Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-x5gtn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-18T01:05:54.353Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

“FILLING IN”, THOUGHT EXPERIMENTS AND INTUITIONS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 July 2016

Abstract

Recently Timothy Williamson has argued that characterizations of the standard (i.e. intuition-based) philosophical practice of philosophical analysis are misguided because of the erroneous manner in which this practice has been understood. In doing so he implies that experimental critiques of the reliability of intuition are based on this misunderstanding of philosophical methodology and so have little or no bearing on actual philosophical practice or results. His main point is that the orthodox understanding of philosophical methodology is incorrect in that it treats philosophical thought experiments in such a way that they can be “filled in” in various ways that undermines their use as counter-examples and that intuition plays no substantial role in philosophical practice when we properly understand that methodology as a result of the possibility of such filling in. In this paper Williamson's claim that philosophical thought experiments cases can be legitimately filled in this way will be challenged and it will be shown that the experimental critique of the intuition-based methods involved a serious issue.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Brown, J. 1991. The Laboratory of the Mind. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Gendler, T. 2004. ‘Thought Experiments Rethought – and Reperceived.’ Philosophy of Science, 71: 1152–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gettier, E. 1963. ‘Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?Analysis, 23: 121–23.Google Scholar
Ichikawa, J. 2009. ‘Knowing the Intuition and Knowing the Counterfactual.’ Philosophical Studies, 145: 435–43.Google Scholar
Ichikawa, J. and Jarvis, B. 2009. ‘Thought Experiments and Truth in Fiction.’ Philosophical Studies, 142: 221–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mach, E. 1960. The Science of Mechanics. La Salle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Stevin, S. 1955. The Principal Works of Simon Stevin. Amsterdam: Swets and Zeitlinger.Google Scholar
Weinberg, J. 2007. ‘How to Challenge Intuitions Empirically Without Risking Skepticism.’ Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 31: 318–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weinberg, J., Nichols, S. and Stich, S. 2001. ‘Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions.’ Philosophical Topics, 29: 429–60.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2000. Knowledge and its Limits (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2007. The Philosophy of Philosophy (London: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2009. ‘Replies to Ichikawa, Martin and Weinberg.’ Philosophical Studies, 145: 465–76.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2011. ‘Philosophical Expertise and the Burden of Proof.’ Metaphilosophy, 42: 215–29.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2016. ‘Knowing by Imagining.’ In Kind, A. and Kung, P. (eds), Knowledge Through Imagination, pp. 113–23. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar