Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-wtssw Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-06T13:56:13.099Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Why We (Still) Need a Revolution

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Abstract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

This paper posits a (very British!) call to arms, and does so in five steps. In part A, we address the need for constitutional fictions by which the many surrender political power to the few, in the name of stability, order and security. In part B, however, we will show that conflict is both a necessary and a core principle of political constitutionalism—that it is the latent possibility of conflict, the (re)awkening of the many where the few abuse that power, that acts as the final check on government. In part C, we trace the steps by which recent re-interpretations of the work of J.A.G. Griffith, with a focus on the work of Tomkins and Bellamy, have reduced politics to its parliamentary form, thereby closing—rather than “enlarging”—the “areas for argument and discussion”—a narrow view of the constitution to which, admittedly, Griffith himself might have subscribed. In part D, we will assess the limits of such a narrow reading of the political and argue that a more dynamic and reflexive approach is needed if we are to remain in—or recover to—rude constitutional health. Finally, in part E, we will use the political and constitutional background to the devolution of legislative and executive power to Scotland in order to demonstrate the power of political conflict, in extraordinary moments, to expose, break down and create new constitutional fictions.

Type
Part I: The Boundaries of the Conception and Practice of Politics within Political Constitutionalism
Copyright
Copyright © 2013 by German Law Journal GbR

Footnotes

*

Lecturer in Law, University of Glasgow, marco.goldoni@glasgow.ac.uk.

**

Lecturer in Law, University of Strathclyde, christopher.mccorkindale@strath.ac.uk.

References

1 Edmund S. Morgan, Inventing the People: The Rise of Popular Sovereignty in England and America 14 (1988).Google Scholar

2 See J.A.G. Griffith, The Political Constitution, 42 Mod. L. Rev. 1 (1979).Google Scholar

3 See id. at 12.Google Scholar

4 See Adam Tomkins, Our Republican Constitution 63 (2005). Adam Tomkins illustrates this point with the classic example of clean air:Google Scholar

We all have an interest, rather obviously, in breathing clean air. None of us acting alone can realise that interest. It is only by acting together—by acting politically—that it can be realised. Now, some of us will have private interests that militate against clean air. Some of us will be industrialists whose factories pollute the air. Others of us will be employees working in such factories, whose livelihoods depend on our employment. But even industrialists and their employees have an interest, as citizens, in breathing clean air.

Id.

5 Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition 8 (Univ. of Chicago Press, 2d ed. 1998) (1958). Hannah Arendt captures this brilliantly. “Plurality,” she said, “is the condition of human action because we are all the same, that is, human, in such a way that nobody is every the same as anyone else who ever lived, lives, or will live.” Id.Google Scholar

6 Griffith, supra note 2, at 3; see also Tomkins, supra note 4, at 63 (noting that the “clean air” example is a good one).Google Scholar

7 Griffith, supra note 2, at 20 (emphasis added).Google Scholar

8 Id. (emphasis added).Google Scholar

9 Indeed, the brief for both this collection and the workshop held in its preparation was precisely to move beyond the dichotomy of the political/legal constitution and to begin to define and promote the political constitution on its own terms.Google Scholar

10 See Griffith, supra note 2, at 16. On referendums as a device of political constitutionalism, see Stephen Tierney, Whose Political Constitution? Citizens and Referendums, 14 German L.J. 2173 (2013). Not all political constitutionalists would agree with Tierney that the referendum is on all fours with constitutionalism, however, particularly where the result of a referendum is to compel Parliament—the political institution par excellence—to legislate or not to legislate, contrary to its wishes. Here we use “compel” in a soft sense, as the results of referendums, at least in the UK, tend not to be legally binding upon government or Parliament, which retains the constitutional authority to “make or unmake any law whatever”.Google Scholar

