Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-5wvtr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-22T22:00:41.391Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Anti-Extremism, Negative Republicanism, Civic Society: Three Paradigms for Banning Political Parties

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

Restrictions on political association and expression are problematic from a democratic point view. The default assumption seems to be that democracy minimally entails that all citizens have claims to participate in the legislative programming of society, which, given the size and complexity of democratic societies, they have to realize to a significant degree as participants in the debates of a political public sphere or through their membership in and support for political organisations such as parties. If they lack such chances, political decisions will lack democratic legitimacy. Where the law prohibits such options, \“it cuts off the possibility of participating in the open ended future required by democracy. Precisely to the extent the law imposes a version of what the future can or cannot be …[people] are reduced to heteronomous subjects, instead of autonomous citizens.\” It follows that the burden of justification for future-constraining regulations on freedom of association and expression is on those who propose and favour them.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2002 by German Law Journal GbR

References

(*) The Author retains all rights to this work.Google Scholar
Post, Robert: “Dignity, Autonomy, and Democracy”, Inaugural Richard Daub Lecture at J.W. Goethe Universität Frankfurt/M., November 1999, available from atticus.igs.berkeley.edu:8880/publications/workingpapers/WP2000-11.pdf.Google Scholar
This is the approach pursued in Kretzmer, D. & Kershman Hazan, F. (eds.): Freedom of Speech and Incitement Against Democracy, The Hague etc: Kluwer 2000.Google Scholar
Anti-extremism is the broader, more inclusive notion directed against organizational as well as individual behaviour, cf. infra, fn. 29.Google Scholar
Ulrich Preuß, K.: “Notstand und Parteienverbot. Über die Geltungsbedingungen der ‘Normalverfassung'”, Kritische Justiz 32, 1999, 263-270.Google Scholar
“Indexical” expressions like “here”, “now”, “I” or “our” identify objects and situations, as it were, by pointing towards them. Indexical references are essentially relative to the participants’ point(s) of view. The term was first used by C.S. Peirce.Google Scholar
The paragraph in question reads “Art. 21.2: Parties which, by reason of their aims or the behaviour of their adherents, seek to impair or abolish the free democratic basic order or to endanger the existence of the Federal Republic of Germany are unconstitutional. The Federal Constitutional Court shall decide on the question of unconstitutionality.” The author is responsible for all translations from the German and from the Italian in this paper.Google Scholar
Claus Leggewie/Horst Meier: Republikschutz. Maßstäbe für die Verteidigung der Demokratie. Reinbek: Rowohlt 1995, 65f.Google Scholar
Proceedings of the Parliamentary Council in Jahrbuch des öffentlichen Rechts, NF, Vol. 1, 73, here quoted from Horst Meier: Parteiverbote und demokratische Republik. Zur Interpretation und Kritik von Art. 21. Abs. 2 des Grundgesetzes. Baden-Baden: Nomos 1993, 338.Google Scholar
“… was wir von ‘früher’ und von ‘drüben’ als politische Ordnung unbedingt nicht wollten”, Günter Dürig, Art. 18, Rdnr. 48ff., in Th. Maunz & G. Dürig (eds.): Grundgesetz-Kommentar, München 1958ff. (1991), cf. Meier, a.a.O., 299.Google Scholar
Stuby, Gerhard: “Das Grundgesetz - seine Entstehung, seine Veränderungen und seine Perspektiven”, in Vereinigung Demokratischer Juristen (Hg.): Das Grundgesetz. Verfassungsentwicklung und demokratische Bewegung in der BRD, Köln 1974, 9-31, 18; cf. Martin Kutscha: Verfassung und “streitbare Demokratie”. Köln: Pahl-Rugenstein 1979, 6568.Google Scholar
See infra, pt. II, text at fn. 70ff.Google Scholar
Cf. Sartori, Giovanni: Comparative Constitutional Engineering. Basingstoke etc.: Macmillan 1994.Google Scholar
Frei, Norbert: Vergangenheitspolitik. Die Anfänge der Bundesrepublik und die NS-Vergangenheit. München: dtv 1999, 343, cf. 342 fn 64 and 343 fn 69.Google Scholar
Frei, op.cit., 333, 338.Google Scholar
Frei, op.cit., 340f., 345.Google Scholar
Entscheidungen des Bundesverfassungsgerichts (BVerfGE) (Decisions of the Federal Constitutional Court). Vol. 2, Tübingen: Mohr 1953, 12f.Google Scholar
BverfGE Vol. 5, Tübingen: Mohr 1956, 141.Google Scholar
BverfGE 5, 134, 135.Google Scholar
Loewenstein, Karl: “Militant Democracy and Fundamental Rights”, American Political Science Review XXXI, 1937, 417ff., 638ff., 432.Google Scholar
Cf. Becker, Jürgen: “§ 167. Die wehrhafte Demokratie des Grundgesetzes”, in J. Isensee/P. Kirchhof (eds.): Handbuch des Staatsrechts der BRD, vol. VII, Heidelberg 1992, 310ff., who lists its self-contradictory character as part of a “specifically German imprint” the constitution bears.Google Scholar
“If the state abstains from intervention, it could leave political space to extremism and thereby weaken democracy. However, if it actualizes its entire repressive potential, the consequence could be the silent weakening of democratic rights by the state.” Hans-Gerd Jaschke: “Rechtsstaat und Rechtsextremismus”, in Wilfried Schubarth/Richard Stöss (eds.): Rechtsextremismus in der Bundesrepublik Deutschland: Eine Bilanz. Bonn: Bundeszentrale für politische Bildung 2000, 314-332. Jaschke therefore calls this a “permanent dilemma”, 315. Kathrin Groh: “Der NPD-Verbotsantrag - eine Reanimation der streitbaren Demokratie?”, Zeitschrift für Rechtspolitik 33, 2000, 500-505, 504, sees an “antinomy” between abridging democratic freedoms and sustaining a free democratic polity.Google Scholar
BverfGE 5, 137.Google Scholar
Böckenförde, E.-W.: “Demokratie als Verfassungsprinzip”, in Böckenförde: Staat, Verfassung, Demokratie. Studien zur Verfassungstheorie und zum Verfassungsrecht. Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp 1991, 289-378, 342.Google Scholar
A distinction proposed in pre-NS writings by Carl Schmitt. Cf. the close and entirely convincing parallel reading of the Court's KPD opinion and Schmitt's Legalität und Legitimität by Horst Meier, Parteiverbote, op.cit‥, 87. See Carl Schmitt: Legalität und Legitimität (1932), Berlin: Duncker & Humblot 1993, 32.Google Scholar
BverfGE 5, 143.Google Scholar
See supra, text at fn. 16.Google Scholar
Cf. the discussion in Meier, Parteiverbote, op.cit., 291-294.Google Scholar
BverfGE 2, 12f.Google Scholar
BverfGE 2, 12f. The reason I do not speak of an anti-totalitarian but of an anti-extremist paradigm is that the concept of extremism is not only broader but has an individualizing tendency (which makes it more useful in the context of a political qualification for civil service, the so-called Berufsverbote). Individual citizens cannot coherently be labelled “totalitarian”, but “extremist”. While a “totalitarian” danger is always that of the possible takeover of state institutions, an “extremist” danger can exist where there is no chance to prevail in a political struggle for power. Extremism therefore is a more flexible concept which captures the decentralisation and fragmentation of society, and which might well be able to survive the demise of totalitarian regimes.Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl: Der Begriff des Politischen, 1932 version, Berlin: Duncker & Humblot 1991, pp. 2629, 47. Cf. the exact parallel in the case of “Berufsverbote“ under the so-called radicals decree, where the centrist lawyer E.W. Böckenförde speaks of “innerstaatliche Feinderklärung“. “Rechtsstaatliche politische Selbstverteidigung als Problem”, in E.W. Böckenförde et al. (eds.): Extremisten und öffentlicher Dienst: Rechtslage und Praxis des Zugangs zum und die Entlassung aus dem öffentlichen Dienst in Westeuropa, USA, Jugoslawien und der EG. Baden-Baden: Nomos-Verlagsgesellschaft 1981, 9-33, 10.Google Scholar
Backes, Uwe und Jesse, Eckhard: “Antiextremistischer Konsens - Prinzipien und Praxis”, Jahrbuch Extremismus und Demokratie 12, 2000, 13-30, 14f., cf. Uwe Backes: Politischer Extremismus in demokratischen Verfassungsstaaten, Opladen 1989.Google Scholar
Cf. John Locke on the basis of the concept of personal identity, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, vol. ii, chap. XXVII.Google Scholar
For a critique of the research program on “extremism” based on the view that there is no single phenomenon to investigate cf. Kopke, C. & Rensmann, L.: “Die Extremismus-Formel”, Blätter für deutsche und internationale Politik 45, 12, 2000, 1451-62. For the related criticism that “anti-extremism” thrives on the assumption of a “symmetry of danger” which is out of proportion, and that it assimilates the fundamentally distinct motivations of “anti-capitalist” left-wing and “anti-democratic” right-wing extremism to each other, see G. Neugebauer: “Extremismus - Rechtsextremismus - Linksextremismus: Einige Anmerkungen zu Begriffen, Forschungskonzepten, Forschungsfragen und Forschungsergebnissen”, in W. Schubarth/R. Stöss (eds.), op.cit, 13-37, 22.Google Scholar
Prantl, Heribert: “Karlsruhe macht den Bock zum Gärtner”, Süddeutsche Zeitung v. 5.2.02 (against playing down the dangers of right wing extremism); Christian Semler: “NPD-Experten als Sozialistenfresser”, taz v. 7.2.02 (criticizing an identification of right- and left-wing extremism).Google Scholar
Sartori, G., Constitutional Engineering, op.cit.Google Scholar
Oberndörfer, Dieter: “Germany's militant democracy”, in Kretzmer/Kershman Hazan (eds.), Incitement, op.cit., 237ff., 242.Google Scholar
Cf. Backes, Uwe/ Jesse, Eckhard: “Die ‘Extremismus-Formel’ - Zur Fundamentalkritik an einem historisch-politischen Konzept”, in Jahrbuch Extremismus und Demokratie 13, 2001, 13-29, 28, and Backes/Jesse: “Antiextremistischer Konsens - Prinzipien und Praxis”, Jahrbuch Extremismus und Demokratie 12, 2000, 13-30, 15.Google Scholar
Meier, Parteiverbote, op.cit., 121-3.Google Scholar
Cobler, S.: “Das Gesetz gegen die ‘Auschwitzlüge’ - Anmerkungen zu einem rechtspolitischen Ablaßhandel”, Kritische Justiz 18, 1985, 159-170, 169.Google Scholar
Nolte, Ernst: “Between Myth and Revisionism. The Third Reich in the Perspective of the 1980s”, in H.W. Koch (ed.), Aspects of the Third Reich, London 1985, 16ff.Google Scholar
Cf. Habermas, Jürgen: “Apologetische Tendenzen”, in Habermas: Eine Art Schadensabwicklung, Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp 1987, 120-136, 131.Google Scholar
Preuß, U.K.: “Notstand und Parteienverbot”, op.cit., 270.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen: “Antworten auf Fragen einer Enquete-Kommission”, in Habermas: Die neue Normalität einer Berliner Republik, Frankfurt/M: Suhrkamp 1995, 46-61, 52.Google Scholar
Pasquino, Gianfranco: “The demise of the First Fascist Regime and Italy's Transition to Democracy, 1943-48”, in G. O'Donnell, P. Schmitter and L. Whitehead (eds.): Transitions from Authoritarian Rule: Southern Europe. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP 1986, 48, 66.Google Scholar
“… perché si deve escludere dalla democrazia chi ha manifestato di essere il suo nemico”, Atti A.C., vol. I, 703, quoted from Fulvio Fennuci: “I partiti politici nel dibatto all'assemblea costituente”, in Convivenza nella libertà. Napoli 1999, Vol. 1, 513-526, 514.Google Scholar
Atti A.C. I, 704, Fenucci, op.cit., 514.Google Scholar
For details on the case against “Ordine Nuovo” cf. Vezio Crisafulli & Livio Paladin: Commentario breve alla Costituzione, Padova: Cedam 1990, 824-826.Google Scholar
Lanchester, Fulco, “Die Institution der politischen Partei in Italien”, in D. Th. Tsatsos, D. Schefold, H.-P. Schneider (eds.): Parteienrecht im europäischen Vergleich. Baden-Baden: Nomos 1990, 370-434, 417. Cf. also Crisafulli & Paladin, Commentario, op.cit., 824: Art. XII “makes reference to Fascism as a phenomenon liable to historical individuation and determination”.Google Scholar
In order to explain historically the Italian-German asymmetry, one would also have to refer to quantitative differences. Whereas Communism had a mass basis in Italy, although not as massive as Togliatti had thought it to be, it was not sufficiently popular in West Germany in order to withdraw, after its exclusion, significant support from the constitution. As against earlier work on the KPD in the constitutional history of the Federal Republic (Kutscha, Verfassung, op.cit.), it seems also plausible to give a contractualist explanation. In Germany the KPD had not been part of the arco costituzionale, as the KPD delegates (like, by the way, the Bavarian delegation), had rejected the Basic Law, ostensibly for the reason that it was going to make German unification more difficult (Meier, Parteiverbote, 50).Google Scholar
