid. p. 71) Again, the insertion of ‘also’ to clarify Holt's meaning is appropriate, although in this case, since I have quoted the earlier passage in full, it is redundant. Holt was addressing two different meanings of the word. Miller and I may interpret this speech differently, although for the life of me I cannot imagine how.