11 See Griffith, supra note 2, at 3.Google Scholar

12 Griffith, J.A.G., Why We Need a Revolution, 40 Pol. Q. 383, 387 (1969).Google Scholar

13 See Woolf, Lord, Droit Public—English Style, Pub. L. 57, 69 (1995). Thus, when Lord Woolf said that there are “advantages” in courts making clear the limits of Parliament's supremacy, he defended his position with the, in our view, dubious claim that these are limits only “of the most modest dimensions which I believe any democrat would accept.Id. (emphasis added).Google Scholar

14 See Morgan, supra note 1, at 13–14.Google Scholar

15 See Isaiah Berlin, Two Concepts of Liberty (1958). Most notably, Isaiah Berlin stated that the distinction between positive and negative liberty owed much to Benjamin Constant's own division between liberties—ancient and modern.Google Scholar

16 See Constant, Benjamin, The Liberty of the Ancients Compared with That of the Moderns, in Benjamin Constant: Political Writings 307, 312 (Biancamaria Fontana ed., 2001) (1819).Google Scholar

17 Id. at 310–11.Google Scholar

18 See id.Google Scholar

19 VI, King James, The Trew Law of Free Monarchies: Or The Reciprock and Mutuall Dutie Betwixt a Free King, and His Naturall Subjects, in James VI and I: Political Writings 62, 76 (Johann P. Sommerville ed., 1994) (1598).Google Scholar

20 Id. at 81.Google Scholar

21 See Arendt, Hannah, On Revolution 240–44 (1963). Arendt's critique of Robespierre and Sant-Just is particularly striking here.Google Scholar

22 See e.g., Henry Parker, The Case Against Shipmony (1642); Henry Parker, Jus Populi (1644). The writings of Parliament's propagandist-in-chief, Henry Parker, amid the 17th century conflicts between Parliament and the Crown.Google Scholar

23 Constant, supra note 18, at 326. For a more detailed account of the often ignored nuances to Constant's position and the argument that he should be seen not only as a defender of negative liberty, but as one of the most forceful proponents of political liberty in the civic republican tradition, see Christopher McCorkindale, Recovering the Public: The Curious Case of Benjamin Constant, in The Public In Law 35 (Claudio Michelon et al. eds., 2012).Google Scholar

24 See Griffith, supra note 2, at 3.Google Scholar

25 Id. at 11.Google Scholar

26 Griffith, supra note 12, at 389.Google Scholar

27 Id. at 383.Google Scholar

28 Ministry of Justice, Memorandum to the Justice Select Committee: Post-Legislative Assessment of the Freedom of Information Act 2000, 2011, Cm. 8236 (U.K.), available at https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/162298/post-legislative-assessment-of-the-foi-act.pdf.pdf (assessing the Freedom of Information Act 2000 post-legislation).Google Scholar

29 It is the combination of these exemptions and the veto power that led Rodney Austen to deride the Freedom of Information Act 2000 as no more than “a fraud on democratic accountability.” Rodney Austin, The Freedom of Information Act 2000—A Sheep in Woolf's Clothing?, in The Changing Constitution 401, 415 (Jeffrey Jowell & Dawn Oliver eds., 2000). On the other hand, long-time Freedom of Information proponents Carol Harlow and Richard Rawlings have described the 2000 Act as being “one of the world's more restrictive pieces of information legislation.” Carol Harlow & Richard Rawlings, Law and Administration 474 (2009).Google Scholar

30 See Paul Cairney, The Scottish Political System Since Devolution: From New Politics to the New Scottish Government (2011); see also Stewart Davidson, Alastair Stark & Gordon Heggie, Best Laid Plans … The Institutionalisation of Public Deliberation in Scotland, 82 Pol. Q. 379 (2011) (describing the “failure” of a new politics to take hold).Google Scholar

31 It seems to be the case that a section 4 declaration will almost certainly attract some form of remedial action, usually through the ordinary legislative process as opposed to the expedited process provided for in section 10 of the HRA. See Stephen Gardbaum, Reassessing the New Commonwealth Model of Constitutionalism, 8 Int'l J. Const. L. 167 (2010). It is, of course, no part of our argument to suggest that the judiciary ought to be empowered to strike down primary legislation. The point here is no more and no less about the gravitational pull towards the center that occurs even here.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

