Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-4rdpn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-18T18:15:44.875Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

WHITE TIME

The Chronic Injustice of Ideal Theory1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 July 2014

Charles W. Mills*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Northwestern University
*
Corresponding author: Professor Charles W. Mills, Department of Philosophy, Northwestern University, 1880 Campus Drive, Kresge 2–335, Evanston, IL 60208. E-mail: c-mills@northwestern.edu

Abstract

The racialization of space is the subject of a huge body of literature, most recently in George Lipsitz’s (2011) How Racism Takes Place. But less has been done on the ways in which time could be racialized. Inspired by provocative treatments of the subject in writings by Michael Hanchard (1999) and Lawrie Balfour (2011), I suggest in this paper that we need to explore the workings of a “White temporal imaginary” analogous to Lipsitz’s “White spatial imaginary,” which likewise serves to protect White racial privilege from the threatening encroachments of racial justice. Using Eviatar Zerubavel’s (2003) Time Maps as a jumping-off point, I argue accordingly for the recognition of a “White time,” a “sociomental” representation of temporality shaped by the interests and experience of the White “mnemonic community.” The concept is obviously one of potentially very general usefulness, but in this essay I seek to apply it specifically to the dominant discourse on justice in political philosophy, as framed for the past forty years by John Rawls’ ([1971] 1999c) “ideal theory.” The relevance to the postracial theme of this issue is that, because of the peculiarity of philosophy as a discipline, it can claim it was always, or always-already, postracial, dealing as it ostensibly does with the (timeless) human condition as such. By making ideal theory—the normative theory of a perfectly just society—central to the conceptualization of social justice, by never exploring how radically different actual societies are from the ideal of society as “a cooperative venture for mutual advantage,” an exclusionary sociohistorical framework is established that makes the Euro-time of the West—abstracted out of the West’s relations of domination over people of color—the Greenwich Mean Time of normativity, while the alternative non-White temporality of structurally unjust societies requiring rectificatory racial justice remains a subject permanently untimely.

Type
Race in a “Postracial” Epoch
Copyright
Copyright © Hutchins Center for African and African American Research 2014 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Abbey, Ruth (Ed.) (2013). Feminist Interpretations of John Rawls. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
Andrews, George Reid (2004). Afro-Latin America, 1800–2000. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aristotle (2000). Nicomachean Ethics. Crisp, Roger(Ed.). New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Balfour, Lawrie (2011). Democracy’s Reconstruction: Thinking Politically with W. E. B. Du Bois. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackburn, Robin (1997). The Making of New World Slavery: From the Baroque to the Modern, 1492-1800. New York: Verso.Google Scholar
Brantlinger, Patrick (2003). Dark Vanishings: Discourse on the Extinction of Primitive Races, 1800–1930. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Cudd, Ann E. (2006). Analyzing Oppression. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fleischacker, Samuel (2004). A Short History of Distributive Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Fredrickson, George M. (1981). White Supremacy: A Comparative Study in American and South African History. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fredrickson, George M. (2002). Racism: A Short History. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Freeman, Samuel (Ed.) (2003). The Cambridge Companion to Rawls. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Freeman, Samuel (2007). Rawls. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goody, Jack (2006). The Theft of History. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hanchard, Michael (1999). Afro-Modernity: Temporality, Politics, and the African Diaspora. Public Culture, 11(1): 245268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haslanger, Sally (2012). Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (1956). The Philosophy of History. Sibree, J. (Trans.). New York: Dover Publications.Google Scholar
Isaac, Benjamin (2004). The Invention of Racism in Classical Antiquity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacobson, Matthew Frye (1999). Whiteness of a Different Color: European Immigrants and the Alchemy of Race. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jennings, Francis (1975). The Invasion of America: Indians, Colonialism, and the Cant of Conquest. New York: W. W. Norton.Google Scholar
Lehning, Percy B. (2009). John Rawls: An Introduction. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lipsitz, George (2011). How Racism Takes Place. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Locke, John (1988). Two Treatises of Government. Laslett, Peter (Ed.). New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lovett, Frank (2011). Rawls’s A Theory of Justice: A Reader’s Guide. New York: Continuum.Google Scholar
Maffetone, Sebastiano (2010). Rawls: An Introduction. Malden, MA: Polity.Google Scholar
Mandle, Jon (2009). Rawls’s A Theory of Justice: An Introduction. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marx, Anthony (1998). Making Race and Nation: A Comparison of the United States, South Africa, and Brazil. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Marx, Karl (1976). Capital, Vol. I. Fowkes, Ben (Trans.). Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin.Google Scholar
Marx, Karl (2000). Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts. In McLellan, David (Ed.), Karl Marx: Selected Writings, pp. 83121. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W. (1997). The Racial Contract. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W. (2009). Rawls on Race/Race in Rawls. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 47 (Supplement: Race, Racism, and Liberalism in the Twenty-First Century): 161184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pateman, Carole (1988). The Sexual Contract. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Pogge, Thomas W. (1989). Realizing Rawls. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John ([1993] 1996). Political Liberalism, expanded ed. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John (1999a). Collected Papers. Freeman, Samuel (Ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John (1999b). The Law of Peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John ([1971] 1999c). A Theory of Justice, rev. ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John (2001). Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Kelly, Erin (Ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, Rodney C. (2002). Introduction. In Roberts, Rodney C. (Ed.), Injustice and Rectification, pp. 16. New York: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Rodney, Walter ([1972] 2011). How Europe Underdeveloped Africa. Baltimore, MD: Black Classic Press.Google Scholar
Smith, Rogers M. (1997). Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship in US History. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Taiwo, Olufemi (2010). How Colonialism Preempted Modernity in Africa. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, Paul ([1993] 2013). Race: A Philosophical Introduction, 2ed. Malden, MA: Polity.Google Scholar
Van den Berghe, Pierre L. ([1972] 1978). Race and Racism: A Comparative Perspective, 2ed. New York: John Wiley.Google Scholar
Voice, Paul (2011). Rawls Explained: From Fairness to Utopia. Chicago, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Warren, Robert Penn (2001). Pondy Woods. In Burt, John (Ed.), Selected Poems of Robert Penn Warren, pp. 1618. Baton Rouge, LA: Louisiana State University Press.Google Scholar
Zerubavel, Eviatar (2003). Time Maps: Collective Memory and the Social Shape of the Past. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar