Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-68ccn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-12T18:22:08.196Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The “Polemical” Spirit of European Constitutional Law: On the Importance of Conflicts in EU Law

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

Recently, scholars have argued of the necessity of going beyond “judicial dialogues” and “conflict-and-power” approaches to the analysis of the role of national Constitutional Courts in the Union. On the one hand, there are risks connected to a “too welcoming an approach by national constitutional courts to EU law”; on the other hand, it is possible to criticize both the Court of Justice of the EU (CJEU) and some national Constitutional Courts for other, less cooperative, decisions. I share this cautious approach for many reasons, and primarily because the preliminary ruling mechanism does not exhaust all the possible means of communication between constitutional courts and the CJEU. For instance, what Komárek calls “parallel references” can serve, in some circumstances, as a technique of alternative (or hidden) dialogue, that has favored a sort of “remote dialogue” over the years. My sole point of disagreement with this scholarly position is over the role of conflicts in this scenario. Whilst Komárek seems to confine conflicts to phenomena of mere resistance or to “‘cold’ strategic considerations,” in this work I am going to adopt a much broader idea of conflict, which goes beyond mere “conflicts and power games.”

Type
Part One
Copyright
Copyright © 2015 by German Law Journal GbR 

References

1 Komárek, Jan, The Place of Constitutional Courts in the EU, 9 Eur. Const. L. Rev. 420 (2013).Google Scholar

2 Id. at 449.Google Scholar

3 See Martinico, Giuseppe, Judging in the Multilevel Legal Order: Exploring The Techniques Of ‘Hidden Dialogue', 21 King's L. J. 257 (2010).Google Scholar

4 Komárek, supra note 1, at 436.Google Scholar

5 Martinico, supra note 3; Martinico, Giuseppe, Multiple loyalties and dual preliminarity: The pains of being a judge in a multilevel legal order, 10 Int'l J. Const. L. 871 (2012).Google Scholar

6 This is the formula (“dialogo a distanza”) used by Gabriella Angiulli, Il rinvio pregiudiziale alla Corte di giustizia dell'Unione europea da parte dei Giudici costituzionali degli Stati membri, http://www.gruppodipisa.it/wpcontent/uploads/2011/05/SIENA_Scuola_dottorale_in_-Diritto_-ed_-economia.pdf (2011).Google Scholar

7 Komárek, supra note 1, at 422. The author was referring to the view expressed by Arthur Dyevre, European Integration and National Courts: Defending Sovereignty under Institutional Constraints? 9 Euro. Const. L. Rev. 139 (2013).Google Scholar

8 Orders of 17 December 2013 and of 14 January 2014, 2 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court] 1390/12; 2 BVerfGE 1421/12; 2 BVerfGE 1438/12; 2 BVerfGE 1439/12; 2 BVerfGE 1440/12; 2 BVerfGE 1824/12; 2 BvE 6/12, available at https://www.bundesverfassungsgericht.de.Google Scholar

9 Gerstenberg, Oliver, An End to European Multilateralism: A Comment on the German Bundesverfassungsgericht's OMT decision, available at http://eutopialaw.com/2014/02/19/an-end-to-european-multilateralism-a-comment-on-the-german-bundesverfassungsgerichts-omt-decision/ (2014); Delledonne, Giacomo, La ‘prima volta’ di Karlsruhe: il rinvio pregiudiziale relativo alle outright monetary transactions (2014), available at www.csfederalismo.it/it/pubblicazioni/commenti/797-la-prima-volta-di-karlsruhe-il-rinvio-pregiudiziale-relativo-alle-outright-monetary-transactions.Google Scholar

10 Case C–399/11, Stefano Melloni v. Ministerio Fiscal, available at http://curia.europa.eu/. Mr. Melloni, an Italian citizen living in Spain, was convicted in absentia for bankruptcy fraud by a sentence delivered by the Tribunale of Ferrara and arrested by the Spanish police. On the basis of the Council Framework Decision on the European Arrest Warrant (2002/584/JHA as amended by the Framework Decision 2009/299/JHA) the Italian authorities asked for the activation of the mechanism. Mr. Melloni opposed surrender to the Italian authorities, by arguing the violation of the right to defence. The Audiencia Nacional (a special Spanish high court) decided to surrender Mr. Melloni to Italy since it considered the right to defence was respected (Mr. Melloni, in fact, was aware of the trial, opted for the asbentia and appointed two lawyers to defend himself). Against the order of the Audiencia Nacional, Mr. Melloni opposed a recurso de amparo (a direct action for the protection of constitutional rights guaranteed by the Constitution) before the Spanish Constitutional Court.Google Scholar

11 After the delivery of this Article, two other Constitutional Courts raised preliminary questions ex Art. 267 TFEU to the CJEU: the Ustavno sodišče (Slovenian Constitutional Court), Order U-I-295/13) available at http://www.usrs.si/aktualno/novice/sklep-ustavnega-sodisca-st-u-i-29513-z-dne-6-11-2014/ and the Trybunał Konstytucyjny (Polish Constitutional Court) decision K 61/13, available at http://otk.trybunal.gov.pl/OTK/otk_odp.asp?droga=%28otk_odp%29&sygnatura=K%2061/13.Google Scholar

12 Melloni, Case C-399/11 at para.58.Google Scholar

13 Id. at para.60.Google Scholar

14 To quote the formula used, also recently, by some scholars: Bogdandy, Armin von & Schill, Stephan, Overcoming absolute primacy: Respect for national identity under the Lisbon Treaty, 48 Common Mkt. L. Rev. 1417 (2011).Google Scholar