32 See Griffith, supra note 12, at 391.Google Scholar

33 See Polybius, Book VI.4, in The Rise of the Roman Empire (Ian Scott-Klivert trans., 1979) (describing the final stage of anacyclosis). Polybius’ classic account states:Google Scholar

The first of these to come into being is one-man rule, and developing from it with the aid of art and through the correction of its defects, comes kingship. This later degenerates into its corrupt but associated form, by which I mean tyranny, and then the abolition of both gives rise to aristocracy. Aristocracy by its very nature degenerates into oligarchy, and when the populace rises in anger to avenge the injustices committed by its rulers, democracy is born; then in due course, out of the license and lawlessness which are generated by this type of regime, mob rule comes into being and completes the cycle.

Id.

34 See Niccolò Machiavelli, Book 1.5, in The Discourses 115 (Bernard Crick ed., Leslie J. Walker trans., 1970). Walker translates this from “chi vuole acquistare o chi vuole mantenere,” that is, those who want to acquire or those who want to keep—which he equates with the typical English distinction of haves and have nots.Google Scholar

35 See id. at 116.Google Scholar

37 See Quentin Skinner, Machiavelli 66 (1981).Google Scholar

38 Machiavelli, supra note 36, at 116.Google Scholar

39 Id. at 114.Google Scholar

40 Id. at 113–14.Google Scholar

41 Id. at 115.Google Scholar

42 Id. at 15, 2728 (introduction by Bernard Crick) (emphasis added).Google Scholar

43 See Philip Pettit, Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government (1997); see also Quentin Skinner, Liberty Before Liberalism (1998). Both authors have refined their views in subsequent work, moving closer, if tentatively so, to the position described in this article. See, e.g., Philip Pettit, On the People's Terms: A Republican Theory and Model of Democracy (2012); Quentin Skinner Visions of Politics: Volume II: Renaissance Virtues (2002). For recent accounts of republicanism, see Legal Republicanism: National and International Perspectives (Samantha Besson & José Luis Marti eds., 2009) and Republicanism and Political Theory (Cécile Laborde & John Maynor eds., 2008).Google Scholar

Pettit's claim, and it is one that has dominated republican scholarship over the past fifteen years or so, is that republican freedom as non-domination is essentially a negative liberty, a freedom from domination—including domination by the sovereign monarch, government, legislature or people—with the twist that something more than a purely negative liberty is needed in order to maintain that freedom—that being institutional channels through which citizens might challenge decisions, policies and laws which run counter to their interests. Thus he is able to distinguish his republican variant with the tradition liberal understanding of freedom as non-interference in the following way:

It may just happen that my master is of a kindly and non-interfering disposition. Or it may just happen that I am cunning or fawning enough to be able to get away with doing whatever I like. I suffer domination to the extent that I have a master; I enjoy noninterference to the extent that that master fails to interfere.

Pettit, Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government at 23.

44 See Laborde, Cécil & Maynor, John, The Republican Contribution to Contemporary Political Theory, in Republicanism and Political Theory 1 (Cécile Laborde & John Maynor eds., 2008) (introduction).Google Scholar

45 See Pettit, Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government, supra note 45, at 17–21.Google Scholar

46 Griffith, supra note 12, at 391.Google Scholar

47 Pettit, supra note 45, at 276–78.Google Scholar

48 See Adam Tomkins, Public Law (2003); Adam Tomkins, Our Republican Constitution (2005). As Tomkins explains in this collection, however, his position has somewhat shifted since those books were published. Adam Tomkins, What's Left of the Political Constitution?, 14 German L.J. 2275 (2013).Google Scholar

49 See Richard Bellamy, Political Constitutionalism: A Republican Defence of the Constitutionality of Democracy (2007), available at http://m.friendfeed-media.com/3378a4e1b5895d2695de77fb46c0d7278bc308a8; see also Richard Bellamy, Republicanism, Democracy and Constitutionalism, in Republicanism and Political Theory 159 (Cécile Laborde & John Maynor eds., 2008).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

