Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-4hhp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-12T00:22:16.519Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Oblique differential object marking and types of nominals

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 December 2021

Monica Alexandrina Irimia*
Affiliation:
University of Modena and Reggio Emilia, Modena, Italy
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The question of whether differentially marked objects should be linked with Case licensing or some other mechanism in the grammar has given rise to numerous debates. Addressing contexts of differential object marking (DOM) with oblique morphology, this article shows that, while the Case licensing approach might be adequate for varieties of Spanish, oblique differential marking rather signals an independent licensing operation, beyond Case, in languages like Romanian, Gujarati or Mandarin Chinese. This additional mechanism, relevant at the syntax-semantics-pragmatics interface, tracks the role of grammaticalized animates or how the speaker relates to other entities in the discourse. Additionally, the data examined here indicate that objects can come in a variety of sizes and structures, with distinct licensing constraints, such that the divide Case licensed/unlicensed or Case licensing/(pseudo-)incorporation is not enough.

Résumé

Résumé

La question de savoir si les objets marqués de manière différentielle doivent être liés à au licenciement casuel ou à un autre mécanisme de la grammaire a donné lieu à de nombreux débats. Abordant les contextes de marquage différentiel d'objets obliques, cet article montre que, bien que l'approche qui lie le marquage différentiel avec le licenciement casuel puisse être adéquate pour les variétés d'espagnol, le marquage différentiel oblique signale plutôt une opération de licenciement indépendante, au-delà du licenciement casuel, dans des langues comme le roumain, le gujarati ou le chinois mandarin. Ce mécanisme supplémentaire, pertinent à l'interface syntaxe-sémantique-pragmatique, suit le rôle des arguments animés grammaticalisés, ou comment le locuteur se rapporte à d'autres entités dans le discours. De plus, les données examinées ici indiquent que les objets peuvent être de tailles et de structures variées, avec des contraintes de licenciement distinctes, de sorte que la distinction ‘licencié par le cas/non-licencié’ ou ‘licencié par le cas/(pseudo-)incorporation’ n'est pas suffisante.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Linguistic Association/Association canadienne de linguistique 2021

1. Introduction

An important reflex of the internal structure of nominals is their behaviour in sentential syntax. Cross-linguistically, a relevant split has been observed between nominals that do not project a full structure (being NPs or NumberPs) and bigger nominals with additional functional heads, such as D0 or K0 (Bittner and Hale Reference Bittner and Hale1996, Massam Reference Massam2001, Danon Reference Danon2006, Ghomeshi Reference Ghomeshi, Karimi, Samiian and Stilo2008, López Reference López2012, Levin Reference Levin2015 for distinctions between KPs and DPs).Footnote 1 In many languages, more complex structure might induce interpretive and/or scrambling correlates, generally connected to the presence of a (uninterpretable) CaseFootnote 2 feature that needs valuation in syntax. Reduced structure, instead, can be limited to non-specific interpretations, prototypical or number neutral readings, with the nominal and the verb sometimes even forming a unit. Under one possibility, the nominal head is incorporated into a verbal head (via head movement, or base generated X0 adjunction, Baker Reference Baker1988), and they form together an X0 constituent. The literature has also identified a less radical process under which a nominal without functional extended projections is base generated as a complement to V and forms a minimal VP with the latter. This process, labeled pseudo-incorporation by Massam (Reference Massam2001), has been discussed for many languages, under many diverse realizations (Farkas and de Swart Reference Farkas and de Swart2003, Dayal Reference Dayal2011, the contributions in Borik and Gehrke Reference Borik and Gehrke2015).

In this article I examine issues related to nominal structure and size which are harder to accommodate under this broad split (namely, licensing in terms of Case vs (pseudo-)incorporation). I restrict my attention to phenomena in the class of differential object marking with oblique morphology (henceforth oblique DOM). A long-standing intuition associates the oblique marker with Case licensing on higher functional heads, such as D0, K0, forcing such nominals to escape (pseudo-)incorporation (Kornfilt Reference Kornfilt and Karimi2003, Ghomeshi Reference Ghomeshi, Karimi, Samiian and Stilo2008, López Reference López2012) and undergo obligatory licensing in the syntax (Ormazabal and Romero Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013a, Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013b; Kalin Reference Kalin2018).

