Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-cfpbc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-18T15:59:34.667Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

SISTERHOOD, AFFECTION AND ENSLAVEMENT IN HYPERIDES’ AGAINST TIMANDRUS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 April 2023

Katherine Backler*
Affiliation:
Trinity College, Oxford
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

A recently published fragment of the fourth-century speechwriter Hyperides contains a speech for the prosecution of Timandrus, accused of mistreating four orphans in his care. This article draws out from the fragment three important contributions to our understanding of Athenian conceptions of family relationships, particularly the relationships of marginalized groups: girls and enslaved people. First, the fragment constitutes a rare portrayal of a relationship between two sisters. Second, the fragment clearly articulates the idea that affective family relationships are not a biological inevitability but arise from socialization, a departure from other fourth-century thinking. Third, the speaker applies this statement to enslaved people, claiming that the separation of children from close family members is so cruel that even slave-traders avoid it in their sale of human beings. Though this claim seems to have been untrue except in a very limited sense, its place in the argumentation of the speech assumes broad recognition of the existence and value of family relationships between enslaved people, vivid evidence of the paradox that slave societies recognized the humanity of people they simultaneously insisted were subhuman.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Classical Association

The publication in 2005 of a fragment of Hyperides’ Against Timandrus Footnote 1 produced a flurry of scholarship: on the text and its transmission (Horváth, Easterling, Ucciardello); on how the speech fitted into what sort of trial (Thür, Whitehead); on the alleged practice of keeping enslaved families together at sale (Jones, Schmitz); on the law concerning the care of orphans (Rubinstein).Footnote 2 Part of the ‘Archimedes Palimpsest’, the fragment consists of two pages (64 lines) from Hyperides’ speech for the prosecution of one Timandrus, guardian (πίτροπος) of four orphans and their property; adjacent pages contain remnants of Hyperides’ Against Diondas. The passage of Against Timandrus, which is all that remains of the speech, begins and ends mid-sentence; it is not clear how much of the text originally appeared on the parchment, or in what context. The lines come from the πίστις (‘proof’) section of the speech.Footnote 3 The narrative (διήγησις) had probably been given by a previous speaker; the speaker of the fragment makes brief reference to some events which this other speaker may have mentioned (lines 20–7, 44–9, 63–4), but this is only guesswork. The central complaint in the fragment is that Timandrus separated a child from her siblings.

The fragment makes valuable contributions to our understanding of Athenian conceptions of family relationships, particularly the relationships of free girls and of enslaved people. This article elucidates three of these contributions. First, the fragment is a rare portrayal of a relationship between sisters—ironically, through the severance of that relationship. It attests to an emotive interest among Classical Athenians in sororal relationships, abundantly clear in tragedy but otherwise unusual in literature, even in forensic speeches concerned with family dynamics. Second, the fragment articulates the idea that affective family relationships are not biologically inevitable but arise from socialization (lines 35–42)—a departure from other fourth-century thinking. Third, the speaker applies this insight to enslaved people, claiming that the separation of children from close family is so cruel that even slave-traders avoid it (29–35). Whether or not this was true, in drawing such an analogy Hyperides recognizes—and expects the jurors to recognize—that enslaved people formed affective relationships comparable to those of free people and worth preserving. This article uses the fragment to develop our understanding of Athenian thinking about family and family relationships, particularly between those whose emotions and relationships are less visible in the historical record.

THE SIBLINGS TRAGEDIZED

In the fragment, Hyperides stages a family tragedy. Griffin has shown that the ‘acute suffering, extreme situations, and agonizing decisions’ which appear on the Athenian tragic stage ‘are intimately linked to events in real, recent, and contemporary life’; these situations resonated because they could and did happen in the real world.Footnote 4 He draws parallels between events of the tragic stage and stories told in the historians; there are similar parallels to be drawn with stories told in the orators.Footnote 5 Andocides tells of a woman who tried to hang herself out of shame at the quasi-incestuous sexual relations within her family (1.124–5; compare Jocasta in Sophocles’ Oedipus Tyrannus); Andocides suggests that the child of one of the women involved should be called Oedipus (128–9).Footnote 6 Isaeus presents a situation in which someone tries to prevent a dead man's relatives from burying him, though the relatives manage to bury him at night (6.39–41; compare Sophocles’ Antigone). Similarly, elements in Hyperides’ narrative are the stuff of tragedy: family members separated in childhood (cf. Creusa and Ion in Euripides’ Ion; Electra and Orestes in Sophocles’ and Euripides’ Electras and Aeschylus’ Choephori); mistreatment of vulnerable children by guardians (cf. Creon, Ismene and Antigone in Sophocles’ Oedipus at Colonus). We know of fourth-century reperformances of the four Sophoclean dramas just mentioned, for example:Footnote 7 Hyperides is evoking patterns on which the tragedians also drew, familiar to his audience from the stage and from life.

Making a quick, compelling sketch of the children and their relationships to elicit maximum pity, Hyperides presents them as two sets of siblings: δυον δελφον κα δελφαν δυον, ‘two brothers and two sisters’, or, to push the dual further, ‘a pair of brothers and a pair of sisters’ (21); contrast Isae. 2.3, without pathos, μεν δ ατ παδες τέτταρες μες, δύο μν ες, δύο δ θυγατέρες, ‘we were his four children, two sons and two daughters’. By presenting the girls as ‘a pair of sisters’, Hyperides establishes the relationship between them which will be broken later (44). The chiasmus marks the phrase; contrast the Suda's δυον δελφον κα δυαν δελφαν (π 847 Adler), referring to this speech. Hyperides contrasts the implicit closeness of the children with the emphasized loss of both mother and father (ρφ̣α̣ναν κα μητρς κα π(ατ)ρ(ό)ς, 21–2).Footnote 8 ρφανός/-ή denoted a child who had lost his or her father; one could be ρφανός with a living mother. The phrasing presents the loss of two parents as a triple blow: the children are ‘orphans/fatherless [having lost] both their mother and their father’. Compare the opening of Sophocles’ Antigone (1–60, especially 49–60) where the closeness and the interdependence of the two sisters are contrasted with the loss of both their father and their mother (and then their brothers). Both sisters repeatedly use duals to describe themselves (Antigone: 3, 21; Ismene: 50, 58, 61–2) and their brothers (Antigone: 21; Ismene: 55–7), although, after Ismene states that she will not help Antigone bury their brother, there are no more duals in the scene, and Antigone distinguishes emphatically between ‘I’ and ‘you’ (69–72, 76–7).

Further, the children are very little (παιδαρίων, 22). The speaker describes the girl as σως … πτ τν (‘perhaps seven years old’, 27); her elder brother was σ̣ω̣ς̣ … δέκα τν (‘perhaps ten years old’, 23–4). It seems unlikely that he did not know their ages: explicit references to children's ages elsewhere in Classical literature show that the numerical ages of both boys and girls were known and important.Footnote 9 The speaker's vagueness may be because the children were in fact older and the speaker is manipulating the facts for sympathy; or they were ten and seven, but σως allows the audience to think of them as being younger.Footnote 10

Hyperides portrays the severance of the children's closeness with similarly brief, emotive detail (25–31):

τν νεωτέραν ατν δελφν ποσπάσας ο̣τοσ Τίμανδρος τρεφε παρ ατ ποκ̣ο̣μ̣ί̣σ̣(α̣ς̣) ες Λμνον σως οσαν πτ τν. κα̣ίτ̣ο̣ι̣ τοτο μ τι πίτροπ(ος) ενους <ν> ν(θρωπ)ος ποιήσαι, λλ’ οδ’ ο κατ πόλεμον γκρατες γιγνόμενοι τ(ν) σωμάτων, λλ κα κατ οκίαν πωλοσιν τι μάλιστα.

This man Timandrus dragged away their younger sister, took her away to Lemnos and brought her up in his house; she was perhaps seven years old. Now, this is a thing no guardian would do, nor any human being with his heart in the right place, not even those who get control of slaves in war, but even they sell them as families as far as possible.

The speaker refers to the younger girl (not named, in accordance with Athenian custom)Footnote 11 not as ‘the younger girl’ but as ‘their younger sister’ (τν νεωτέραν ατν δελφήν), thereby focalizing through the other children.

The image conjured up at 28–31, where the speaker compares Timandrus’ behaviour to that of conquering armies, is ‘the truly frightening one of andrapodismos’.Footnote 12 νδραποδισμός involved soldiers who captured a settlement extracting the older children and young women to exploit themselves or sell to traders for exploitation by others; to achieve this end, they typically killed any surviving men of fighting age, then slaughtered a number of unwanted women and children (the old or very young) to terrorize the rest into submission, then, by cudgelling and other tactics, separated out the desired women and children.Footnote 13 ποσπάω (25) is part of this image: it evokes the violent manhandling associated in Classical Athens with slavehood, and specifically the sexual violation of enslaved girls, including war captives;Footnote 14 aggravated sexual violence against women and girls was central to νδραποδισμός.Footnote 15 Paired with ποσπάω, the shared prefix of the more neutral verb ποκομίζω (‘carry away’, 26) gives it a sinister tone, developing the image (it is once used of war captives, Thuc. 7.82, and more often for people in a state of helplessness: Isoc. 19.39, Andoc. 1.61).

Again, the speaker's story has a Sophoclean counterpart. In Oedipus at Colonus, Creon, the uncle and soon-to-be-guardian of Ismene and Antigone, kidnaps Ismene and takes her away from her sister and father in Attica to his home in Thebes (818–47). Timandrus, being the children's πίτροπος, could well have been an uncle and was almost certainly a male relative.Footnote 16 Creon later kidnaps Antigone too, dragging her away onstage. ποσπάω is not used but equivalents are: ξυναρπάσας (819), ξάγειν | κουσαν (826–7), φήσεις (835), φέλκομαι (844), πρς βίαν πορεύομαι (845).

Hyperides portrays the separation of the siblings as a great cruelty, which suggests a shared understanding among those he addresses of the value to children's well-being of maintaining sibling relationships and the suffering caused by their severance. Given high infant mortality rates, it is likely that many jurors would have lost a sibling in childhood;Footnote 17 Hyperides may thus be drawing on the jurors’ memories to arouse their grief and indignation over siblings lost to each other while still alive. If so, it is notable that he focusses on the thwarted relationship between the sisters, not between the sister and her brother(s); the jurors are expected to sympathize across the gender division, a point to which I return. The immediacy of the separation is also a grievance: it happened ‘right in the first year when their father died’ (εθς τ πρώτ νι̣αυτ ̣(ς) <> π̣(ατ)ρ̣ ατ̣(ν) ̣τ̣ε̣λ̣ε̣ύ̣τησεν, 63–4). Though it seems that the Athenian mourning period lasted until the rites performed thirty days after the death,Footnote 18 it may be that the first year was felt to be a particularly sensitive time. This fits with the possibility that the annual rites performed for the individual dead (νιαυσία) were celebrated on the anniversary of the death (as opposed to the anniversary of the person's birthday or funeral).Footnote 19 In another prosecution of a guardian, after the dead man's wife and children were told of his death they continued to live in his house ‘for the first year’ (τν … πρτον νιαυτόν, Lys. 32.8). Only after the first year did their guardian Diogeiton split them up, perhaps making him a more sensitive guardian, at least initially.Footnote 20

Hyperides’ emphasis on the relationship between the sisters is remarkable. The emotional climax of the fragment is the sisters’ inability to recognize each other after years of separation (42–5):

Τίμανδρος τοίνυν τούτου α̣τ̣ο̣̣ γε̣ ατιος γέγον(εν) στε τ̣ς̣ μν δελφς̣ λλήλας μ ναγνν(α̣ι̣) μήτε ν ̣δ̣̣ι̣ μήτε ν ̣ε̣ρ̣̣ι̣ δούσας

And so Timandrus was guilty of this: that the sisters did not recognize each other when they saw each other in the street nor at the temple

Hyperides attests to the potential closeness and importance of sororal relationships by showing us one thwarted. Though the (failed) interaction which he describes happened in adulthood, it is used to argue for the cruelty of their treatment as children and relies on the pathos of a childhood spent apart; his interest is in the emotions and affective relationships of children, girls at that.

Why does Hyperides specify the street and the temple? The speaker may be revisiting details from a fuller, earlier account—perhaps the διήγησις probably given by another speaker—which described how the younger sister visited Athens, or the older sister visited Lemnos (as her brother did, and perhaps with him) and the two women, now in their twenties and probably married with children of their own, walked around the same city without knowing each other. This lost narrative would have been a rare account of female sociality and interaction in public spaces, both sacred and not. Another possibility is that this narrative of non-interaction is introduced here for the first time; the specific details encourage the jurors to imagine precise situations and bring the sisters’ thwarted reunion to life. Streets and temples would have been among the most public places accessible to women. By specifying these places, emphasized by their coordinating negatives (μήτε ν ̣δ̣̣ι̣ μήτε ν ̣ε̣ρ̣̣ι̣), the speaker stresses that Timandrus’ separation of the girls deprived them not only of the domestic intimacy which female relations could enjoy but even of the pleasure of knowingly encountering each other in public (temples and sanctuaries were favourite sites for women's social interaction).Footnote 21 Further, the mention of the temple brings the gods into the narrative, which allows the jurors to imagine divine disapproval.Footnote 22 The extant narrative contributes to our increasingly complex picture of female ‘public’ visibility and invisibility in Classical Athens:Footnote 23 it suggests that it was unremarkable that free élite Athenian women would encounter unfamiliar women in streets and temples, and that streets and temples could be sites of female visibility.

The abducted woman's brother did not recognize her on sight either, but no emotional point is made of this. Her sister's non-recognition is contrasted with her brother's recognition; that he too did not recognize her on sight is added as an explanatory detail (47–9):

τν δ δελφν τουτον κάδημον ναγνωρίσαι τν αυτο δελφήν, λθόν(τα) δ̣ ε̣̣ς̣ Λ̣̣μ̣ν̣ο̣ν̣ μ̣̣ γ̣ν̣̣ναι̣ δόν(τα).

but it took her brother here, Academus, to recognize his own sister, though he had come to Lemnos and did not know her when he saw her.

The girl's relationship with all three siblings was severed, but Hyperides foregrounds the thwarted sororal relationship even over her relationship with Academus, present in court (τουτονί, 47). We may infer that if a girl had both brother and sister, her childhood relationship with her sister was expected to be the stronger one. Certainly Hyperides’ use of the thwarted sororal relationship as an illustration of Timandrus’ cruelty—the central illustration, at least in the text that we have—suggests that the jurors would generally have accepted that sororal relationships were special and worth preserving.

Golden laments the lack of evidence for sororal relationships in Classical Athens, which he attributes in part to selective exposure of baby girls (to which we might add gendered undernourishment)Footnote 24 but mainly to ‘our sources’ systematic scanting of women’.Footnote 25 Coo refines this judgement, noting that ‘while we have little evidence for the real-life relationship between sisters in Classical Greece, we find an abundance of sisters in myth and literature’Footnote 26 and compiling a list of 17 extant and 27 fragmentary or lost tragedies which certainly or probably featured pairs or groups of sisters. Sophocles’ portrayals of sororal relationships in Oedipus at Colonus, Antigone and Electra are well known. Coo argues further for the centrality of sisterhood in Sophocles’ Tereus and Euripides’ Erechtheus. Her list and analysis attest to an emotional interest among Athenians in sororal relationships, upon which Hyperides—sometimes using tragic motifs—draws.

Among the evidence for ‘real-life sisters’, Golden notes a monument commemorating two sisters, Melino and —ostrate (IG II2 5673, c.350, Piraeus):Footnote 27

κα ζσαι̣ πλούτου πατρικο μέρος
εχον μοίως, | τν ατν φιλίαν κ̣α̣
χρήματα τατ’ νόμιζον.
οδ]ένα λυπήσασα τέκνων δ’ πιδοσ-
α τι] παδας | τ̣ς κοινς μοίρας πσ-
ιν χει] τ μέρος.
——οστράτη, Μελινώ
——νος ναφλυστ[ίου]

While they were alive, they had an equal portion of their father's wealth;Footnote 28 they considered their affection and wealth the same.