50 For we can be sure that, if the antithesis of the political constitution is a constitution of judges, then those judges are well prepared to act on those same failings and to redefine the constitution on their terms. Indeed, in a Hamlyn Lecture delivered in 1949, Mr. Justice Denning—as he then was—had this to say about the failings of the political constitution:Google Scholar

No one can suppose that the executive will never be guilty of the sins that are common to all of us. You may be sure that they will sometimes do things which they ought not to do: and will not do things that they ought to do. But if and when wrongs are thereby suffered by any of us, what is the remedy? Our procedure for securing our personal freedom is sufficient, but our procedure for preventing the abuse of power is not … [Resolving this predicament] is not a task for Parliament. Our representatives there cannot control the day to day activities of the many who administer the manifold activities of the State: nor can they award damages to any who are injured by those abuses. The courts must do this. Of all the great tasks that lie ahead, this is the greatest. Properly exercised the new powers of the executive lead to the Welfare State; but abused they lead to the totalitarian state. None such must ever be allowed in this country.

Sir Alfred Denning, Freedom Under the Law 126 (1949).

These same suspicions of the executive, and of Parliament's failings, run through the extra-judicial writings and speeches of many judges to this day. See, e.g., Lord Woolf, supra note 13; Lord Woolf, The Rule of Law and a Change in the Constitution (Mar. 3, 2004), available at: http://www.law.cam.ac.uk/faculty-resources/download/lord-woolf-squire-centenary-lecture-the-rule-of-law-and-a-change-in-constitution-transcript/1415/pdf (transcribing his Squire Centenary Lecture). The same tone runs through the judgments delivered by Lord Steyn, Lord Hope, and Baroness Hale in Jackson v. Attorney General, [2006] 1 AC 262 (H.L). (appeal taken from Eng.) (U.K.) and repeated about the Scottish Parliament, by Lord Hope in AXA General Insurance v. Lord Advocate, [2012] 1 A.C. 868 (appeal taken from Scot.) (U.K.).

51 On the shift from the analysis of the political constitution to political constitutionalism as a normative approach see Tomkins, supra note 4, at 38–40.Google Scholar

52 For a detailed and insightful treatment, see Samantha Besson, The Morality of Conflict (2005).Google Scholar

53 See Adam Tomkins, In Defence of the Political Constitution, 22 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 157 (2002) (powerfully advocating the central place of contestation in the political constitution). Contestation was already placed at the core of republican political philosophy by Thomas Paine. See, e.g., Thomas Paine, Paine: Political Writings 186 (Cambridge Univ. Press 1989) (1790). The same principle, even though in a rather diluted version, is of course taken up by Pettit. See Pettit, supra note 45, at 183–201.Google Scholar

54 This is the view of Bernard Crick, who defines politics as a precise thing which “arises from accepting the fact of the simultaneous existence of different groups, hence different interests and different traditions, within a territorial unit under common rule.” Bernard Crick, In Defence of Politics 17–18 (1962).Google Scholar

55 This is the case, for example, in the United States. See Mark Tushnet, Taking the Constitution Away from the Courts (1999). It might also be possible to see popular constitutionalism as a variation on political constitutionalism that is particular to the United States. See, e.g., Larry Kramer, The People Themselves (2004).Google Scholar

56 Ewing, K.D., The Resilience of the Political Constitution, 14 German L.J. 2099 (2013).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

57 Bellamy, Political Constitutionalism, supra note 51, at 165.Google Scholar

58 This said, there seems to be a growing consensus among political constitutionalists of the legitimacy of weak judicial review. See Stephen Gardbaum, The Case for the New Commonwealth Model of Constitutionalism, 14 German L.J. 2217 (2013); Janet Hiebert, The HRA: Ambiguity About Parliamentary Sovereignty, 14 German L.J. 2253 (2013); Mark Tushnet, The Relation Between Political Constitutionalism and Weak-Form Judicial Review, 14 German L.J. 2237 (2013). For a criticism of the rejection of judicial review, see Paul Craig, Political Constitutionalism and the Judicial Role: A Response, 9 Int'l J. Const. L. 112 (2011).Google Scholar

