Hostname: page-component-76dd75c94c-qmf6w Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-30T09:11:19.618Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Assistance with Fewer Strings Attached

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 September 2012

Abstract

International organizations and bilateral donors often tie financial assistance to the undertaking of political and economic reforms–a practice known as conditionality. In recent years, the use of good governance conditionality has provoked controversy in the academic and policy worlds. So far, the issue of whether conditionality is effective in achieving compliance with good governance norms has occupied center stage in the debate. However, whether it is morally defensible to attach political conditions to financial assistance has largely been taken for granted.

This article explores the extent to which it is morally defensible to attach good governance conditions to aid and loans in international society. It argues that the use of conditionality should be limited for two reasons. First, there is an unavoidable tension between conditionality and rights to self-determination. Second, focusing on conditionality can obscure the fact that the rules of the international economy are no less contestable than the governance of individual states, and, in turn, are in just as great a need of reform. This leads to two main conclusions. First, the use of conditionality should now be rooted in a conception of basic rights and complemented by more equitable rules in the global economy. Second, the attempt to make good governance within states an issue of global concern must be accompanied by greater democratization of the international financial institutions.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Carnegie Council for Ethics in International Affairs 2003

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 For a more detailed discussion of conditionality, see Stokke, Olav, “Core Issues and State of the Art,” in Stokke, Olav, ed., Aid and Political Conditionality (London: Frank Cass, 1995), pp. 187Google Scholar.

2 See Johnson, John H. and Wasty, Sulaiman S., “Borrower Ownership of Adjustment Programs and the Political Economy of Reform” (Washington, D.C.: World Bank, 1993CrossRefGoogle Scholar), which argues that ownership is vital for providing credibility to policies, safeguarding against policy reversals, and ensuring sustainability of benefits.

3 See, e.g., Killick, Tony, Aid and the Political Economy of Policy Change (London: Routledge, 1998), p. 16Google Scholar.

4 Feldstein, Martin, “Refocusing the IMF,” Foreign Affairs 77 (1998), p. 27CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Quoted in Riddell, Roger, Foreign Aid Reconsidered (London: James Currey, 1987), p. 62Google Scholar.

7 See Hewitt, Adrian and Killick, Tony, “Bilateral Aid Conditionality and Policy Leverage,” in Stokke, Olav, ed., Foreign Aid towards the Year 2000: Experiences and Challenges (London: Frank Cass, 1996), pp. 130–67Google Scholar.

9 Clapham, Christopher S., Africa and the International System: The Politics of State Survival (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), p. 3CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 See Jackson, Robert H., Quasi-states: Sovereignty, International Relations, and the Third World (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), p. 44Google Scholar.

11 Singer, Peter, “Famine, Affluence, and Morality,” in Beitz, Charles R. et al. , eds., International Ethics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985), pp. 247–62Google Scholar.

12 Ibid., p. 249Google Scholar.

13 Rawls, John, The Law of Peoples (London: Harvard University Press, 1999), pp. 105–13Google Scholar.

14 Singer, Peter, quoted in Andrew Kuper, “More than Charity: Cosmopolitan Alternatives to the ‘Singer Solution,”’ Ethics & International Affairs 16, no. 1(2002), p. 115Google Scholar.

15 See ibid, pp. 107–20. On the problems of giving aid in conflict-ridden countries, see, e.g., Boyce, James K., “Investing in Peace: Aid and Conditionality after Civil Wars,” Adelphi Paper 351 (2002Google Scholar); Anderson, Mary B., Do No Harm: How Aid Can Support Peace—or War (Boulder, Colo.: Lynne Rienner, 1999Google Scholar); Uvin, Peter, Aiding Violence: The Development Enterprise in Rwanda (West Hartford, Conn.: Kumarian Press, 1998Google Scholar); and Terry, Fiona, Condemned to Repeat? The Paradox of Humanitarian Action (London: Cornell University Press, 2002Google Scholar).

16 Dudley Seers and G. Myrdal, “The Withering of Aid,”Guardian, July 2,1982, quoted in Riddell, , Foreign Aid Reconsidered, p. 53Google Scholar.

17 Seers, Dudley, “What Types of Government Should Be Refused What Types of Aid?IDS Bulktin 4 (1972), pp. 1415Google Scholar.

18 Ibid., p. 7Google Scholar.

19 John Rawls's The Law of Peoples, e.g., distinguishes between rules governing relations between liberal states and rules governing relations between liberal and non-liberal states.