She caused grief to no one, but having even seen children's children, she has a portion of the fate that is shared by everyone.Footnote 29

——ostrate, Melino

[daughter(s)] of ——on of Anaphlystus

The couplets were inscribed at the same time. Kaibel suggests that the sister praised in the second couplet died first (—ostrate, named first?) and that her sister (Melino?) set up the monument for her before being buried in it herself; in his view, Melino had the couplet referring to both of them inscribed in preparation for her own death at the time she commemorated —ostrate.Footnote 30 The sisters were almost certainly πίκληροι, which likely motivated the emphasis on their inheritance. This status may have given them a sense of their own significance, along with some level of access to or influence over financial resources, which enabled the erection of such a monument, into which Melino must have had input: this is a sister's description of her sororal relationship. The phrase τν ατν φιλίαν κ̣α̣ χρήματα τατ’ νόμιζον (‘they considered their love/affection and wealth the same’) seems to mean ‘they valued their relationship as much as their money’.Footnote 31 Though —ostrate, a grandmother, was at some point married, the sisters apparently maintained a strong relationship throughout their long lives.

It is this kind of sororal relationship, close and persisting into adulthood, that the speaker of Against Timandrus accuses Timandrus of thwarting. The speech's emotional engagement with real-life sisters makes it extremely unusual in Attic forensic oratory. Elsewhere in the orators there are a few pairs or groups of sisters, but we are given almost no sense of their relationships with each other: mostly speakers just note their marriages and dowries.Footnote 32 In a handful of cases, sisters are presented in a way which implies an affective or cooperative relationship. In Isaeus 6, the two daughters of Euctemon, who have three brothers (§6), are situated together socially within their family and their father's phratry and deme (§10). More importantly, they are said to have come together with their mother after their marriages to bury their estranged father when he died (§§40–1).

In Isaeus 12.5, the speaker portrays two men's willingness to testify to the citizen status of their brother-in-law Euphiletus as facilitated by the shared attitudes of the sisters married to them. The speaker, Euphiletus’ paternal half-brother, claims that these men would not have given false evidence in favour of Euphiletus because Euphiletus’ mother was their wives’ stepmother:

εώθασι δέ πως ς π τ πολ διαφέρεσθαι λλήλαις α τε μητρυια κα α πρόγονοι· στε ε οτος ξ λλου τινς νδρς ν τ μητρυι κα οκ κ το μετέρου πατρός, οκ ν ποτε,  νδρες δικασταί, τος αυτν νδρας α δελφα μαρτυρεν [εασαν κα] πέτρεψαν.

and stepmothers and daughters from a former marriage mostly tend to be at odds with each other, so if this man had been [born] to the stepmother from some other man and not from our father, our sisters would never, jurymen, have allowed their husbands to be witnesses.

The speaker implies a unity of feeling between the sisters and a united response to the situation.

Demosthenes 27 provides indirect evidence for an affective relationship between sisters, Demosthenes’ mother Cleobule and her sister Philia. Demosthenes says that Philia's husband helped Cleobule by acting as her advocate (14–15), and Philia's son married Cleobule's daughter ([Plut.] Mor. 847C), though her dowry had been appropriated by her guardians (Dem. 27.5–6, 65, passim).Footnote 33 Philia's husband's and son's support for Cleobule and her daughter suggests a close, supportive relationship between Cleobule and Philia herself.Footnote 34 Lys. 3.6–7 offers a rare glimpse of sisters in childhood: the speaker mentions his fatherless nieces, who were allegedly intruded upon in the γυναικωντις, the women's space of the house. He describes them as παδας κόρας κα ρφανάς (‘young girls, orphans’) and says that ‘they have lived such orderly lives that they are ashamed to be seen even by their [male] relatives’ (οτω κοσμίως βεβιώκασιν στε κα π τν οκείων ρώμεναι ασχύνεσθαι). We infer that the sisters shared a living space and lifestyle, the kind of συνήθεια (‘shared life’, lines 36–7 of our fragment; cf. τ̣ συντρόφους … εναι, ‘being brought up together’, 37) that later in the speech Hyperides says leads to ε̣νοιαι (‘affectionate feelings’, 36) among family members; the second part of this article discusses this claim in detail.Footnote 35

Tchernetska and her co-editors suggest that ‘Akademos, now head of the family, was in a position to establish the identity as well as the whereabouts of his younger sister, but when he first saw her in Lemnos, he failed to recognize the young woman he had last seen over thirteen years ago when they had both been orphaned in early childhood.’Footnote 36 Though Lemnos might have a particular ethical resonance given that a ‘Lemnian’ deed was proverbial for a cruel deed,Footnote 37 it is more relevant that in fourth-century Athenian courts Lemnos was associated with estranged relatives and difficult-to-establish identities of family members. Lemnos was home to many Athenian κληροχοι, emigrants who lived some or all of the time in Lemnos and held land there, but retained Athenian citizenship and membership of the deme and tribe to which they had belonged; Timandrus, whose home was in Lemnos (26–7), was probably one.Footnote 38 ‘Athenian litigiousness did not fail to seize the opportunities of fraud presented by the existence of a body of citizens practically unknown in Attica.’Footnote 39 In Isaeus 6, the speaker's opponents claim that the testator had sons with a second wife from Lemnos; the speaker contends that no such woman existed and that the claim her father came from Lemnos was a convenient excuse for his untraceability. In Terence's Phormio, one character, like Academus in Against Timandrus, travels to Lemnos to search for a female relative from whom he has been separated and who has since grown to adulthood (Phorm. 568–72). Donatus’ commentary on the play strongly suggests that its plot is closely based on Apollodorus’ Epidikazomenos.Footnote 40 In this case the lost relative is the man's illegitimate daughter: during a previous stay in Lemnos, he had contracted a secret second marriage under a false name, though already married in Athens, and had a child.

Recognition scenes between long-lost family members were frequent in tragedy and, under its influence (particularly that of Euripides), New Comedy. Particularly relevant is the Electra/Orestes recognition scene between a brother and a sister separated in early childhood. Euripides’ and Sophocles’ Electras and Aeschylus’ Choephori all feature such a scene; in none of them do the pair recognize each other on sight. Euripides makes explicit what is implicit in Hyperides (Eur. El. 282–4); the language used in the two passages is similar:

ρέστης: εθ ν ρέστης πλησίον κλύων τάδε.
λέκτρα: λλ, ξέν, ο γνοίην ν εσιδοσά νιν.
ρέστης: νέα γάρ, οδν θαμ, πεζεύχθης νέου.
Orestes: If only Orestes were nearby to hear this.
Electra: But stranger, I would not know him if I saw him.
Orestes: No wonder, for you were both young when he left you.

Euripides’ reworking of Aeschylus’ rendition (Eur. El. 215–431, 508–84; Aesch. Cho. 212–45) suggests the popularity of the theme, but where in Aeschylus’ and Euripides’ versions the reunion scenes come early and are fairly brief, in Sophocles’ Electra the recognition between long-lost brother and sister is much delayed and forms the emotional high point of the play.

THE SOCIAL CONSTRUCTION OF THE FAMILY RELATIONSHIP

The speaker claims that ‘affectionate feelings between people exist because of shared lives and their having a shared upbringing rather than because of shared blood’ (α … ε̣νοιαι τ̣ο̣̣ς̣ νθρώπ̣ο̣ι̣ς̣ εσ δι τν συνήθειαν κα τ̣ συντρόφους ατος εναι μλλον δι τς συγγενείας, 35–8).Footnote 41 The ‘evidence’ (τ̣εκμήριον) for this claim, he continues, is that ‘fathers would not be fond of their children if they [sc. the children] had not been brought up by them from infancy, if someone had immediately dragged them off [text missing: ‘and kept hold of them’?], nor would children be fond of their parents if they had not been brought up by them’ (38–42). Hyperides’ absolutist examples here recommend the translation of μλλον as ‘rather than’ instead of ‘more than’. How typical was such a sentiment in Classical Athens? Let us compare the analyses of two contemporary authors who engage with the question of the nature, origin and significance of affection between kin: Aristotle and Isaeus.