59 For a philosophical elaboration of this point, see the sophisticated account offered by Thomas Christiano. Thomas Christiano, The Constitution of Equality (2008).Google Scholar

60 See Waldron, Jeremy, Can There be a Democratic Jurisprudence?, 58 Emory L.J. 675 (2009); see also Richard Ekins, the Nature of Legislative Intent 119–40 (2012).Google Scholar

61 In this respect, the political constitution might seem to come closer to what Costantino Mortati defined as the “material constitution” or “costituzione materiale.“ Costantino Mortati, La costituzione materiale (1944).Google Scholar

62 Bellamy, Political Constitutionalism, supra note 51, at 5.Google Scholar

63 Interestingly, this is the case both for liberal and republican legal constitutionalism. See John Rawls, Political Liberalism 214 (1993) (referencing “constitutional essentials”); see also Pettit, Republicanism, supra note 45, at 56.Google Scholar

64 Henry Richardson, Democratic Autonomy 53 (2002).Google Scholar

65 Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (1977).Google Scholar

66 Ewing, K.D., The Resilience of the Political Constitution, 14 German L.J. 2099 (2013).Google Scholar

67 Bellamy, Political Constitutionalism, supra note 51, passim (describing “actually existing democracies”); see also Bellamy, Republicanism, Democracy and Constitutionalism, supra note 51, passim (describing “actually existing democratic processes”).Google Scholar

68 C.f. The Parliamentary Style of Politics (Suvi Soininen & Tapani Turkka eds., 2008), available at http://tocs.ulb.tu-darmstadt.de/211472263.pdf.Google Scholar

69 See Loughlin, Martin, Constituent Power Subverted: From English Constitutional Argument to British Constitutional Practice, in The Paradox of Constitutionalism, 27 (Neil Walker & Martin Loughlin eds., 2007) (reconstructing the debate on constituent power in Great Britain).Google Scholar

70 Andreas Kalyvas, Democracy and the Politics of the Extraordinary: Max Weber, Carl Schmitt, & Hannah Arendt 7 (2008).Google Scholar

71 On the plurality as defining characteristic of the human condition, see Arendt, supra note 5.Google Scholar

72 Griffith, supra note 2.Google Scholar

73 Bellamy, Political Constitutionalism, supra note 51; see also Bellamy, Republicanism, Democracy and Constitutionalism, supra note 51.Google Scholar

74 Waldron, Jeremy, Law and Disagreement (1999).Google Scholar

75 See Antonio Negri, Insurgencies (1999) (radically interpreting constituent power as an absolute alternative to constituted power).Google Scholar

76 Arendt was rather adamant on the importance of new beginnings. See Arendt, supra note 23, at 206; see also Jason Frank, Constituent Moments (2010); Kalyvas, supra note 72, at 10.Google Scholar

77 For a reconstruction of public reason, see Grégoire Webber, the Negotiable Constitution (2009).Google Scholar

78 See Tushnet, supra note 60.Google Scholar

79 The idea of reflexive politics is developed in Emilios A. Christodoulidis, Law and Reflexive Politics (1998) and in Emilios A. Christodoulidis, Republican Constitutionalism and the Reflexivity of Politics, 92 Archiv fuer Rechts—und Sozialphilosophie (ARSP) 1 (2006).Google Scholar

80 Arendt, supra note 23, at 268 (finding the British parliament to be an expression of the elite rather than the seat of authentic political action).Google Scholar

81 See Jacques Rancière, Disagreement (2008). Rancière, as many other authors, distinguishes between politics and the political and places disagreement at play in the distinction between the former and the latter.Google Scholar