15 Tribunal Constitucional (Spanish Constitutional Court), sentencia No. 26/2014 of 13 February 2014, available at http://www.tribunalconstitucional.es/es/jurisprudencia/restrad/Paginas/JCCJCC262014en.aspx.Google Scholar

16 Pérez, Aida Torres, Melloni in Three Acts: From Dialogue to Monologue, 10 Eur. Const. L. Rev. 308 (2014).Google Scholar

17 Case C-314/08, Filipiak, 2009 E.C.R. I-11049.Google Scholar

18 Case C-409/06, Winner Wetten, 2010 E.C.R. I-08015.Google Scholar

19 “The ECtHR's margin of appreciation doctrine plays a role similar to that of the reverse Solange jurisprudence of Schmidberger and Omega—allowing the court to acknowledge and defer to national specificities in the understanding of common principles—while the BVG's Görgülü doctrine corresponds to Solange—allowing the national court to defer to judgments by the ECtHR, as long as the latter provides, in general, equivalent protection of fundamental rights.” Charles F. Sabel & Oliver Gerstenberg Constitutionalising an Overlapping Consensus: The ECI and the Emergence of a Coordinate Constitutional Order, 16 Eur. L. J. 511 (2010).Google Scholar

20 On the importance of constitutional transformation in European constitutional law, see Fossum, John Erik & Agustín José Menéndez, The Constitution's Gift. A Constitutional Theory for a Democratic European Union 28 (2010). See also Joseph H.H. Weiler, The transformation of Europe, in The Constitution of Europe 10 (Joseph H.H. Weiler ed., 1999).Google Scholar

21 Using the distinction employed by the Spanish Constitutional Court: Tribunal Constitucional, declaración 1/2004 of 13 December 2004, available at www.tribunalconstitucional.es.Google Scholar

22 Bogdandy, von & Schill, Stephan, supra note 14.Google Scholar

23 On constitutional pluralism, see MacCormick, Neil, Beyond the sovereign state, 56 Mod. L. Rev. 1 (1993); Walker, Neil, The Idea of Constitutional Pluralism, 65 Mod. L. Rev. 317 (2002); and Maduro, Miguel P., Contrapuntal law: Europe's constitutional pluralism in action, in Sovereignty in Transition 501 (Neil Walker ed., 2003).Google Scholar

24 Pernice, Ingolf, Multilevel Constitutionalism and the Treaty of Amsterdam: European Constitution Making Revisited?, 36 Common Mkt. L. Rev. 703 (1999); Mayer, Franz & Pernice, Ingolf, La costituzione integrata dell'Europa, in Diritti e Costituzione nell'Unione Europea 49, 43 (Gustavo Zagrebelsky ed., 2005); Pernice, Ingolf, Multilevel Constitutionalism in the European Union, 27 Eur. L. Rev. 511 (2002). On multilevel constitutionalism, see also Leonard Besselink, A Composite European Constitution/Een Samengestelde Europese Constitutie (2007).Google Scholar

25 Bogdandy, von & Schill, supra note 14.Google Scholar

26 Article 4 TEU states,Google Scholar

1. In accordance with Article 5, competences not conferred upon the Union in the Treaties remain with the Member States. 2. The Union shall respect the equality of Member States before the Treaties as well as their national identities, inherent in their fundamental structures, political and constitutional, inclusive of regional and local self-government. It shall respect their essential State functions, including ensuring the territorial integrity of the State, maintaining law and order and safeguarding national security. In particular, national security remains the sole responsibility of each Member State. 3. Pursuant to the principle of sincere cooperation, the Union and the Member States shall, in full mutual respect, assist each other in carrying out tasks which flow from the Treaties. The Member States shall take any appropriate measure, general or particular, to ensure fulfilment of the obligations arising out of the Treaties or resulting from the acts of the institutions of the Union. The Member States shall facilitate the achievement of the Union's tasks and refrain from any measure which could jeopardise the attainment of the Union's objectives.

27 Bogdandy, von & Schill, supra note 14, at 1,418.Google Scholar

29 I developed this thesis in Martinico, Giuseppe, What lies behind Article 4.2 TEU?, in National constitutional identity and European integration 93 (Alejandro Saiz Arnaiz & Carina Alcoberro Llivina eds., 2013).Google Scholar

30 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court], Case 2 BvG 52/71 Bundesverfassungsgericht: Federal Constitutional Court [1974] 2 CMLR 540.Google Scholar

31 On this process, see Gordillo, Luis I., Interlocking Constitutions Towards an Interordinal Theory of National, European and UN Law 66 (2012). The Author describes a process, consisting of two stages—“the establishment of the red lines” and “the rapprochement of positions.”Google Scholar

32 Pizzorusso, Alessandro, Common constitutional traditions as Constitutional Law of Europe? Sant'Anna Legal Studies (STALS) Research Paper, 1/2008, http://stals.sssup.it/files/stals_Pizzorusso.pdf (2008).Google Scholar