In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle, without a prosecution case to make, offers a different account (1161b3–4).Footnote 42 As elsewhere in this work, he begins his analyses from, and tests them against, νδοξα (‘reputable views’; the views of the majority or, in certain cases, experts); he often begins from definitions he claims are generally accepted or cites proverbs to support his arguments.Footnote 43 Aristotle's concern is with φιλία, friendship or affection, rather than ενοια, the term Hyperides uses (in the plural). Aristotle asserts that ενοια (singular) is commonly used to mean ‘wishing another's good’; as such, φιλία is commonly understood to consist in reciprocal ενοια (1155b).Footnote 44 Outside philosophy, ενοια describes an established positive interpersonal emotional attitude ranging from the weaker ‘goodwill’ (for example in diplomatic contexts) to a more earnestly felt, devoted affection as between close friends and family members.Footnote 45 A comparison between Hyperides’ account of ενοιαι and Aristotle's of φιλία is therefore still productive.

Aristotle argues that all affection (φιλία) inheres in κοινωνία (community, having something in common), but categorizes affection between family and friends as different from friendship between fellow citizens, fellow tribe members and colleagues, because it is less contractual. He argues that all family affection ( συγγενικ [φιλία]) depends upon paternal love,Footnote 46 ‘for parents love their children because the children are something of themselves, but children love their parents because they are something from them’ (ο γονες μν γρ στέργουσι τ τέκνα ς αυτν τι ντα, τ δ τέκνα τος γονες ς π κείνων τι ντα). Parents are ‘close’ to their children, he continues, because the children have come from and belong to their bodies; therefore, parents love their children as soon as they come into existence, while children require knowledge, or perception, to love their parents. Parents love their children as being part of themselves; children love their parents as being their source; brothers love each other as sharing a source. This biological or essentialist explanation differs from Hyperides’ claim that fathers separated from their children in infancy would not be fond of them, and children brought up by people other than their parents would not be fond of their parents (38–42): Aristotle asserts that mothers who give their children to be raised by others (διδόασι τ αυτν τρέφεσθαι) still love them (κα φιλοσι), though they do not expect to be loved by them in return (ντιφιλεσθαι δ ο ζητοσιν, 1159a). For Hyperides in this fragment, unlike for Aristotle, ‘sharedness’ between siblings (Aristotle's κοινωνία, Hyperides’ συνήθεια and τ̣ συντρόφους … εναι) is not dependent on the children's relationship to their parents.

Modern kinship studies tend to de-emphasize the role of biology that was so important to Aristotle. Most insistent is Sahlins, who argues that kinship is entirely cultural, and counter-intuitively uses this passage as an illustration: ‘Anchored as it may be in concepts of birth and descent, Aristotle's discussion of kinship at once goes beyond and encompasses relations of procreation in larger meanings of mutual belonging that could just as well accommodate the various performative modes of relatedness. Or so I read the possibilities of his sense of kinship as “the same entity in discrete subjects.”’Footnote 47 This overstates the flexibility of Aristotle's conception of kinship: Aristotle's ‘same entity in discrete subjects’, his ‘being of [the other, where in fact, “the other” is always and only the parent]’, is biological: parents are ‘close’ (οκεος) to their children because the children have come from and belong to their bodies, like a tooth or hair (1161b2). However, Aristotle adds a socio-cultural element, claiming that φιλία between brothers is much increased (though not generated) by their shared upbringing and similar age (μέγα δ πρς φιλίαν κα τ σύντροφον κα τ καθ λικίαν); he cites the saying ο συνήθεις ταροι (literally, ‘those who spend time together [become] friends’). For this reason, affection between brothers is similar to affection between friends (δι κα  δελφικ [φιλία] τ ταιρικ μοιοται).

When Aristotle is speaking in apparently general terms, he predominantly uses language specifically relating to men. Hyperides does the same in this speech: though he says that slave-traffickers and slave-dealers try not to separate a mother from her little children (31–5), the first ‘proof’ he gives of his explanation that separation prevents family affection is that fathers (π̣(ατέ)ρ̣(ε)ς) would not love their children if they had been brought up by someone else (38–40). In seeking the jurors’ emotional engagement, the speaker appeals to them in terms of men's emotional experiences and attachments. He continues, however, ‘nor would children love their parents’ (τος γονέας, 41–2);Footnote 48 the elision of gender in Hyperides’ argumentation is discussed below. In Aristotle, ‘the word for brothers, “adelphoi”, can be translated “siblings”, but [Aristotle] probably takes it for granted that our attention will be on male adelphoi.’Footnote 49 It is hard to know how far Aristotle would have considered his analysis applicable to girls or women. Hyperides’ attention to the emotional lives and affective relations of young girls in Against Timandrus is unusual in Attic literature outside tragedy.

The question of what constitutes family closeness is thematic in Isaeus, who deals extensively with family relationships in the context of disputed inheritances, often arguing that his client was a closer relative to the dead man than to his opponent. Isaeus uses a framework in which being related to someone is characterized and constituted by blood kinship (συγγένεια) and certain shared life experiences, like cohabitation and shared religious practice (analogous to Hyperides’ συνήθεια), and shared upbringing (cf. Hyperides’ and Aristotle's τ σύντροφον). Unlike Hyperides and Aristotle, Isaeus portrays emotional connection not as arising from biology and/or shared life experiences but as complementary to them in constituting family closeness, and demonstrated by behaviours such as raising a child in one's home and including her or him in religious rites.Footnote 50 This is because his arguments sometimes rely on reconstructing the supposed intentions of the deceased, where their alleged behaviour is taken to indicate their feelings. For Isaeus (and, he must assume, the jurors), feelings of affection between family members, combined with and demonstrated by certain behaviours, attest to the existence of a family relationship. Family relationships themselves are never understood as solely biological, not least because of the prevalence of adoption. Where necessary, Isaeus prioritizes shared life experience over biology.

Most relevant is Isaeus’ frequent foregrounding of the familial context of a child's upbringing. In Isaeus 8, part of the proof of the legitimacy of Ciron's daughter by his first wife (that is, of the family relationship between Ciron and his daughter) is that Ciron brought her up with his second family: κα κείνην τε τρεφε παρ τ γυναικ κα μετ τν ξ κείνης παίδων (‘and he brought her up with his [second] wife and alongside his children by that wife’, 7); she was τρεφομένην νδον (‘brought up in his home’, 14). Ciron was willing to spend money on bringing her up and publicly to acknowledge her as a member of his household and family. Isaeus 9 describes how a remarried woman brought her son Astyphilus from her first marriage into her second marriage; when she had a son, Theophrastus, with her new husband, the boys were educated together (28). Theophrastus uses this to argue for his close family relationship to Astyphilus and therefore his claim to inherit. In Isaeus 7, Thrasyllus claims the estate of Apollodorus, who he says adopted him. The adoption was not finalized before Apollodorus’ death, so Thrasyllus must argue that Apollodorus intended to adopt him and that his own claim trumps that of Apollodorus’ first cousin. The thrust of Thrasyllus’ argument is that Apollodorus was full of goodwill to him and ill-will to his cousin. The context of Apollodorus’ goodwill towards Thrasyllus was that Thrasyllus’ grandfather Archedamus brought up Apollodorus. As Thrasyllus tells it, after Apollodorus’ father died, Apollodorus went to live with his uncle and πίτροπος, while his mother was remarried to Archedamus. Archedamus saw that the πίτροπος was financially abusing his wife's son and ‘brought him to live with him and the boy's mother and brought him up when he was a child’ (τρεφέ τε ατν παδα νθ, ς αυτν κα τν μητέρα κομισάμενος, 7; τρεφέ is promoted by a kind of hysteron proteron). Apollodorus’ goodwill towards Archedamus is said to have come from being brought up by him, not from blood relationship—since there was none.