82 Bellamy, Political Constitutionalism, supra note 51, at 5.Google Scholar

83 Rather interestingly, in his recent restatement of a theory of republican democracy, Pettit is compelled to close the book by introducing the distinction between constituent and constituted powers as unavoidable. See Pettit, On the People's Terms, supra note 45, at 279–91.Google Scholar

84 See Griffith, supra note 2, at 15.Google Scholar

85 James Mitchell, Devolution in the United Kingdom 220 (2009).Google Scholar

86 However, for a persuasive answer to this question, see Jim Gallagher, How and Why to Answer the West Lothian Question (2012), available at http://www.ippr.org/images/media/files/publication/2012/04/west-lothian-question_Apr2012_8954.pdf.Google Scholar

87 For more information on the results of the 1987 general election, see House of Commons, Public Information Fact Sheet, No. 47, General Election Results, 11 June 1987, available at www.parliament.uk/documents/commons-information-office/m11.pdf.Google Scholar

88 James Mitchell, From National Identity to Nationalism, 1945–99, in The Challenge to Westminster: Sovereignty, Devolution and Independence 154, 160 (H.T. Dickinson & Michael Lynch eds., 2000).Google Scholar

89 Lynn G. Bennie, Understanding Political Participation: Green Party Membership in Scotland 22 (2004).Google Scholar

90 For more detail, see Danny Burns, Poll Tax Rebellion (1992).Google Scholar

91 For more on this, see Michael Lavalette & Gerry Mooney, “No Poll Tax Here!”: The Tories, Social Policy, and the Great Poll Tax Rebellion, in Class Struggle and Social Welfare 199, 212 (Michael Lavalette & Gerry Mooney eds., 2000).Google Scholar

92 See the account of this coming together given by Tommy Sheridan, chair of the Pollock Anti Poll Tax Union and later MSP. Id. at 218.Google Scholar

93 While the initial Maryhill and Somerset APTU was a short-lived affair, its very coming into being inspired the creation of similar associations across the country, many of which last the course.Google Scholar

94 Given that a huge number of Scots fell off the electoral register altogether in order to avoid detection for nonpayment, official figures were impossible to gather.Google Scholar

95 Hugh Parker Atkinson & Stuart Wilks-Heeg, Local Government from Thatcher to Blair: The Politics of Creative Autonomy 71 (2000).Google Scholar

96 The Poll Tax in Scotland: 20 Years On, BBC News, Apr. 1, 2009, available at http://news.bbc.co.uk/1/hi/scotland/7976782.stm.Google Scholar

97 As Lord Reid put it in Madzimbamuto v. Lardner-Burke, [1969] 1 AC 645, 723 (appeal taken from Eng.):Google Scholar

It is often said that it would be unconstitutional for Parliament to do certain things, meaning that the moral, political and other reasons against it are so strong that most people would regard it has highly improper if Parliament did these things. But that does not mean that it is beyond the power of Parliament to do such things. If Parliament chose to do any of them the courts would not hold the Act of Parliament to be invalid.

98 Arendt, supra note 5, at 50.Google Scholar

99 See BBC News, supra note 98.Google Scholar

100 Marr, Andrew, The Battle for Scotland 180 (1992).Google Scholar

101 The Conservatives, understandably, sat out and lobbied Scottish business interests to do the same. The Scottish National Party (SNP), early supporters of a convention, sat out too, fearing that Labour domination of the agenda could be used counterproductively to attack the SNP's policy of “independence within Europe.” See David Denver Et Al., Scotland Decides: The Devolution Issue and the Scottish Referendum 32–33 (2000).Google Scholar

102 See Ewen A. Cameron, Civil Society, Protest and Parliament: Housing and Land in Modern Scotland, in The Challenge to Westminster: Sovereignty, Devolution and Independence 123 (H.T. Dickinson & Michael Lynch eds., 2000).Google Scholar

103 Michael Keating, Managing the Multinational State: Constitutional Settlement in the United Kingdom, in The Dynamics of Decentralization: Canadian Federalism and British Devolution 21 (Trevor C. Salmon & Michael Keating eds., 2001).Google Scholar