33 See, for instance, Articles 9 (“right to marry and right to found a family”), 10(2) (“freedom of thought, conscience and religion”), 14(3) (“right to education”), 27 (“workers’ right to information and consultation within the undertaking”), 28 (“right of collective bargaining and action”), 30 (“protection in the event of unjustified dismissal”, and 34–36 (“social security and social assistance”, “health care” and “access to services of general economic interest”). A possible effect of such provisions might be to increase the reference to the national traditions of Member States, a sort of margin of appreciation doctrine spread at EU level—especially when the reference to national legislations and practices is not accompanied by that to EU law—but of course this also implies the risk of an erroneous reference to national legislations. Title IV, devoted to “Solidarity,” is particularly rich in such references and perhaps it is not a coincidence, since in this field the EUCFR is more innovative than in other cases (with the exceptions of the title devoted to “Citizens’ rights”, for obvious reasons) compared with the ECHR.Google Scholar

34 After the delivery of this article, this attention paid to fundamental rights has been somehow questioned by Opinion 2/13 delivered by the CJEU and concerning the accession of the EU to the ECHR. CJEU, Opinion 2/13, pursuant to Article 218(11) TFEU, (Dec. 18, 2014), http://curia.europa.eu/. However, despite this Opinion, I still think that the EU has not abandoned its project to transform itself into a Europe of Rights.Google Scholar

35 See Ruggeri, Antonio, Trattato costituzionale, europeizzazione dei ‘controlimiti’ e tecniche di risoluzione delle antinomie tra diritto comunitario e diritto interno (profili problematici), available at www.forumcostituzionale.it (2005). See also, Mattias Kumm, The jurisprudence of constitutional conflict: Constitutional supremacy in Europe before and after the Constitutional Treaty, 11 Eur. L. J. 262 (2005).Google Scholar

36 For instance, the many provisions of the Charter of Fundamental Rights of the EU. I reflected on these clauses in another piece: Giuseppe Martinico, Chasing the European Court of Justice: On Some (Political) Attempts to Hijack the European Integration Process, 14 Int'l Community L. Rev. 243 (2012).Google Scholar

37 “European unification on the basis of a union of sovereign states under the Treaties may, however, not be realised in such a way that the Member States do not retain sufficient space for the political formation of the economic, cultural and social circumstances of life. This applies in particular to areas which shape the citizens’ circumstances of life, in particular the private space of their own responsibility and of political and social security, which is protected by the fundamental rights, and to political decisions that particularly depend on previous understanding as regards culture, history and language and which unfold in discourses in the space of a political public that is organised by party politics and Parliament. Essential areas of democratic formative action comprise, inter alia, citizenship, the civil and the military monopoly on the use of force, revenue and expenditure including external financing and all elements of encroachment that are decisive for the realisation of fundamental rights, above all as regards intensive encroachments on fundamental rights such as the deprivation of liberty in the administration of criminal law or the placement in an institution. These important areas also include cultural issues such as the disposition of language, the shaping of circumstances concerning the family and education, the ordering of the freedom of opinion, of the press and of association and the dealing with the profession of faith or ideology.” Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court], cases 2 BvE 2/08 at para. 249.Google Scholar

38 More recently see a decision of the Czech Constitutional Court which did not have to do with constitutional identity but which demonstrates the permanent risks of conflicts even after the entry into force of Article 4(2) TEU. Ústavní soud (Czech Constitutional Court, judgment of 31 January, PI. ÚS 5/12, Slovak Pensions XVII. The English translation is available at http:// http://www.usoud.cz/.Google Scholar

39 Martinico, Giuseppe, The Tangled Complexity of the EU Constitutional Process: The Frustrating Knot of Europe (2012).Google Scholar

40 The mot-problème (Edgar Morin, Introduzione al pensiero complesso, 1993, and Edgar Morin, Conoscenza della conoscenza, 1989) complexity is polysemous. Millard, for instance, recalls at least four different meanings of the word ‘complex’ (Eric Millard, Eléments pour une approche analytique de la complexité, in Droit et complexite Pour une nouvelle intelligence du droit vivant 141 (Mathieu Doat, Jacques Le Goff, & Philippe Pédrot eds., 2007). Complex, in fact, is often used as a synonym of “complicated” and in this sense an antinomy may be understood as complex given its difficulty in being solved because of the legal abundance caused by the coexistence of so many legislators in the EU and of the consequent difficult manageability of the several materials, languages and meanings present in the multilevel system. Secondly, complexity may refer “à la situation d'un objet fragmentée, découpée. L'ensemble social n'est pas simple, au sens d'une théorie des ensembles: il résulte de l'addition ou de l'interaction entre une pluralité d'ensembles partiels, eux- měmes sans doute s'entreměles (Id. 143).” Thirdly, complex is understood as non-aprioristic/pragmatic; in this respect a reason is complex when it cannot infer choices and decisions from general, clear and abstract principles which were defined aprioristically. On Europe as a complex system, see Morin, Edgar, Pensare l'Europa (1988).Google Scholar

41 Scholars have identified at least four different meanings of primacy/supremacy in CJEU case law. Moreover, the notion of primacy enshrined in Art I-6 of the Constitutional Treaty seems to be different from that used by the CJEU. See, e.g., Monica Claes, The National Courts’ Mandate in the European Constitution 100 (2006). In order to find a solution to this ambiguity, some scholars have devised a ‘law of laws'; see Eijsbouts, Willem Tom & Besselink, Leonard, Editorial: The Law of Laws—Overcoming Pluralism, 4 Eur. Const. L. Rev. 395 (2008).Google Scholar