In the context of the speech, Hyperides’ claim that ‘affectionate feelings between people exist because of shared lives and having a shared upbringing, rather than because of shared blood’ casts Timandrus’ alleged separation of the siblings as the wholesale destruction of a family relationship, which could never have been in the children's interests. This is part of the rhetorical strategy which probably set out to disable a claim by Timandrus that it was in the separated sister's interest to be raised in Lemnos and in the other siblings’ interest to be raised in Athens.Footnote 51 In the context of fourth-century Attic thought on kinship, Hyperides’ argument is not entirely novel, but its formulation is extreme. It is striking that he expected the jurors to accept it.

ENSLAVED FAMILIES AND SOCIALITY

Jones and Schmitz have attempted to assess the accuracy of Hyperides’ claim that the Classical Athenian slave trade avoided the separation of siblings and of mothers with young children.Footnote 52 Schmitz finds one probable example of an enslaved Thracian woman being sold with her two children as a single ‘item’ in the auction lists of the property of the Hermocopidae,Footnote 53 and points out that the possibility of identifying an enslaved family in these lists suggests that the other enslaved people listed did not live or were not sold ‘as families’.Footnote 54 Andocides informs us that an enslaved man named Andromachus and his brother, also enslaved and living in the same household, were witnesses to the profanation of the Mysteries (1.11–12).Footnote 55 They may have been captured, sold and bought together, or (less relevant to the question at hand) born in their enslaver's home to the same enslaved mother. At any rate, they were still together in adulthood. To these examples we may add the case of Midas and his sons Pancalus and Procles/Polycles (the source gives two different names) in another Hyperides speech: a man infatuated with one of the boys intended to buy and free him, and was persuaded to buy his father and brother too (3.4–6, 24). The late fourth-century φιάλαι ‘inscriptions’, traditionally understood as records of manumissions, seem also to include some family groups.Footnote 56

However (a)typical the preservation of enslaved families was, the implications of Hyperides’ claim and of its place in his argument have not been much addressed. The argument at the centre of the fragment is as follows: it was cruel of Timandrus to separate the siblings; separating families is so cruel that even slave-traders and slave-traffickers, apparently a byword for cruelty, do not do such a thing to enslaved people; the reason they do not do this (γ(άρ), 35) is that affection between family members does not arise ‘naturally’ from blood kinship but from lives—particularly childhoods—spent together. The third stage of the argument is compressed: the intermediary stage must be something like ‘traders and traffickers do not do this because they acknowledge (actual or potential) affective relationships between enslaved family members, which would be destroyed or thwarted by separation’. The implication of this stage is significant: it humanizes enslaved people. The speaker recognizes—and implies that the jurors recognize—the capacity of enslaved people to form profound affective relationships based on shared histories, comparable to family relationships among free people. Not only does the speaker (and, by implication, the jurors) recognize the relationships, but he (and, by implication, the jurors) professes to value them and their effect on the enslaved people who form them. The argument is based on the premise that ενοιαι should ideally be allowed to (even facilitated in) enslaved people.

Arguing that the hallmark of enslavement is the ‘social death’ of the enslaved person, which includes ‘natal alienation’, the forcible disregarding of that person's relationships, Patterson explains that ‘this does not mean that he or she did not experience or share informal social relations … [However,] these relationships were never recognized as legitimate or binding … [P]arents were deeply attached to their children, but the parental bond had no social support … slaves had no custodial claims or powers over their children, and children inherited no claims or obligations to their parents.’Footnote 57 This aspect of slavery was recognized and discussed in Athens, for example by Callicles in Plato's Gorgias (483a–b):Footnote 58

oδ γρ νδρς τοτό γ στν τ πάθημα, τ δικεσθαι, λλ νδραπόδου τινς κρεττόν στιν τεθνάναι ζν, στις δικούμενος κα προπηλακιζόμενος μ οός τέ στιν ατς ατ βοηθεν μηδ λλ ο ν κήδηται.

For this suffering, that is, being wronged, is not the part of a man, but the part of some slave, for whom it is better to be dead than alive, who, if he is wronged or trampled in the mud, is unable to help himself, or anyone he cares for.

Though the enslaved person experiences an attachment (κήδηται) to another person, he is unable to realize the relationship by carrying out its ethical obligations. Callicles makes this comment as part of a challenge to Socrates’ mode of argumentation, but despite Callicles’ cynicism both he and Socrates seem to treat it as understood that an enslaved person was incapable of decisively supporting his or her loved ones,Footnote 59 and that this set the enslaved person apart from the (free) ‘man’ (νήρ).

This combination of attachment and powerlessness could be weaponized by the enslaver. The author of the pseudo-Aristotelian Oeconomica recommends that in order to ensure the obedience of enslaved people δε … κα ξομηρεύειν τας τεκνοποιίαις (‘it is necessary to take hostages by means of [their] begetting children’, 1134b). That is, enslaved people should be allowed to have children with each other both so that the enslaver might threaten the parents with harm to or separation from their children and so that the parents might be discouraged from escaping and incurring the cost of separation from their children.Footnote 60

Here it is worth drilling into the specific claims Hyperides makes. He asserts that those who have captured people in war (ο κατ πόλεμον γκρατες γιγνόμενοι τ(ν) σωμάτων, 29–30) try as far as possible to sell them ‘as a household/family’ (κατ’ οκίαν, 30). He then refers to another group of people: slave-dealers and slave-traffickers (ονδραποδοκάπηλ(οι) κα μποροι, 31–2),Footnote 61 who, he claims, despite their unscrupulous profiteering, try where possible to sell young siblings or mother-and-infant groups (δ̣ε̣λ̣φ̣ παιδάρι(α) … μ̣η̣τέρα κα παιδία, 33) together, even if it means incurring a loss.Footnote 62 From later accounts of νδραποδισμός, Gaca shows that, though soldiers generally did not want infants who were likely to die in transport, ‘leav[ing] infants with their young mothers can be expedient for inducing the mothers to go along without resistance’.Footnote 63 If Hyperides’ claim that such separations were avoided is true, this was a likelier motivation than respect for affective bonds. The claim about young siblings is harder to evaluate; was compliance a factor here too? Its rhetorical value lies in the directness of the comparison to his (free) clients, who were separated from their sibling.

Hyperides’ elisions and assumptions around gender and family are illuminating. Though he claims that soldiers ideally sold andrapodized people ‘as a household/family’, by this stage of νδραποδισμός the household/family of the victims had been destroyed, the adult male members killed and the older female or very young members left behind. Either Hyperides elides this reality—surely familiar to the jurors—or he is using the phrase to mean ‘along with any other οκία members selected for sale’. Though men were not andrapodized, they were trafficked into slavery by other methods, but in speaking of family preservation by traffickers and traders Hyperides limits his claim to child siblings and mothers with infants. In neither case is the οκία preserved, nor are many family relationships—including paternal relationships, the value and potency of which Hyperides uses in the following sentence to explain this practice. If there is truth in his claims about family preservation in the slave system, Hyperides is extrapolating from age-, gender- and situation-specific practices to make a falsely universalizing claim about respect for all family relations among enslaved people to serve his argument about the wickedness of Timandrus’ separation of his clients from their sister.

Nevertheless, he makes the claim. In Against Timandrus, the speaker's recognition of the existence and value of social ties between enslaved people throws into sharp relief the intellectual and moral paradox of slave societies: enslavers recognized the humanity of people they simultaneously insisted were subhuman.Footnote 64 This paradox is apparent in the fragment's language: where Hyperides argues that enslaved families are kept together where possible because family feeling comes from shared experience rather than biology (27–38), he uses the word for ‘slaves’ which most reduces them to their biology: τν σωμάτων (‘bodies’, 29–30).Footnote 65 Among many other instances, this is the term used in Dem. 47.12 and 15, where the speaker discusses rendering an enslaved woman for torture, in which the slavehood of a person is most brutally enacted. Yet in this speech it is where Hyperides discusses ‘humane’ treatment of enslaved people and acknowledges their humanity that he uses this dehumanizing term; where he recognizes their emotions, relationships and histories he talks about them as bodies.