Bobbio, Norberto: “Origine e caratteri della costituzione”, in Bobbio: Dal fascismo alla democrazia, Milano: Baldini & Castoldi 1997, 159-183, 167f.Google Scholar
Bobbio, N.: “Dialogue with Renzo de Felice”, in N. Bobbio, R. de Felice, G.E. Rusconi, Italiani, amici nemici. Milano: Reset 1996, 9-54, 11, cf. Bobbio: “Il regime fascista”, in Bobbio, Dal fascismo, op.cit., 37ff., 37-39.Google Scholar
But see the striking parallelism between banning the reconstitution of the Fascist party in Art. XII and banning the members of the monarchic dynasty of the Savoyans from Italian territory in Art. XIII of the Constitution's Final Dispositions.Google Scholar
There is one exception to this diagnosis, namely that “dissemination of racist propaganda” has subsequently been identified as one instrument of reorganizing the Fascist party (§ 1 of the “Scelba” statute, n. 645 of 20.6.1952), which means that at least one substantive criterion has been introduced into the conception of the anti-democratic character of Italian fascism.Google Scholar
as stated by Renzo de Felice in an interview with Giuliano Ferrara, Corriere della Sera, 27.12.1987, repr. in Società é critica, 37-40, 1989, 74f.Google Scholar
Bobbio, N.: “Preferite questa democrazia o la migliore delle dittature?”, Corriere della Sera 29.12.1987, repr. in Società é critica, 37-40, 1989, 78.Google Scholar
E.g. Bovero, Michelangelo: “Fascismo e democrazia nel pensiero di Norberto Bobbio”, in Bobbio, op.cit., 7-34, 22.Google Scholar
Loewenstein, , “Militant Democracy”, op.cit., 432.Google Scholar
Ibid. Loewenstein does rule out the legitimacy of suppressing only communism and not fascism, but not the reverse. Op.cit., ibid.Google Scholar
See the Court's Pronuncie 0254, 1974, Nr. 7468, and 0015, 1973, Nr. 6569.Google Scholar
Barile, Paolo & Siervo, Ugo De: “Sanzioni contro il Fascismo ed il Neofascismo”, Novissimo Digesto Italiano, vol. XVI, Torino 1969, 542-564, 562. Alessandro Pizzorusso: “Art. XII” in Pizzorusso & Branca: Commentario della Costituzione, Bologna: Zanichelli 1995, 197-202, 198; Barile: Libertà di manifestazione del pensiero, Milano: Giuffré 1975, 107 fn. 93.Google Scholar
Cf. e.g. Tranfaglia, Nicola: Un passato scomodo. Fascismo e postfascismo. Bari: Laterza 1999, 103f., 97-99.Google Scholar
Ritterspach, Theodor (Judge at the Federal Constitutional Court): “Referat”, in Die Stellung der politischen Partein in der Verfassung, Verhandlungen des 2. Deutsch-Italienischen Juristenkongresses vom 26.-28.9.1968 in Berlin, Karlsruhe: Müller 1969, 27-46, 30.Google Scholar
Cassandro, Giovanni (former Judge at the Italian Constitutional Court): “Referat”, in Stellung der politischen Parteien, a.a.O., 47-61, 53; cf. Lanchester, “Die Institution”, op.cit., 416f.Google Scholar
Leggewie, /Meier, , Republikschutz, op.cit., 308. The passages referred to condense the views expressed in Meier, Parteiverbote, op.cit., 396ff.Google Scholar
All quotations from Leggewie/Meier, Republikschutz, op.cit., 313 and 317.Google Scholar
Margalit, Avishai & Motzkin, Gabriel: “The Uniqueness of the Holocaust”, Philosophy and Public Affairs 25, 1, Summer 1996, pp. 6583.Google Scholar
On singularity as liability (“Unvertretbarkeit der uns zugemuteten Haftung”) see Habermas, J.: “Vom öffentlichen Gebrauch der Historie”, in Habermas, Eine Art Schadensabwicklung, op.cit., 144.Google Scholar
See Collotti, Enzo: “Die Historiker und die Rassengesetze in Italien”, in C. Dipper et al. (eds.): Faschismus und Faschismen im Vergleich. Köln: SH 1998, 59-77. Cf. Wolfgang Wippermann: “Hat es Faschismus überhaupt gegeben? Der generische Faschismusbegriff zwischen Kritik und Antikritik”, Ethik und Sozialwissenschaften 11, 2000, 289-296, 292.Google Scholar
Thus the subtitle of the influential volume by Collotti, E. (ed.): Fascismo e antifascismo. Roma, Bari: Laterza 2000. For De Felice's contributions cf. supra fn. 51 and the literature mentioned in that volume.Google Scholar
I quote from the manuscript of the party ban motion (Verbotsantrag) authorized by the German Bundestag, on file with its authors, Frankfurt/M. and Bonn 2001, 36.Google Scholar