104 See generally National Archives of Scotland, Translation of the Declaration of Arbroath (Alan Borthwick trans. 2005), available at http://www.nas.gov.uk/downloads/declarationArbroath.pdf.Google Scholar

105 A Claim of Right for Scotland (Owen Dudley Edwards ed., 1989).Google Scholar

108 Christopher Harvie & Peter Jones, The Road to Home Rule 154 (2000). In surrendering to opponents of the First Past the Post system, the Labour Party was consoled by the knowledge that, with the adoption of this compromise, it would be almost impossible for the SNP ever to win a majority in the chamber. That conventional wisdom (pun not intended), of course, was shattered at the 2011 elections to the Scottish Parliament, which defied all odds (and indeed the electoral system itself) to return a single party, SNP majority, to the chamber. The result of the Scottish independence referendum on 18 September 2014 will tell us just how historically significant (and transformative) that anomaly might be.Google Scholar

109 See generally Brian Taylor, The Scottish Parliament (1999) (discussing the negotiating framework of the Convention). The final report of the convention, containing the details of the agreed framework, was published as Scotland's Claim, Scotland's Right, Scottish Constitutional Convention (1995).Google Scholar

110 Stephen Tierney, “We the Peoples”: Constituent Power and Constitutionalism in Plurinational States, in The Paradox of Constitutionalism 229, 242–43 (Neil Walker & Martin Loughlin eds., 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

111 Murray v. Rogers, 1992 S.L.T. 221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

112 Pringle, Petitioner 1991 S.L.T. 330. For more on these cases, see generally Denis J. Edwards, The Treaty of Union: More Hints of Constitutionalism, 12 Legal Stud. 34 (1992); Chris Himsworth & Neil Walker, The Poll Tax and Fundamental Law, 36 Jurid. Rev. 45 (1991).Google Scholar

113 As Lavalette and Mooney report it:Google Scholar

The local ATPU organisers were nearly always taken aback by the response. In apparently “demoralised” working-class communities which had suffered from unemployment, poverty and deprivation, and within which the struggle for daily survival was immense, there were mass meetings of between 200 and 500 people, all of whom were bitterly opposed to the poll tax and determined to fight it.

Lavalette, & Mooney, , supra note 93, at 218.Google Scholar

114 Here, I borrow for this context a phrase used by Hannah Arendt to describe the voice of council system of democracy that emerged in revolutions as diverse as those in the United States, France, Russia, and Hungary. See Hannah Arendt, Thoughts on Politics and Revolution, in Hannah Arendt, Crises of the Republic 199, 232 (1972).Google Scholar

115 Mitchell, James, Strategies for Self-Government: The Campaigns for a Scottish Parliament 287–90 (1996).Google Scholar

116 See Hadfield, Brigid, The United Kingdom as a Territorial State, in The British Constitution in the Twentieth Century 623 (Vernon Bogdanor ed., 2004).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

117 Loughlin, supra note 71, at 48.Google Scholar

118 Griffith, supra note 12, at 42.Google Scholar

119 Arendt, Hannah, The Origins of Totalitarianism 324 (Schocken, 2004) (1951).Google Scholar

120 Griffith, supra note 12, at 386.Google Scholar

121 No wonder then that when Arendt re-visited the party system in On Revolution, a book dedicated to the study of constituent power, her views on the two-party system had shifted quite markedly. No longer the dynamic of political liberty, her view was much more pessimistic:Google Scholar

[W]hile it may be true that, as a device of government, only the two-party system has proved its viability and, at the same time, its capacity to guarantee constitutional liberties, it is no less true that the best it has achieved is a certain control of the rulers by those who are ruled, but that it has by no means enabled the citizen to become a “participator” in public affairs. The most the citizen can hope for it to be “represented,” whereby it is obvious that the only thing that can be represented and delegated is interest, or the welfare of the constituents but neither their actions nor their opinions.

Arendt, supra note 23, at 268.