20 Pogge, Thomas W., “The Moral Demands of Global Justice,” Dissent (Fall 2000), p. 42Google Scholar.

21 See Shue, Henry, Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy, 2nd ed. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), p. 173–80Google Scholar.

22 Collier, Paul, “Learning from Failure: The International Financial Institutions as Agencies of Restraint in Africa,” in Schedler, Andreas, Diamond, Larry, and Plattner, Marc F., eds., The Self-Restraining State: Power and Accountability in New Democracies (Boulder, Colo.: Lynne Rienner, 1999), p. 319Google Scholar. It should be stressed that the international financial institutions have recognized that the logistical burdens of conditionally have contributed to its ineffectiveness, and are in the process of reviewing their use of conditionality.

23 See, e.g., International Development Association and IMF, “Review of the Poverty Reduction Strategy Paper (PRSP) Approach: Main Findings,” March 15, 2002; available at http://www.imf.org/external/np/prspgen/review/2002/031502a.htm. See also related documents at poverty. http://worldbank.org/prsp.

24 See, e.g., the criticisms in EURODAD, “Many Dollars, Any Change? Part I: The Changing Nature of Development Co-operation: Buildling Ownership” (Belgium: Eurodad, 2001); available at http://www.eurodad.org/uploadstore/cms/docs/eurodad_manydollarsanychange_parti.pdf.

25 See Carlos Santiso, “Governance Conditionality and the Reform of Multilateral Development Finance: The Role of the Group of Eight,” p. 11; available at http://www.wtowatch.org/library/admin/uploadedfiles/Governance_Conditionality_and_the_Reform_of_Mu.pdf.

26 Feldstein, “Refocusing the IMF,” p. 27.

27 Killick, Tony, “The ‘Streamlining’ of IMF Conditionality: Aspirations, Reality and Repercussions. A Report for the Department for International Development” (London: Overseas Development Institute, 2002Google Scholar); available at http://www.brettonwoodsproject.org/topic/adjustment/condikillick.pdf.

28 Killick, Aid and the Political Economy of Policy Change.

29 For example, foreign direct investment (FDI) in Africa in 2001 was $17 billion, but most of this was concentrated in Morocco and South Africa. By contrast, FDI in Asia was about $100 billion, and figures for the EU exceeded $300 billion. United Nations Conference on Trade and Development, World Investment Report 2002 (New York: United Nations, 2002Google Scholar).

30 Walzer, Michael, Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1994), p. xGoogle Scholar.

31 See, e.g., Hinsley, F. H., Sovereignty, 2nd ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986Google Scholar).

32 Walzer, Michael, Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations, 3rd ed. (New York: Basic Books, 2000), p. 54Google Scholar.

33 Ibid., p. 68Google Scholar.

34 Walzer, Thick and Thin, especially ch.1.

35 Walzer, Michael, “The Moral Standing of States: A Response to Four Critics,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 9, no. 3 (1980), pp. 209–29Google Scholar.

36 Walzer, Michael, “Arguing for Humanitarian Intervention,” in Mills, Nicolaus and Brunner, Kira, eds., The New Killing Fields: Massacre and the Politics of Intervention (New York: Basic Books, 2002), p. 21Google Scholar.

37 Recent research suggests that fostering “ownership” is more likely to lead to better implementation of reforms than coercive conditionality. See Killick, Aid and the Political Economy of Policy Change.

38 This is Feldstein's argument with respect to the IMF and South Korea. Feldstein, “Refocusing the IMF.”

39 See Hans Singer, quoted in Riddell, Foreign Aid Reconsidered, pp. 37–38.

40 Pogge, Thomas W., World Poverty and Human Rights: Cosmopolitan Responsibilities and Reforms (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2002Google Scholar).

41 Pogge, Thomas W., “Rawls on International Justice,” Philosophical Quarterly 51, no. 203 (April 2001), p. 253CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

42 See Shue, Basic Rights.

43 See also Hurrell, Andrew, “Global Inequality and International Institutions,” Metaphilosophy 32, no. 1–2 (2001), p. 49CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

44 See Miller, David L., “Justice and Inequality,” in Hurrell, Andrew and Woods, Ngaire, eds., Inequality, Globalization and World Politics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 202203Google Scholar.

45 Walzer, Michael, “Governing the Globe,” Dissent (Fall 2000), pp. 4452Google Scholar.

46 See Woods, Ngaire, “Making the IMF and the World Bank More Accountable,” International Affairs 77, no. 1 (2001), pp. 83100CrossRefGoogle Scholar.