Even Meier concedes that its result is acceptable not only politically, but “as a matter of constitutional law”. Parteiverbote, op.cit., 409. However, it must be conceded that there exists a long list of abortive attempts to justify anti-NS “Sonderrecht“ from the Basic Law. Historically, the most prominent line of thought relies on the “transitory disposition” of Art. 139 (postulating the continuing validity of immediate post-war de-Nazification statutes). The final nail into the coffin of such attempts is Gertrud Lübbe-Wolff: “Zur Bedeutung des Art. 139 GG für die Auseinandersetzung mit neonazistischen Gruppen”, Neue Juristische Wochenschrift 1988, 1289ff.Google Scholar
BverfGE 2, 6570.Google Scholar
“There is no doubt that the former NSDAP, in a retrospective grasp of its development, would, as a currently existing party, be unconstitutional according to Art. 21.2; as it is the experiences with this party which gave rise to the establishment of Art. 21.2”. BverfGE 2, 70.Google Scholar
Frankenberg/Löwer devote the first and more substantive part of their motion to the demonstration of the NPD's essential affinity to the NSDAP (91-183). In the second part, they argue that also for reasons unrelated to its Nazi-affinity, the NPD should be banned: because of its “violation of the free democratic basic order” (184-278). However, it should be pointed out that “Wesensverwandtschaft“ is a sufficient reason to ban a party because it automatically demonstrates a violation of the free democratic basic order.Google Scholar
See the comprehensive study by Ignazi, Piero: Il Polo Escluso, Bologna: Mulino 1989.Google Scholar
Valiani, Leo: “Il no al fascismo resti nella Costituzione”, Corriere della Sera, 21.1.1988, repr. in Società é Critica 37-40, 1988, 81.Google Scholar
On content- and viewpoint-based restrictions of political liberties cf. Cass Sunstein: Democracy and the Problem of Free Speech, New York: Free Press 1993, 167ff.Google Scholar
The phrase comes from Preuß, Ulrich K.: Legalität und Pluralismus, Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp 1973, 163f. and passim. For Leggewie/Meier's use of the phrase cf. Republikschutz, op.cit, 317, for Frankenberg/Löwer's see Verbotsantrag, 86.Google Scholar
Leggewie, /Meier, , Republikschutz, op.cit., 314.Google Scholar
Despite disagreement as to its “essentially affine” character, there is substantial agreement on this point between Preuß, Ulrich K.: “Die empfindsame Demokratie”, Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung, 22.8.2000, 51; Frankenberg/Löwer, Verbotsantrag, and the recent work by Horst Meier: “‘Ob eine konkrete Gefahr besteht, ist belanglos’. Kritik der Verbotsanträge der NPD”, in Claus Leggewie/Horst Meier (eds.): Verbot der NPD oder: Mit Rechtsradikalen leben? Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp 2002, 14-29, 18.Google Scholar
Cf. the contributions in Schubarth, W./Stöss, R. (eds.), op.cit., supra fn. 21.Google Scholar
Another category of direct harms emanating from NS successor parties would be that of harms to the symbolic integrity of the republic. Although there are significant liberal objections to be considered, I think that legal measures to avert such harms should not be in principle ruled out, but cannot pursue the matter here. For an illuminating related discussion of permissible symbolic functions of hate speech law see Robert Post: “Racist Speech, Democracy, and the First Amendment”, in Henry Louis Gates et al.: Speaking of Race, Speaking of Sex. Hate Speech, Civil Rights, and Civil Liberties. New York: New York UP 1994, 115-180.Google Scholar
Cf. Verbotsantrag, op.cit., 260-267.Google Scholar
Cem Özdemir (Green Party), member of the Bundestag, in the parliamentary debate on the NPD ban motion of Dec. 8, 2000, quoted in Frankenberg/Löwer, Verbotsantrag, op.cit. 73.Google Scholar
Rühl, Ulli F.: “Versammlungsrechtliche Maßnahmen gegen rechtsradikale Demonstrationen und Aufzüge zur Versammlungsfreiheit”, Neue Juristische Wochenschrift 1995, 561ff., 564.Google Scholar
In the German Penal Code, the display of Nazi symbols is outlawed by a concrete reference to National Socialism in the text of StGB 86a (1). One advantage of the negative republican paradigm is that it seems to be the only conception to make constitutional sense of this provision.Google Scholar