The passage of Aristotle discussed earlier offers an analysis of affective relationships between free and enslaved people which runs up against the same paradox (Eth. Nic. 1161a–b):

φιλία δ οκ στι πρς τ ψυχα οδ δίκαιον. λλ οδ πρς ππον βον, οδ πρς δολον δολος. οδν γρ κοινόν στιν· γρ δολος μψυχον ργανον, τ δ ργανον ψυχος δολος. μν ον δολος, οκ στι φιλία πρς ατόν, δ νθρωπος· δοκε γρ εναί τι δίκαιον παντ νθρώπ πρς πάντα τν δυνάμενον κοινωνσαι νόμου κα συνθήκης· κα φιλία δή, καθ σον νθρωπος.

but there can be no affection/friendship/social bondFootnote 66 (φιλία) or justice towards/with inanimate things; no, not towards a horse or an ox, nor towards a slave qua slave. For they [the imagined subject and the enslaved person] share nothing/have nothing in common (οδν γρ κοινόν στιν): for a slave is an animate tool, as a tool is an inanimate slave. So in so far as he is a slave, there can be no affection/friendship/social bond towards/with him—but not in so far as he is a human being: for it seems that for any human being there is a kind of justice [owed?] to anyone who is able to share in law and contract, and so too the possibility of affection/friendship/a social bond, in so far as the object is a human being.

Various scholars have discussed Aristotle's not entirely satisfying distinction between relating to an enslaved person qua slave and qua human being.Footnote 67 Importantly for the questions addressed in this article, Aristotle seems to be thinking of the affective relationship of an enslaver (or at least a free person) with an enslaved person:Footnote 68 he might concede that there could be something κοινόν between one enslaved person and another, even if not between an enslaved person and a free person.Footnote 69 However, if Aristotle envisions affective relationships between enslaved people, that is not explicit. Hyperides’ insistence—for the purposes of his case—on the possibility and value of relationships between enslaved people, including children, goes well beyond Aristotle. Yet the ambivalence remains: Hyperides insists on enslaved people's claim to family relationships—or at least certain family relationships—but not their claim to freedom.Footnote 70 They are human beings with the capacity for relationships beyond the solely biological; at the same time, they are merely bodies.

CONCLUSION

This new fragment is studded with precious details—on family composition, movement within and between poleis, expectations around bereavement, and more—which enrich our picture of Athenian social and family life. Fundamentally, though, its narrative and argumentation transform our understanding of Athenian thinking and feeling about families, free and enslaved. Hyperides’ brief but evocative portrayal of sibling relationships and their severance, and his condemnation of the latter, are a rare contribution to our evidence for Athenian childhood relationships and emotions, and their perception by adults. Furthermore, the development of his argument comprises both a new, more extreme articulation of ideas implicit in Isaeus and Aristotle about the nature of family relationships—namely, the importance of shared upbringing and life experience in generating affective relations between kin—and the radical application of those ideas to enslaved people, whose affective relationships the speaker claims are widely recognized. The disjuncture between the recognition of these relationships and their forcible destruction as part of the practice of slavery illuminates the psychological and moral problems faced by a slave society.

Footnotes

I thank Claire Hall, Nino Luraghi, Teresa Morgan, Rosalind Thomas, Josephine Quinn and especially Christine Plastow for their kind assistance; and CQ's reader and Editor for helpful comments. All translations are mine.

References

1 Tchernetska, N., ‘New fragments of Hyperides from the Archimedes Palimpsest’, ZPE 154 (2005), 16Google Scholar; improved edition in Tchernetska, N. et al. , ‘New readings in the fragment of Hyperides’ “Against Timandros” from the Archimedes Palimpsest’, ZPE 162 (2007), 14Google Scholar.

2 Horváth, L., ‘Note to Hyperides In Timandrum’, AAntHung 48 (2008), 121–3Google Scholar; Horváth, L., Der Neue Hypereides: Textedition, Studien und Erläuterungen (Berlin, 2014)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Easterling, P., ‘Fata libellorum: Hyperides and the transmission of Attic oratory’, AAntHung 48 (2008), 1117Google Scholar; Ucciardello, G., ‘Hyperides in the Archimedes Palimpsest: palaeography and textual transmission’, BICS 52 (2009), 229–52Google Scholar; Thür, G., ‘Zur phasis in der neu entdeckten Rede Hypereides’ gegen Timandros’, Zeitschrift der Savigny-Stiftung für Rechtsgeschichte. Romanistische Abteilung 125 (2008a), 645–63CrossRefGoogle Scholar; G. Thür, ‘Zu μίσθωσις und φάσις οκου ρφανικο in Hypereides, Gegen Timandros’, AAntHung 48 (2008b), 125–37; Whitehead, D., ‘HypereidesTimandros: observations and suggestions’, BICS 52 (2009), 135–48Google Scholar; Jones, C., ‘Hyperides and the sale of slave-families’, ZPE 164 (2008), 1920Google Scholar; Schmitz, W., ‘Der Verkauf einer Sklavenfamilie’, ZPE 179 (2011), 54–6Google Scholar; Rubinstein, L., ‘Legal argumentation in Hypereides Against Timandros’, BICS 52 (2009), 149–59Google Scholar; see also Bearzot, C., ‘Lemno, gli oratori e il “nuovo Iperide”’, AASA 138 (2010), 283–90Google Scholar.

3 Whitehead (n. 2), 138.

4 Griffin, J., ‘Desperate straits and the tragic stage’, in Finglass, P.J., Collard, C. and Richardson, N.J. (edd.), Hesperos: Studies in Ancient Greek Poetry Presented to M.L. West on his Seventieth Birthday (Oxford and New York, 2007), 189203CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 189.

5 For tragic topoi in fourth-century oratory, see Wilson, P.J., ‘Tragic rhetoric: the use of tragedy and the tragic in the fourth century’, in Silk, M.S. (ed.), Tragedy and the Tragic: Greek Theatre and Beyond (Oxford, 1996), 310–31Google Scholar, at 311–21.

6 Cf. Wilson (n. 5), 317–18.

7 Epict. Diss. fr. 11 Schenkl (Oedipus Tyrannus, Oedipus at Colonus), Dem. 19.246 (Antigone), Gell. NA 6.5 (Electra); see Finglass, P.J., ‘Ancient reperformances of Sophocles’, Trends in Classics 7 (2015), 207–23CrossRefGoogle Scholar, especially 218–19. For fifth-century tragedy in the fourth century more generally, see Hanink, J., Lycurgan Athens and the Making of Classical Tragedy (Cambridge, 2014)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Lamari, A.A., Reperforming Greek Tragedy: Theater, Politics, and Cultural Mobility in the Fifth and Fourth Centuries BC (Berlin and Boston, 2017)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Wilson (n. 5).

8 Strictly this phrase should only apply to the sisters. E. Handley (apud Tchernetska [n. 1 (2005)], 4, ad loc.) comments: ‘all four children, necessarily, are without both father and mother: the point of the feminine dual is, I suppose, that it is harder, and from the orator's point of view, more pathos-making, for young girls to be without a mother as well as a father’, but the orator seems more interested in the relationship between the sisters than their relationship with their mother. Thür (n. 2 [2008a]), 652 suggests that it may point to a mention of their marriage elsewhere in the speech, which seems tenuous. A remote possibility, pace Handley's ‘necessarily’, is that the brothers and the sisters were amphimetric half-siblings, which would have to be explained elsewhere.

9 E.g. Antiph. 5.69; Dem. 27.4 (cf. Dem. 29.43); Isae. 12.10; Lys. 10.4; Ar. Lys. 641–7; Xen. Oec. 7.5 (contrast 3.13); with less certainty, Hdt. 5.51. A boy's transition into legal adulthood at the δοκιμασία depended on reaching the age of eighteen ([Ath. Pol.] 42.1); the δοκιμασία can be used as a temporal marker (e.g. Lys. 26.21).