42 See, for instance, the piece by Dani, Marco, Economic and Social Conflicts, Integration and Constitutionalism in Contemporary Europe, LSE ‘Europe in Question’ Discussion Paper Series, 13/2009, available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1518629 (2009). See also the special issue of the European Law Journal (Volume 18, Issue 5) devoted to this subject and edited by Damian Chalmers and Marco Dani with contributions by Michelle Everson, Christian Joerges, Alexander Somek, and Floris de Witte. See also Dani, Marco, Il diritto pubblico europeo nella prospettiva dei conflitti (2013).Google Scholar

43 Angiulli, supra note 6.Google Scholar

44 This was, for instance, the word used by Tomuschat, Christian, La Unión Europea en el marco constitucional de los Estados Miembros. El caso de Alemania, at a conference given at the Complutense University on 17 April 2013. See also Ragone, Sabrina, Las relaciones de los Tribunales Constitucionales de los Estados miembros con el Tribunal de Justicia y con el Tribunal Europeo de Derechos Humanos: una propuesta de clasificación, Revista de Derecho Constitucional Europeo, available at http://www.ugr.es/~redce/REDCE16/articulos/02SRagone.htm (2011).Google Scholar

45 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court], orders of 17 Dec. 2013 and of 14 Jan. 2014, 2 BvR 1390/12; 2 BvR 1421/12; 2 BvR 1438/12; 2 BvR 1439/12; 2 BvR 1440/12; 2 BvR 1824/12; 2 BvE 6/12, available at https://www.bundesverfassungsgericht.de.Google Scholar

46 Among others, see Cour d'Arbitrage [Belgian Court of Arbitration], 19 February 1997, no. 6/97, available at www.arbitrage.be/fr/common/home.html Google Scholar

47 Among others, see Verfassungsgerichtshof VfGH [Austrian Constitutional Court], 10 March 1999, B 2251/97, B 2594/97, available at www.vfgh.gv.at/cms/vfgh-site Google Scholar

48 Lietuvos Respublikos Konstitucinis Teismas [The Constitutional Court of the Republic of Lithuania], decision of 8 May 2007, available at www.lrkt.lt Google Scholar

49 Corte Costituzionale [Italian Constitutonal Court], sentenza no. 102/2008 and ordinanza no. 103/2008, available at www.cortecostituzionale.it. The preliminary reference was raised during principaliter proceedings. More recently the Italian Constitutional Court extended its revirement to incidenter proceedings, see: ordinanza 207/2013, http://www.governo.it/Presidenza/CONTENZIOSO/comunicazione/allegati/ordinanza_207_2013_completa.pdf Google Scholar

50 Tribunal Constitucional [Spanish Constitutional Court] Auto 86/2011, available at http://www.tribunalconstitucional.es/.Google Scholar

52 Ustavno sodišče [Slovenian Constitutional Court], Order U–I–295/13) available at http://www.usrs.si/aktualno/novice/sklep-ustavnega-sodisca-st-u-i-29513-z-dne-6-11-2014/.Google Scholar

53 Trybunał Konstytucyjny [Polish Constitutional Court] decision K 61/13, available at http://otk.trybunal.gov.pl/OTK/otk_odp.asp?droga=%28otk_odp%29&sygnatura=K%2061/13.Google Scholar

54 Among her works, see Mouffe, Chantal, The Return of the Political (1993); Mouffe, Chantal, The Democratic Paradox (2000); Mouffe, Chantal, On the Political (2005) (“I use the concept of agonistic pluralism to present a new way to think about democracy which is different from the traditional liberal conception of democracy as a negotiation among interests and is also different from the model which is currently being developed by people like Jürgen Habermas and John Rawls. While they have many differences, Rawls and Habermas have in common the idea that the aim of the democratic society is the creation of a consensus, and that consensus is possible if people are only able to leave aside their particular interests and think as rational beings. However, while we desire an end to conflict, if we want people to be free we must always allow for the possibility that conflict may appear and to provide an arena where differences can be confronted. The democratic process should supply that arena.”); Mouffe, Chantal, Hearts, Minds and Radical Democracy, available at http://www.redpepper.org.uk/hearts-minds-and-radical-democracy/ (1998).Google Scholar

55 Mouffe, Chantal, On the Political 3 (2005).Google Scholar

56 Mouffe, Chantal, On the Political 84 (2005).Google Scholar

57 “Because for me that is what politics is about. If there is politics in society it is because there is conflict […] I started to look at Freud. He does not really develop this idea from the perspective of the collective subject; he develops it more in terms of the individual. I consider the idea of the division of the subject—Eros and Thanatos—and the way the concept of the drive is linked to conflict, very important for politics. I have also been interested in the work of Elias Canetti, in ‘Masse und Macht', when he insists that there is a tension between the individuality and the drive to be part of the mass. Again, the idea that we are divided is predominant.” Chantal Mouffe, Hegemony, Democracy, Agonism and Journalism: An Interview with Chantal Mouffe, 7 Journalism Stud. 964 (2006), http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/3020/1/Hegemony,_democracy,_agonism_and_journalism_%28LSERO%29.pdf.Google Scholar

58 Noonan, Jeff, Democratic society and human needs 193 (2006).Google Scholar

59 Mouffe, Chantal, On the Political 120 (2005).Google Scholar

60 Case C-36/02, Omega, 2004 E.C.R. I–9609.Google Scholar

61 Case C-213/07, Michaniki, 2008 E.C.R. I–9999.Google Scholar

62 Case C-34/09, Gerardo Ruiz Zambrano v. Office National de l'emploi, 2011 E.C.R. I-01177.Google Scholar

63 Case C-173/09, Elchinov, 2010 E.C.R. I-08889.Google Scholar

64 “It needs what I call a ‘conflictual consensus.’ We need to accept a common symbolic framework, but within this symbolic framework, of course, there is room for disagreement. Let me give you an example of what I mean by that. The common symbolic framework of modern pluralist democracy is the expression of ‘liberty and equality for all'. Those are its ‘ethico-political principles'. Citizens in a pluralist democracy need to agree that those are the principles that are going to inform their coexistence. But, of course, those shared principles can be interpreted in many different ways. After all, what is liberty? What is equality? And who belongs to this ‘all'? There are many different interpretations of this last term alone, and we should accept the legitimacy of those different interpretations.” Chantal Mouffe, Which Public Space for Critical Artistic Practices?, https://readingpublicimage.files.wordpress.com/2012/04/chantal_mouffe_cork_caucus.pdf (2005).Google Scholar

65 Mouffe, Chantal, The Democratic Paradox 102 (2000). On the Schmittian influence, see Ince, Onur Ulas, The Return Of The Schmittian: Radical Democratic Theory At Its Limits, available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1675583 (2009).Google Scholar

66 Halberstam, Daniel, Constitutional Heterarchy: The Centrality of Conflict in the European Union and the United States, in In Ruling the World? Constitutionalism, International Law and Global Governance 326 (Jeffrey L. Dunoff & Joel P. Trachtman eds., 2009) (“In one important sense, however, the relationship between the European Union and its Member States is, of course, different from that between the United States and the several states. In the United States, the relationship between federal and state law, and, in particular, between the federal Supreme Court and the state judiciary, are fully ordered…In the European Union, by contrast, the relationship between the central and component state legal orders is fundamentally unsettled.”)Google Scholar

67 Started with the famous Solange I, Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court], Case No. 2 BvG 52/71 Bundesverfassungsgericht: Federal Constitutional Court [1974] 2 CMLR 540.Google Scholar

68 Joined Cases C–188/10 and C–189/10, Melki and Abdeli, 2010 E.C.R. I–05667.Google Scholar

69 François-Xavier Millet, La ‘question prioritaire de constitutionnalité’ e il dialogo a singhiozzo tra giudici in Europa (Unione europea, Corte di giustizia dell'Unione europea, grande sezione, sentenza 22 giugno 2010, cause C-188/10 e C–189/10), 17 Giornale di diritto amministrativo 139 (2011).Google Scholar

70 Case C–314/85, Foto-Frost, 1987 E.C.R. 4199.Google Scholar

71 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court], 26 Aug. 2010, Case No. 2 BvR 2261/06.Google Scholar

72 As Mayer pointed out: “[A]n ultra vires-control of European acts by the German Constitutional Court would only occur in extraordinary circumstances and obvious cases, and apparently a preliminary reference to the ECJ would have to take place first.” Franz Mayer, Rashomon in Karlsruhe—A Reflection on Democracy and Identity in the European Union, Jean Monnet Working Paper, 5/10, available at http:://jeanmonnetprogram.org/paper/rashomon-in-karlsruhe-a-reflection-on-democracy-and-identity-in-the-european-union/ (2010).Google Scholar

73 As Le Goff put it when writing about the relation between complexity and labour law: “Comme si s'on optait pour la technique homéopathique de lutte contre le mal par le mal lui-měme, le désordre devenant paradoxalement vecteur d'ordre”, Jacques Le Goff, Le droit du travail, terre d'élection de la complexité, in Droit et complexite Pour une nouvelle intelligence du droit vivant 106 (Mathieu Doat, Jacques Le Goff & Philippe Pédrot eds., 2007).Google Scholar

74 This is also consistent with a certain branch of political science scholars: Jack Knight Institutions and social conflict (1992). See also the importance of the relationship between conflicts and order in Machiavelli, especially in the Discourses on the Ten Books of Titus Livy. On this see: Alberto Giacomin, La ‘roba’ e gli ‘onori': conflitto distributivo e ordine politico nel pensiero di Machiavelli, Note di Lavoro, http://www.unive.it/media/allegato/DIP/Economia/Note_di_lavoro_sc_economiche/NL2007/NL_DSE_Giacomin_11_07.pdf (2007).Google Scholar

75 Marty, Mireille Delmas, Le pluralisme ordonne et les interactions entre ensembles juridiques, Recueil Dalloz 951 (2006).Google Scholar

76 For a different but very convincing idea of order, see Itzcovich, Giulio, Legal Order, Legal Pluralism, Fundamental Principles. Europe and Its Law in Three Concepts, 18 Eur. L. J. 358 (2012). For a stimulating reading on the relation between order and disorder see: Neil Walker, Beyond boundary disputes and basic grids: Mapping the global disorder of normative orders, 6 Int'l J. Const. L., 373 (2008).Google Scholar

77 Omega, Case C–36/02.Google Scholar

78 Case C–81/05, Cordero Alonso, 2006 E.C.R. I–7569.Google Scholar

79 Case C–442/00, Rodríguez Caballero, 2002 E.C.R. I–11915.Google Scholar

80 Tribunal Constitucional [Spanish Constitutional Court], decision No. 306/1993 of 25 October 1993, available at www.tribunalconstitucional.es Google Scholar

81 Cordero Alonso, Case C–81/05 at para. 41.Google Scholar

82 Omega, Case C–36/02.Google Scholar

83 Case C–244/06, Dynamic Medien, 2008 E.C.R. I–505.Google Scholar

84 Dani, Marco, Tracking Judicial Dialogue—The Scope for Preliminary Rulings from the Italian Constitutional Court, Jean Monnet Working Paper, 10/2008, available at http://econpapers.repec.org/paper/erpjeanmo/p0207.htm (2008). See also the reactions to the Mangold case (Case C–144/04, Mangold, 2005 ECR I–9981), Roman Herzog & Lüder Gerken, [Comment] Stop the European Court of Justice, available at http://euobserver.com/9/26714 (2008). This piece is the translation of an article originally published in German, Stoppt den Europäischen Gerichtshof, Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung, 8 September 2008.Google Scholar

85 Case C–314/08, Filipiak, 2009 E.C.R. I–11049.Google Scholar

86 Winner Wetten, Case C–409/06.Google Scholar

88 Filipiak, Case C–314/08.Google Scholar

89 Case C–416/10, Križan & Others, (Jan. 15 2013), http://curia.europa.eu/.Google Scholar

90 Križan, Case C–416/10 at para. 47.Google Scholar

91 “Finally, as a supreme court, the Najvyšší súd Slovenskej republiky is even required to submit a request for a preliminary ruling to the Court of Justice when it finds that the substance of the dispute concerns a question to be resolved which comes within the scope of the first paragraph of Article 267 TFEU. The possibility of bringing, before the constitutional court of the Member State concerned, an action against the decisions of a national court, limited to an examination of a potential infringement of the rights and freedoms guaranteed by the national constitution or by an international agreement, cannot allow the view to be taken that that national court cannot be classified as a court against whose decisions there is no judicial remedy under national law within the meaning of the third paragraph of Article 267 TFEU. In the light of the foregoing, the answer to the first question is that Article 267 TFEU must be interpreted as meaning that a national court, such as the referring court, is obliged to make, of its own motion, a request for a preliminary ruling to the Court of Justice even though it is ruling on a referral back to it after its first decision was set aside by the constitutional court of the Member State concerned and even though a national rule obliges it to resolve the dispute by following the legal opinion of that latter court.” Id. Google Scholar

92 “The Court has concluded therefrom that the existence of a rule of national law whereby courts or tribunals against whose decisions there is a judicial remedy are bound on points of law by the rulings of a court superior to them cannot, on the basis of that fact alone, deprive the lower courts of the right provided for in Article 267 TFEU to refer questions on the interpretation of EU law to the Court of Justice (see, to that effect, Rheinmühlen-Düsseldorf, paragraphs 4 and 5, and Cartesio, paragraph 94). The lower court must be free, in particular if it considers that a higher court's legal ruling could lead it to give a judgment contrary to EU law, to refer to the Court questions which concern it (Case C-378/08 ERG and Others 2010 E.C.R. I-0000, paragraph 32).” Melki and Abdeli, Joined Cases C–188/10 and C–189/10 at para. 42.Google Scholar

93 Article 61–1states, “If, during proceedings in progress before a court of law, it is claimed that a statutory provision infringes the rights and freedoms guaranteed by the Constitution, the matter may be referred by the Conseil d'État or by the Cour de Cassation to the Constitutional Council, within a determined period. An Organic Law shall determine the conditions for the application of the present article.” On this, see Fabbrini, Federico, Kelsen in Paris: France's constitutional reform and the introduction of a posteriori constitutional review of legislation, 9 German L.J., 1297 (2008).Google Scholar

94 The saga is indeed multilevel: during a proceeding initiated by Mr. Melki and Mr. Abdeli, two Algerians, unlawfully present in France. They were arrested and put into detention after a police control carried out in an area close to the Belgian border, on the basis of Art. 78–2, p. 4, of the French Code of Criminal Procedure. The judge deciding on provisional detention decided to refer to the Court of Cassation (as we know the French Constitutional Reform gave the Court de Cassation and the Conseil d'État a role of filter of the questions raised by the lower courts) a question concerning the consistency with the French Constitution of the possibility to check the identity of persons in a border area. The referring judge had in mind Art. 88-1 of the Constitution, which reads ‘The Republic shall participate in the European Union constituted by States which have freely chosen to exercise some of their powers in common pursuant to the [Treaties]', in so far as Union law ensures the absence of internal border controls for persons. The Court de Cassation deciding on the possibility to pass the question to the French Conseil Constitutionnel, aware of the consequence on European Union law of a decision like that and doubting the mechanism of the priority of the constitutional question devised by the French Reform, raised a preliminary reference to the CJEU.Google Scholar

95 Melki, Joined Cases C–188/10 and C–189/10 at para.22Google Scholar

96 Conseil Constitutionnel [French Constitutional Council], Décision no. 2010–605 DC of 12 May 2010, available at http://www.conseil-constitutionnel.fr/decision/2010/2010-605-dc/decision-n-2010-605-dc-du-12-mai-2010.48186.html.Google Scholar

97 Case C–106/77, Simmenthal, 1977 E.C.R. I–62.Google Scholar

98 Case C–210/06, Cartesio, 2008 E.C.R. I–9641.Google Scholar

99 Conseil Constitutionnel [French Constitutional Council], Décision 2010-605 DC, available at http://www.conseilconstitutionnel.fr/decision//decision-n-2010-605-dc-du-12-mai-2010.48186.html. Francis Donnat, La Cour de Justice et la QPC: chronique d'un arrět imprévisible et imprévu, Recueil Dalloz, 1640 (2010); Fabbrini, Federico, La Corte di Giustizia si pronuncia sulla “legittimità comunitaria” del nuovo modello di giustizia costituzionale francese, Quaderni Costituzionali 4 (2010), Daniel Sarmiento, L'affaire Melki: esquisse d'un dialogue des juges constitutionnels et européens sur toile de fond française, Revue trimestrielle de droit européen 588 (2010).Google Scholar

