Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-xm8r8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-16T00:47:22.808Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Shared Epistemic Responsibility

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 August 2019

Boyd Millar*
Affiliation:
Washington University in St. Louis, USA
*
*Corresponding author. Email: millar.boyd@gmail.com

Abstract

It is widely acknowledged that individual moral obligations and responsibility entail shared (or joint) moral obligations and responsibility. However, whether individual epistemic obligations and responsibility entail shared epistemic obligations and responsibility is rarely discussed. Instead, most discussions of doxastic responsibility focus on individuals considered in isolation. In contrast to this standard approach, I maintain that focusing exclusively on individuals in isolation leads to a profoundly incomplete picture of what we're epistemically obligated to do and when we deserve epistemic blame. First, I argue that we have epistemic obligations to perform actions of the sort that can be performed in conjunction with other people, and that consequently, we are often jointly blameworthy when we violate shared epistemic obligations. Second, I argue that shared responsibility is especially important to doxastic responsibility thanks to the fact that we don't have the same kind of direct control over our beliefs that we have over our actions. In particular, I argue that there are many cases in which a particular individual who holds some problematic belief only deserves epistemic blame in virtue of belonging to a group all the members of which are jointly blameworthy for violating some shared epistemic obligation.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2019

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alston, W. (1985). ‘Concepts of Epistemic Justification.’ The Monist 68, 5789.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alston, W. (1988). ‘The Deontological Conception of Epistemic Justification.’ Philosophical Perspectives 2, 257–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Axtell, G. (2011). ‘Recovering Responsibility.Logos and Episteme 3, 429–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beerbohm, E. (2012). In Our Name: The Ethics of Democracy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Brady, M. and Fricker, M. (eds) (2016). The Epistemic Life of Groups: Essays in the Epistemology of Collectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dougherty, T. (2010). ‘Reducing Responsibility: An Evidentialist Account of Epistemic Blame.’ European Journal of Philosophy 20, 534–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feldman, R. (2002). ‘Epistemological Duties.’ In Moser, P. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology, pp. 362–84. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fienberg, J. (1968). ‘Collective Responsibility.’ Journal of Philosophy 65, 674–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, M. (2016). ‘Fault and No-Fault Responsibility for Implicit Prejudice: A Space for Epistemic ‘Agent-Regret’.’ In Brady, M. and Fricker, M. (eds), The Epistemic Life of Groups: Essays in the Epistemology of Collectives, pp. 3350. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. (1988). ‘Strong and Weak Justification.’ Philosophical Perspectives 2, 5169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, A. (2017). The Social Contexts of Intellectual Virtue. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hall, R. and Johnson, C. (1998). ‘The Epistemic Duty to Seek More Evidence.’ American Philosophical Quarterly 35, 129–39.Google Scholar
Hedberg, T. (2014). ‘Epistemic Supererogation and Its Implications.’ Synthese 191, 3621–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Held, V. (1970). ‘Can a Random Collection of Individuals be Morally Responsible?Journal of Philosophy 67, 471–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hieronymi, P. (2008). ‘Responsibility for Believing.’ Synthese 161, 357–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huebner, B. (2014). Macrocognition: A Theory of Distributed Minds and Collective Intentionality. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kim, K. (1994). ‘The Deontological Conception of Epistemic Justification and Doxastic Voluntarism.’ Analysis 54, 282–4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kornblith, H. (1983). ‘Justified Belief and Epistemically Responsible Action.’ Philosophical Review 92, 3348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, J. (ed.) (2014). Essays in Collective Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leon, M. (2002). ‘Responsible Believers.’ The Monist 85, 421–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levy, N. (2017). ‘The Bad News About Fake News.’ Social Epistemology Review & Reply Collective 6, 2036.Google Scholar
Levy, N. (2018). ‘Socializing Responsibility.’ In Hutchison, K., Mackenzie, C. and Oshana, M. (eds), Social Dimensions of Moral Responsibility, pp. 185205. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google ScholarPubMed
Levy, N. and Mandelbaum, E. (2014). ‘The Powers that Bind: Doxastic Voluntarism and Epistemic Obligation.’ In Matheson, J. and Vitz, R. (eds), The Ethics of Belief: Individual and Social, pp. 1532. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
May, L. (1992). Sharing Responsibility. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Mellema, G. (2016). Complicity and Moral Accountability. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meylan, A. (2015). ‘The Legitimacy of Intellectual Praise and Blame.’ Journal of Philosophical Research 40, 189203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, S. (2001). ‘Collective Moral Responsibility for Omissions.’ Business and Professional Ethics Journal 20, 524.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, S. (2008). ‘Collective Responsibility and Information and Communication Technology.’ In van den Hoven, J. and Weckert, J. (eds), Information Technology and Moral Philosophy, pp. 226–50. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, S. (2015). ‘Joint Epistemic Action and Collective Moral Responsibility.’ Social Epistemology 29, 280302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, S. and Makela, P. (2005). ‘The Collectivist Approach to Collective Moral Responsibility.’ Metaphilosophy 36, 634–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Narveson, J. (2002). ‘Collective Responsibility.’ Journal of Ethics 6, 179–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nottelmann, N. (2007). Blameworthy Belief: A Study in Epistemic Deontologism. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Palermos, O. and Pritchard, D. (2016). ‘The Distribution of Epistemic Agency.’ In Reider, P. (ed.), Social Epistemology and Epistemic Agency: Decentralizing Epistemic Agency, pp. 109–26. London: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Peels, R. (2017). Responsible Belief: A Theory in Ethics and Epistemology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rüdiger, P. (ed.) (2016). Cognitive Illusions: Intriguing Phenomena in Thinking, Judgment, and Memory, 2nd edition. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (2001). ‘Epistemic and Moral Duty.’ In Steup, M. (ed.), Knowledge, Truth, and Duty: Essays on Epistemic Justification, Responsibility, and Virtue, pp. 3448. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steup, M. (1988). ‘The Deontic Conception of Epistemic Justification.’ Philosophical Studies 53, 6584.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sverdlik, S. (1987). ‘Collective Responsibility.’ Philosophical Studies 51, 6176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tidman, P. (1996). ‘Critical Reflection: An Alleged Epistemic Duty.’ Analysis 56, 268–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Woudenberg, R. (2009). ‘Ignorance and Force: Two Excusing Conditions for False Beliefs.’ American Philosophical Quarterly 46, 373–86.Google Scholar