10 Less probably, the speaker is positioning the children against the ages of seven and ten as cultural reference points: didactic treatises on education identify certain ‘significant ages’ which they associate with transitions through stages of childhood, and seven and ten are consistently important (M. Golden, Children and Childhood in Classical Athens [Baltimore, 2015], 17–18; for girls, note Ar. Lys. 641–7). Slightly different is the emphatic circumlocution ‘not yet [current age + 1]’ (e.g. Xen. Oec. 7.5, Antiph. 5.69). Like other diminutives for children in Attic Greek, παιδάριον is not tied to a particular age: [Dem.] 53.19 qualifies παιδάριον with μικρόν, attesting to its wide application; cf. [Dem.] 59.18, where μικρόν qualifies παιδίον (for the vocabulary of childhood, see Golden [this note], 10–12). Hyperides’ application of the term to boys and girls interested late antique scholars; a comment in the Suda (π 847 Adler, s.v. παιδάριον) to that effect helped Tchernetska (n. 1 [2005]), 1 identify this fragment.

11 D.M. Schaps, ‘The woman least mentioned: etiquette and women's names’, CQ 27 (1977), 323–30; Sommerstein, A.H., ‘The naming of women in Greek and Roman comedy’, QS 11 (1980), 393418Google Scholar = Talking about Laughter and Other Studies in Greek Comedy (Oxford, 2009), 43–69. Neither sister is named; both brothers are.

12 Rubinstein (n. 2), 156.

13 Gaca, K.L., ‘The andrapodizing of war captives in Greek historical memory’, TAPhA 140 (2010), 117–61Google Scholar; Gaca, K.L., ‘Telling the girls from the boys and children: interpreting παῖδες in the sexual violence of populace-ravaging ancient warfare’, ICS 35–6 (2011), 85109Google Scholar.

14 E.g. Eur. Hec. 277, with 612; Hdt. 6.32; Lys. 1.12. For a different accusation against a guardian for treating his (male) ward as if enslaved, see Isae. 5.11.

15 Gaca (n. 13 [2010]).

16 Athenian πίτροποι were typically close kin, most often the father's brother, but sometimes the mother's brother or another close relation (S.C. Humphreys, Kinship in Ancient Athens: An Anthropological Analysis [Oxford, 2018], 97–104). Occasionally a father appointed a non-kinsman in conjunction with a kinsman or kinsmen, as in the case of Demosthenes (27.4; see Humphreys [this note], 97); Thür (n. 2 [2008a]), 652 suggests that this may have been the case here.

17 I thank Christine Plastow for this point. Golden (n. 10), 70–5 discusses Athenians’ emotional responses to child deaths, observing (72–3) that ‘child rearing in high-mortality societies is often diffused, not the responsibility of parents alone, but shared to some extent with other adults and with older children [predominantly older sisters, we might add]; as a result, the burden of loss is also distributed more widely than in some cultures.’

18 Garland, R., The Greek Way of Death (London, 2001), 39Google Scholar; cf. Lys. 1.14.

19 Cf. Garland (n. 18), 104–5.

20 Rubinstein (n. 2), 153 notes that Diogeiton's separation of the children from their mother at around the same age as these siblings is never condemned.

21 For temples and sanctuaries as sites of women's sociality, cf. Ar. Lys. (especially 1–3), Thesm., Eccl. (especially 17–18); Men. Dys., Epit. 476–8; Lys. 1.20; Sappho, fr. 94.25–8 Voigt.

22 Cf. Griffin (n. 4), 190–1: ‘Ideally, such scenes [of great emotional intensity as feature in tragedy] should also involve some important moral choice or some human disaster, and—above all—they should bring in the agency and participation of the gods.’

23 E.g. Blok, J.H., ‘Virtual voices: toward a choreography of women's speech in Classical Athens’, in Lardinois, A.P.M.H. and McClure, L. (edd.), Making Silence Speak: Women's Voices in Greek Literature and Society (Princeton and Oxford, 2001), 96116Google Scholar; Lewis, S., The Athenian Woman: An Iconographic Handbook (London and New York, 2002), 192–3Google Scholar; Llewellyn-Jones, L., Aphrodite's Tortoise: The Veiled Woman of Ancient Greece (Swansea, 2003), 189214CrossRefGoogle Scholar; L.C. Nevett, ‘Towards a female topography of the ancient Greek city: case studies from Late Archaic and Early Classical Athens (c.520–400 BCE)’, Gender & History 23 (2011), 576–96. For the visibility of girls and women in the street, cf. the ambivalent evidence of Ar. Ach. 253–5, 262; of women in sanctuaries, Isae. 5.39.

24 Gendered undernourishment: Taylor, C., Poverty, Wealth, & Well-Being: Experiencing Penia in Democratic Athens (Oxford, 2017), 130–1CrossRefGoogle Scholar. The extent of gendered exposure of infants is controversial: Patterson, C., ‘“Not worth the rearing”: the causes of infant exposure in ancient Greece’, TAPhA 115 (1985), 103–23Google Scholar; Demand, N., Birth, Death, and Motherhood in Classical Greece (Baltimore and London, 1994), 67Google Scholar; Ingalls, W., ‘Demography and dowries: perspectives on female infanticide in Classical Greece’, Phoenix 56 (2002), 246–54CrossRefGoogle Scholar; also Sneed, D., ‘Disability and infanticide in ancient Greece’, Hesperia 90 (2021), 747–72CrossRefGoogle Scholar, cautioning against poorly evidenced assumptions about grounds for infanticide.

25 Golden (n. 10), 114–15.

26 L. Coo, ‘Greek tragedy and the theatre of sisterhood’, in P.J. Finglass and L. Coo (edd.), Female Characters in Fragmentary Greek Tragedy (Cambridge, 2020), 40–61, at 40.

27 CEG 2.541, EM 8888. This is the text visible to me, more conservative than Kirchner's in IG II². The underlined text denotes letters recorded by Ross, L., Allgemeine Literatur-Zeitung 5 (1837), at 692–3Google Scholar, 710–11 and Pittakis, K., AE 17 (1839), 277Google Scholar (§311) but no longer visible.

28 Peek, W., Griechische Grabgedichte, Griechisch und Deutsch (Berlin, 1960), 281CrossRefGoogle Scholar believes that they held their inheritance portion in common, which stretches μοίως: the usual terms for describing inherited property held in common are κοινόω, κοινός (Lys. 32.4, Dem. 47.34).

29 For the connection between the inheritance portion and the ‘portion’ of death, see Tsagalis, C., Inscribing Sorrow: Fourth-Century Attic Funerary Epigrams (Berlin and New York, 2008), 139–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

30 G. Kaibel (ed.), Epigrammata Graeca ex lapidibus conlecta (Berlin, 1878), 26–7 (§81).

31 Golden (n. 10), 115 understands it as ‘they regarded both their love and their property as common possessions’, but see n. 29 above.

32 E.g. Isae. 2.3 (two sisters, two brothers; speaker mentions girls’ marriages and dowries); Lys. 19.15 (two sisters, one brother; speaker mentions girls’ marriages and dowries); Isae. 5.5 (four sisters, one brother; speaker mentions girls’ marriages); Dem. 41.1 (two sisters, one adoptive brother; speaker mentions girls’ marriages, but at §21 presents the sisters acting together; see also SEG 17.83 with Shear, T.L., ‘The campaign of 1936’, Hesperia 6 (1937), 333–81CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 339–42.

33 Cf. J.K. Davies, Athenian Propertied Families, 600300 B.C. (Oxford, 1971), 141–2 on 3716.

34 Cf. S.B. Pomeroy, Families in Classical and Hellenistic Greece: Representations and Realities (Oxford, 1997), 172.

35 Outside oratory, Xen. Mem. 2.7 depicts shared labour and affect between sisters (and other female relatives).

36 Tchernetska et al. (n. 1 [2005]), 3, ad loc. In Lysias 32, the eldest orphaned boy (their mother is still alive) is allegedly thrown out of the house when he comes of age, goes to find his mother and brings her to his brother-in-law (§§9–10); as here, the orphan comes of age and goes to seek out his sister (on whom the boys in Lysias 32 partially base their plea to her husband for help).

