Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Home
Hostname: page-component-99c86f546-7mfl8 Total loading time: 0.354 Render date: 2021-11-28T05:57:49.656Z Has data issue: true Feature Flags: { "shouldUseShareProductTool": true, "shouldUseHypothesis": true, "isUnsiloEnabled": true, "metricsAbstractViews": false, "figures": true, "newCiteModal": false, "newCitedByModal": true, "newEcommerce": true, "newUsageEvents": true }

G. W. F. Hegel: Geometrical Studies Introduction

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 June 2015

Alan L. T. Paterson*
Affiliation:
m1p1t@yahoo.com
Get access

Extract

Throughout his life, Hegel showed great interest in physics and mathematics. His most sustained, surviving treatment of Euclidean geometry is his early work ‘Geometrische Studien’, which he completed while he was a private tutor [Hoffmeister] in Frankfurt, shortly before leaving for Jena to join Schelling. GS is not easy reading, but despite that, it seems to me that Hegel presents in it a remarkably erudite as well as interesting and insightful critique of geometry. He investigates some of the themes from the foundations of geometry, in particular from the first book of the Elements of Euclid. Like the mathematical philosophies of Kant and Frege, Hegel's understanding of geometry is conceptually based, but unlike them, it is also grounded in the classical Greek philosophy of mathematics, which achieved its definitive expression in Proclus's great commentary on Euclid 1. Much of this classical philosophy of geometry is forgotten nowadays, under the influence of the great modern mathematical philosophers (in particular, Cantor, Frege and Gödel). In my view, it well deserves reconsideration, especially since, as illustrated by Gödel's incompleteness theorems, modern mathematical philosophy has failed in its attempt to ground mathematics within the framework of formal systems.

Much of GS has not survived, and what remains is condensed and fragmentary. It seems that originally, Hegel covered all of the propositions of Euclid 1 rather than just the 14 propositions (1-12, 26, 29) that are covered in what remains of the original GS. I have given detailed treatment of GS together with related material in Hegel's Jena dissertation elsewhere (Paterson 2004/2005). The objective of the present paper is to introduce the translation of GS.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Hegel Society of Great Britain 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Abbreviations:

Dok.: Hegel, G. W. F. (1936), Dokumente zu Hegels Entwicklung. Hoffmeister, Johannes ed., Stuttgart: Frommann.Google Scholar

GS: Hegel, G.W.F (1936), ‘Geometrische Studien’, in Dok., 288300.Google Scholar

Euclid 1: the first book of Euclid's Elements in Hea., see below.

Hea.: Euclid, (1956) The thirteen books of Euclid's Elements, Vol. 1, Heath, T. L. trans., Dover Publications: New York.Google Scholar

JL: Hegel, G. W. F (1986), The Jena System, 1804-5: Logic and Metaphysics, Burbidge, J. W. and di Giovanni, G. eds. and trans., McGill-Queen's University Press: Kingston and Montreal Google Scholar. (English translation of the ‘Logik and Metaphysik’ of JS)

JS: Hegel, G.W.F (1971), Jenaer Systementwürfe II, Horstmann, R.P. and Trede, J. H. eds., Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft: Bonn-Bad Godesberg. (German edition)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Lor.: Euclid, (1781), Euklids Elemente, funf-zehn Büecher. Lorenz, J. F. tr., Halle: Oswald Seidensticker.Google Scholar

P: Proclus, (1970), Proclus: A Commentary on the first book of Euclid's Elements. Morrow, G. R. trans., Princeton University Press: Princeton, N. J.Google Scholar

SL: Hegel, G.W.F. (1990), Hegel's Science of Logic. Miller, A. V. tr., Humanities Press International, Inc.:Atlantic Highlands, NJ. (English translation of WL.)Google Scholar

WL: Hegel, G.W.F. (1967), Wissenschaft der Logik, Lasson, G. ed., in two volumes, Felix Meiner: Hamburg.Google Scholar

2 The Elements was written by the Alexandrian mathematician Euclid (c. 325-265 BC). This is the most popular and influential mathematical work of all time, and its influence continues to the present day. Indeed, despite the great progress in modern mathematical philosophy, it is still the case, that, as Quine puts it, in the beginning, there was Euclidean geometry.

3 Proclus lived c. 411-485 and was, in his later years, the head of the Academy in Athens.

4 I am grateful to the referees for helpful comments. In particular, one of the referees has brought to my attention the book by Paul Zilche (1996) which is of particular relevance to Hegel's thinking about mathematics and physics in the Jena period. I am especially grateful to Professor Stephen Houlgate who subjected this translation to a painstaking and time-consuming examination; almost all of his many suggestions have been incorporated into the translation, which through them, has been greatly improved. Lastly, I am grateful to Katerina Deligiorgi for her help with getting this work into printed form.

5 I am grateful to one of the referees for pointing out that Hegel's teacher, Pfleiderer in Tübingen, adopted a German translation of the Clairaut version of Euclid, Éléments de Géométrie, in his teaching. However, following Hoffmeister, I feel that Lorenz's book is probably the more influential for Hegel since as his early Tagebuch records, he excerpted from it. For more information about Pfleiderer's work in Tübingen, the reader is referred to Paul Zilche's edition of Pfleiderer's Physics (1994).

6 For a detailed argument justifying the use of P to elucidate GS see Paterson 2004/2005.

7 For Kant (in the first chapter of the Analytic of Principles in the Kritik der reinen Vernunft) the schema of a triangle exists only in thought, and is a rule of synthesis of the imagination, in respect to pure figures in space. Again for more discussion see Paterson 2004/2005.

8 See the discussion of this in Paterson 2004/2005.

9 Of course, we are here discussing only angles in two dimensional space.

10 Hegel does say that the center is not a limit of the sphere. But (as we have seen) it is a limit of the circle? Perhaps the reason why the sphere and circle are different in this respect lies in the foundational role in geometry of the circle as the limited form of the line.

11 Cf. Hegel's discussion of the synthetic-analytic distinction in WL II, 442.; SL, 786f..

12 The postulate is stated in the translation following. Hegel briefly refers to the postulate in his treatment of geometry in WL II, 466; SL, 807-808. He says there that Euclid is correct to treat it as an axiom. For Hegel, it can only be justified by philosophy (the Concept).

Send article to Kindle

To send this article to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about sending to your Kindle. Find out more about sending to your Kindle.

Note you can select to send to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be sent to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

G. W. F. Hegel: Geometrical Studies Introduction
Available formats
×

Send article to Dropbox

To send this article to your Dropbox account, please select one or more formats and confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your <service> account. Find out more about sending content to Dropbox.

G. W. F. Hegel: Geometrical Studies Introduction
Available formats
×

Send article to Google Drive

To send this article to your Google Drive account, please select one or more formats and confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your <service> account. Find out more about sending content to Google Drive.

G. W. F. Hegel: Geometrical Studies Introduction
Available formats
×
×

Reply to: Submit a response

Please enter your response.

Your details

Please enter a valid email address.

Conflicting interests

Do you have any conflicting interests? *