100 Melki, Joined Cases C–188/10 and C–189/10 at para. 51.Google Scholar

101 C–314/85, Foto-Frost, 1987 E.C.R. 4199 (“It should also be observed that the priority nature of an interlocutory procedure for the review of the constitutionality of a national law, the content of which merely transposes the mandatory provisions of a European Union directive, cannot undermine the jurisdiction of the Court of Justice alone to declare an act of the European Union invalid, and in particular a directive, the purpose of that jurisdiction being to guarantee legal certainty by ensuring that EU law is applied uniformly.”).Google Scholar

102 C–457/09, Chartry, 2011 E.C.R I–00819.Google Scholar

103 Case C–112/13, A v. B., (Sept. 11, 2014), http://curia.europa.eu/. On the differences between Melki and A v. B, see Guazzarotti, Andrea, Rinazionalizzare i diritti fondamentali? Spunti a partire da Corte di Giustizia UE, A. c. B. e altri, sent. 11 settembre 2014, C–112/13, available at www.diritticomparati.it (2014).Google Scholar

104 Mangold, Case C–144/04. See Calvano, Roberta, Il caso “Mangold”: la Corte di giustizia afferma (senza dirlo) l'efficacia orizzontale di una direttiva comunitaria non scaduta?, available at www.associazionedeicostituzionalisti.it (2006).Google Scholar

105 Mangold, Case C–144/04 at para. 78.Google Scholar

106 Id. at para. 67.Google Scholar

107 Id. at para. 74.Google Scholar

108 Id. at paras. 77–78.Google Scholar

109 Hatzopoulos, Vassilis, Why the Open Method of Coordination is Bad for You: A Letter to the EU, 13 Eur. L. J. 309, 337 (2007).Google Scholar

110 Case C–60/00, Carpenter, 2002 E.C.R. I–6279.Google Scholar

111 Case C–71/02, Karner, 2004 E.C.R. I–3025.Google Scholar

112 Hatzopoulos, supra note 109, at 337.Google Scholar

113 Herzog & Gerken, supra note 84.Google Scholar

114 Dani, supra note 84.Google Scholar

115 Case C-555/07, Kücükdeveci, 2010 E.C.R. I–365.Google Scholar

116 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court] 123, 267 – Treaty of Lisbon, 2009, https://www.bundesverfassungsgericht.de/entscheidungen/es20090630_2bve000208en.html.Google Scholar

117 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court] 2 BvR 2661/06, www.bundesverfassungsgericht.de Google Scholar

118 Case C–285/98, Kreil, 2000 E.C.R. I–69.Google Scholar

119 Article 12a 4 states: “If, during a state of defence, the need for civilian services in the civilian health system or in stationary military hospitals cannot be met on a voluntary basis, women between the age of eighteen and fifty-five may be called upon to render such services by or pursuant to a law. Under no circumstances may they be required to render service involving the use of arms.”Google Scholar

120 Case C–213/07, Michaniki AE v. Ethniko Simvoulio Radiotileorasis and Ipourgos Epikratias, 2008 E.C.R. I–9999.Google Scholar

121 Article 14, p. 9 provides: “The ownership, financial standing and means of financing of the media must be disclosed, as stipulated by law. The measures and restrictions necessary to ensure full media transparency and pluralism shall be specified by law. It is prohibited to concentrate control of several media of the same or different form. In particular, it is prohibited to concentrate control of more than one electronic medium of the same form, as specified by law. The status of owner, partner, main shareholder or management executive of a media undertaking shall be incompatible with the status of owner, partner, main shareholder or management executive of an undertaking which undertakes with the State or a legal person in the public sector in the broad sense to perform works or provide supplies or services. The prohibition in the previous subparagraph shall also extend to any form of intermediary, such as spouses, relatives or financially dependent persons or companies. A law shall set out the specific regulations, the sanctions (which may go as far as revocation of a radio or television station's licence and an order prohibiting the signature of, or cancelling, the contract in question), the system of supervision and the guarantees to prevent circumvention of the foregoing subparagraphs.”Google Scholar

122 Michaniki AE, Case C–213/07 at para. 69.Google Scholar

123 On this case law, see Guastaferro, Barbara, Beyond the Exceptionalism of Constitutional Conflicts: The Ordinary Functions of the Identity Clause, 31 Y.B. Eur. L. 263 (2012).Google Scholar

124 As we know, while in the first pillar the counter-limits bomb never exploded (and this might be seen as a confirmation of the particular strength of the interpretative position of the CJEU in this context), the third pillar knew some episodes of tension between the Constitutional Courts and the CJEU: the decisions of the Polish (Trybunał konstytucyjny, P 1/05, available at www.trybunal.gov.pl/eng/index.htm) and German (BVerfG, 2 BvR 2236/04, available at www.bundesverfassungsgericht.de/enl) Constitutional Courts (but also see the decisions of the Cypriot, 294/2005, available at www.cylaw.org and Czech judges Ústavní Soud, PI. ÚS 66/04, available at http:// http://www.usoud.cz/), which have recalled the question of the ultimate barriers in the field of the European arrest warrant. Jan Komárek, European constitutionalism and the European Arrest Warrant: In search of the limits of contrapunctual principles, Jean Monnet Working Paper, 10/05 available at http://econpapers.repec.org/paper/erpjeanmo/p0250.htm (2005).Google Scholar

125 Case C–399/09, Landtová, 2011 E.C.R. I–05573.Google Scholar

126 Id. at para. 49.Google Scholar

127 Ústavní soud [Czech Constitutional Court], judgment of 31 January, PI. ÚS 5/12, Slovak Pensions XVII. The English translation is available at http:// http://www.usoud.cz/.Google Scholar

128 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court], 30 June 2009, 2 BvE 2/08, www.bundesverfassungsgericht.de/en.Google Scholar

129 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court], 26 Aug. 2010, 2 BvR 2261/06, www.bundesverfassungsgericht.de/en.Google Scholar

130 Bosphorus v. Ireland, App. No. 45036/98, (June. 30, 2005), http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/.Google Scholar

131 Tzanakopoulos, Antonios, The Solange Argument as a Justification for Disobeying the Security Council in the Kadi Judgments, in Kadi on Trial: A Multifaceted Analysis of the Kadi Trial 121 (Matej Avbelj, Filippo Fontanelli & Giuseppe Martinico eds., 2014). See also Gattini, Andrea, Joined Cases C-402/05 P & 415/05 P, Yassin Abdullah Kadi, Al Barakaat International Foundation v. Council and Commission, judgment of the Grand Chamber of 3 September 2008, 46 Common Mkt. L. Rev. 213, 234 (2009); Gordillo, supra note 31, at 235–57, 311–13.Google Scholar

132 Joined Cases C–584/10 P, C–593/10 P, and C–595/10 P, Commission, Council, United Kingdom v. Yassin Abdullah Kadi, (July 18, 2013), http://curia.europa.eu/; Joined Cases C-402/05 P and C–415/05 P, Yassin Abdullah Kadi and Al Barakaat International Foundation, 2008 ECR I–6351. On the Kadi saga, see The Multificated Analysis of the Kadi Trial, supra note 131.Google Scholar

133 Lorenzo Zucca, Monism and Fundamental Rights in Europe, available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1734602 (2011). A slightly different version was published in Philosophical Foundations of EU Law 331 (Julie Dickson & Pavlos Eleftheriadis, eds., 2012).Google Scholar

134 On this, see Fabbrini, Federico, The Euro-Crisis and the Courts: Judicial Review and the Political Process in Comparative Perspective, available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2328060 (2013); Delledonne, Giacomo, Financial Constitutions in the EU: From the Political to the Legal Constitution?, Sant'Anna Legal Studies (STALS) Research Paper 5/2012, http://stals.sssup.it/files/Delledonne%20Stals%205%202012.pdf (2012).Google Scholar

135 Bin, Roberto, Gli effetti del diritto dell'Unione nell'ordinamento italiano e il principio di entropia 363, 372-73 (2010), http://www.robertobin.it/articoli/scritti_modugno.pdf.Google Scholar

136 Foley, Michael, The Silence of Constitutions: Gaps, ‘Abeyances', and Political Temperament in the Maintenance of Government 198 (1989).Google Scholar

137 Id. at 3.Google Scholar

138 Id. 10.Google Scholar

139 Pierdominici, Leonardo, Fear of activity, fear of activism, the silence of courts. The docket and the legitimacy of the ECJ and its “Passive Virtues”, paper presented at the seminar ‘Comparative Law and Comparative Institutional Analysis', European University Institute, 23 April 2012. On file with Author.Google Scholar

140 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court], 28 Feb. 2012, 2 BvC 4/10 and BVerfG, 2 BvE 8/11. “It is in this sense that integration cannot be well understood as an autonomously “constitutional” phenomenon in its own right, as some of integration's most fervent advocates like to maintain. Rather, despite the EU's extensive normative power, the process of integration lacks the autonomous capacity to legitimize itself in democratic and constitutional terms. For that, the integration process still very much needs the nation-state and national constitutional oversight, whether legislative, executive, or judicial. The most recent decision of the German Federal Constitutional Court regarding national-parliamentary oversight is simply a concrete expression of this continuing dependence.” Peter Lindseth, National parliaments in European integration: Europeanization, renationalization, or reconciliation? (2012), available at http://eutopialaw.com/2012/03/01/national-parliaments-in-european-integration-europeanization-renationalization-or-reconciliation/.Google Scholar

141 123 BVerfgE 267.Google Scholar

142 Knight, Jack, supra note 74; Pizzorno, Alessandro, Le classi sociali (1959); Pizzorno, Alessandro, Le radici della politica assoluta (1993); Crouch, Colin & Pizzorno, Alessandro, Conflitti in Europa (1977); Dahrendorf, Ralf, Toward a Theory of Social Conflict, 2 J. Conflict Resol. 170 (1958); Dahrendorf, Ralf, Essays in the Theory of Society (1968).Google Scholar

143 Luciani, Massimo, Costituzionalismo irenico e costituzionalismo polemic (2006), available at http://archivio.rivistaaic.it/materiali/anticipazioni/costituzionalismo_irenico/index.html.Google Scholar

144 Martinico, Giuseppe, Lo spirito polemico del diritto europeo. Studio sulle ambizioni costituzionali dell'Unione (2011).Google Scholar