37 Aesch. Cho. 631–4, Hdt. 6.138.4; S. Todd, unpublished paper cited by Whitehead (n. 2), 141.

38 Thür (n. 2 [2008a]), 652 and Thür (n. 2 [2008b]), 128–30, suggesting that Timandrus’ particular legal status as a cleruch may account for some of the alleged irregularities in his dealing with the orphans’ estate; Bearzot (n. 2), 285–6. Reorganization of cleruchic land after Lemnos was restored to Athens in the Peace of Antalcidas: Agora XVI no. 41; individuals using Athenian demotics on Lemnos in the fourth century: M. Segre, ‘Iscrizioni greche di Lemno’, ASAA 15–16 (1942), 289–314, no. 14, Accame, S., ‘Iscrizioni del Cabirio di Lemno’, AASA 19–21 (1948), 75105Google Scholar, nos. 1 and 2; see further E. Culasso Gastaldi, ‘L'isola di Lemno attraverso la documentazione epigrafica’, AASA 138 (2010), 349–66; land on Lemnos owned by the Antiochis tribe: SEG 3.117. See C. Igelbrink, Die Kleruchien und Apoikien Athens im 6. und 5. Jahrhundert v. Chr.: Rechtsformen und politische Funktionen der athenischen Gründungen (Berlin and Boston, 2015), 184–97 for the nature and strategic purpose of Lemnos (and Imbros) and Marchiandi, D., ‘Riflessioni in merito allo statuto giuridico di Lemno nel V secolo a.C. La ragnatela bibliografica e l'evidenza archeologica: un dialogo possibile?’, AASA 86 (2010), 1138Google Scholar for the legal status of the Lemnians.

39 Wyse, W., The Speeches of Isaeus (Cambridge, 1904), 499Google Scholar, on Isae. 5.13.2; cf. Bearzot (n. 2).

40 See e.g. R. Maltby (ed.), Terence: Phormio (Oxford, 2012), 18–25.

41 The ‘blood’ metaphor is not present in the Greek (contrast Arist. Eth. Nic. 1161b3, discussed later) but conveys the sense.

42 For Aristotle's analysis of φιλία, see J. Whiting, ‘The Nicomachean account of philia’, in R. Kraut (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics (Williston, 2006), 276–304.

43 On the ‘endoxic method’, see R. Kraut, ‘How to justify ethical propositions: Aristotle's method’, in R. Kraut (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics (Williston, 2006), 76–95; on its use for socio-cultural history, see Cartledge, P., The Greeks: A Portrait of Self and Others (Oxford, 1993), 121–2Google Scholar (slightly overstated?).

44 Aristotle defines ενοια more narrowly and understands reciprocal ενοια as necessary but not sufficient for φιλία (1167a); here he also identifies ενοια as a source of φιλία. Cf. Whiting (n. 42), 280–4.

45 E.g. Lycurg. Leoc. 48: feelings towards one's father (asserting the primacy of biology—though in comparison to adoption, which often happened in the adoptee's adulthood); Diod. Sic. 1.71.4: a feeling akin to φιλοστοργία among kin; 18.41.3: friends faithful to the point of death.

46 Aristotle uses the adjective πατρικός, meaning ‘paternal’; his explanation uses the noun ο γονες, which means ‘parents’ in the plural, as here, but ‘father’ in the singular.

47 Sahlins, M., What Kinship Is—And Is Not (Chicago, 2013), 20CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

48 See n. 46 on the gendering of this word.

49 S. Broadie and C.J. Rowe (edd.), Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics (Oxford, 2002), 415 on 1159b32.

50 Cohabitation: Isae. 1.12, 18, 28; 6.21; 8.7, 14; 9.27, 30. Shared religious practice: 1.31; 8.15–16; 9.21, 30; also Lys. 1.20.

51 Rubinstein (n. 2), especially 149–56.

52 Jones (n. 2), Schmitz (n. 2).

53 IG I3 422, lines 193–9, with Schmitz (n. 2) and W. Schmitz, ‘“Sklavenfamilien” im archaischen und klassischen Griechenland’, in J. Deissler and H. Heinen (edd.), Kindersklaven, Sklavenkinder: Schicksale zwischen Zuneigung und Ausbeutung in der Antike und im interkulturellen Vergleich: Beiträge zur Tagung des Akademievorhabens Forschungen zur antiken Sklaverei (Mainz, 14. Oktober 2008) (Stuttgart, 2012), 63–102, at 78.

54 Schmitz (n. 53), 78–9.

55 Cf. Schmitz (n. 53), 79.

56 The inscriptions are collected by Meyer, E.A., Metics and the Athenian Phialai-inscriptions: A Study in Athenian Epigraphy and Law (Stuttgart, 2010)Google Scholar, though she argues that they represent not manumissions but unsuccessful prosecutions of metics. For the families, see Humphreys (n. 16), 176–7.

57 O. Patterson, Slavery and Social Death: A Comparative Study (Cambridge, MA and London, 1982), 6. O. Patterson, ‘Trafficking, gender and slavery: past and present’, in J. Allain (ed.), The Legal Understanding of Slavery: From the Historical to the Contemporary (Oxford, 2012), 322–59, at 323–9 updates the term ‘natal alienation’ to ‘social isolation’ ‘to take account of the non-legality of modern slavery’; as he argues, the essential characteristics of the enslaved person's condition remain the same.

58 Patterson (n. 57 [1982]), 8.

59 Cf. Grg. 511c–512, with T. Irwin (ed.), Plato Gorgias (Oxford, 2019) on 483b, 511e–512a.

60 J.D. Porter, ‘The sexual agency of slaves in Classical Athens’, in D. Kamen and C.W. Marshall (edd.), Slavery and Sexuality in Classical Antiquity (Madison, WI, 2021), 80–97 contextualizes this recommendation within what he argues is a specifically Classical Athenian view of sexual (and family) relationships between enslaved people as primarily a means for enslavers to control them, as opposed to a means of ‘producing’ more enslaved people.

61 On the distinction between a κάπηλος (retailer/dealer) and an μπορος (trader/trafficker), see Jones (n. 2), 19, citing LSJ s.v. μπορος III: an μπορος ‘mak[es] voyages and import[s] goods himself’.

62 Some text is missing, but the meaning is fairly clear: Jones (n. 2), 20.

63 Gaca (n. 13 [2010]), 139.

64 For this paradox, see e.g. C. Meillassoux, The Anthropology of Slavery: The Womb of Iron and Gold, transl. A. Dasnois (Chicago, 1991), 9–10; D.B. Davis, The Problem of Slavery in Western Culture (Ithaca, 1966), 62; in Classical Greek thought, P. Millett, ‘Aristotle and slavery in Athens’, G&R 54 (2007), 178–209, especially 183–8, 196–200; Brunt, P.A., Studies in Greek History and Thought (Oxford, 1993), 347–8Google Scholar; Finley, M.I., Ancient Slavery and Modern Ideology (London, 1980), 118–19Google Scholar.

65 Cf. Gaca, K.L., ‘Manhandled and “kicked around”: reinterpreting the etymology and symbolism of νδράποδα’, Indogermanischen Forschungen 116 (2011), 110–46CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 125, with n. 34 for σώματα used to describe ‘human (as distinct from animal) plunder’.

66 Zelnick-Abramovitz, R., Not Wholly Free: The Concept of Manumission and the Status of Manumitted Slaves in the Ancient Greek World (Leiden, 2005), 3657CrossRefGoogle Scholar argues that in this context φιλία should be understood to mean ‘a social bond involving exchange of services and loyalty’ (37), of which ‘friendship’ in the modern sense is a subset but not an equivalent (45).

67 E.g. Zelnick-Abramowitz (n. 66), 53–7; Millett (n. 64), 186–8; Brunt (n. 64), 366–71; Garnsey, P., Ideas of Slavery from Aristotle to Augustine (Cambridge, 1996), 124–7Google Scholar.

68 Zelnick-Abramovitz (n. 66), 37–57 analyses φιλία in enslaved–enslaver pairs.

69 Cf. Mulgan, R.G., Aristotle's Political Theory: An Introduction for Students of Political Theory (Oxford, 1977), 15Google Scholar on the impossibility of κοινωνία in the enslaver–enslaved relationship.

70 On this ambivalence in Aristotle, cf. Broadie and Rowe (n. 49), 416 on 1161b6–7.