The data I am concerned with come from Romance (Spanish, Romanian), Indo-Aryan (Gujarati), and Sino-Tibetan (Mandarin Chinese). A problem in these languages is that the morpho-syntactic encoding of their objects cannot be easily reduced to the split (pseudo-)incorporation vs. oblique DOM. One issue is that, besides oblique DOM, there appear to be other structural objects that come with positional and more general licensing constraints, similar to uninterpretable Case, suggesting that they too escape (pseudo-)incorporation and need licensing, even if they do not carry oblique DOM. These observations raise two questions, which will be addressed in this article: i) how to analyze oblique DOM so as to distinguish it from other non-incorporating objects; ii) what precise strategies correlating nominal size and licensing are possible in human language.

I propose that these, more complex, nominal patterns can be reconciled under the hypothesis that oblique DOM signals a separate licensing operation, beyond uninterpretable Case, on nominals with an enriched structure. This additional mechanism, relevant at the syntax-semantics-pragmatics interface (but distinct from topicality or specificity in some of these languages), is connected with the valuation of an interpretable feature, tracking the role of animates or how the speaker relates to other entities in the discourse. As the initial licenser (v 0) in the relevant domain (below TP) is needed for Case, any additional features will use an additional licenser (following Jaeggli Reference Jaeggli1982). The languages under discussion recruit a functional projection from the low discourse-related layer in the vP (following Belletti Reference Belletti and Rizzi2004 or Pancheva and Zubizaretta Reference Pancheva and Zubizarreta2018), which will value any features left behind by the initial licenser, resulting in the spell-out of oblique DOM. The work also builds on recent discussions about a type of A licensing, related to δ (discourse) features (Miyagawa Reference Miyagawa2017, Belletti Reference Belletti, Petrosino, Pietro and van der Hulst2018, Mursell Reference Mursell2018), extending it beyond topics. I also show that reducing oblique DOM to a morphological operation cannot account for the various syntactic effects it gives rise to. Another line of research the article contributes to is the exploration of a syntax-pragmatics interface layer in the high periphery of nominals (such as the discourse information-bearing Speech Act domain, in Ritter and Wiltschko Reference Ritter and Wiltschko2019, or Hill and Mardale's Reference Hill and Mardale2021 multi-layered DP).

The structure of the article is as follows. In section 2, I introduce data illustrating oblique DOM and other direct objects (DO) in standard Spanish. I review two prominent accounts: i) oblique DOM equated with Case, anti-incorporation and obligatory licensing (Ormazabal and Romero Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013a, Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013b), and ii) oblique DOM as obligatory raising (López Reference López2012). In section 3, I present a related oblique-DOM prominent language, Romanian, where these two hypotheses appear to be problematic. Although similar to other objects that cannot be analyzed under pseudo-incorporation and which appear to require licensing, Romanian DOM is not easily identified via raising; moreover, it cannot be equated just with a morphological operation, as it gives rise to important syntactic effects. The hypothesis that DOM is a syntactic, A-related licensing mechanism beyond Case can capture its behaviour in a non-stipulative way. In section 4, I turn to Gujarati; in this language oblique DOM, similarly to other objects which appear to equally escape pseudo-incorporation, co-occurs with object agreement, which results from an independent nominal licensing mechanism. The idea of an additional licensing operation for oblique DOM explains these two co-occurring overt realizations (agreement and oblique DOM) for Gujarati direct objects. In section 5, I extend the same analysis to the ba marker in Mandarin Chinese, deriving its scrambling to a yet higher position than other objects which, similarly, cannot undergo (pseudo)-incorporation due to their complex structure. Section 6 summarizes the results and concludes with further brief remarks about the role of oblique DOM in the realm of licensing operations, and remaining questions.

2. Differential object marking in standard Spanish

Spanish direct objects come in a variety of sizes (Torrego Reference Torrego1998; Leonetti Reference Leonetti, Heusinger and Kaiser2003, Reference Leonetti2008; Bleam Reference Bleam2005; Laca Reference Laca2006; Rodríguez-Mondoñedo Reference Rodríguez-Mondoñedo2007; López Reference López2012). As illustrated below in (1a) they can be bare (especially if plural), can take an overt indefinite morpheme or the definite one. Additionally and mainly regulated by animacy, object nominals with overt (in)definiteness morphology can surface with a preposition which is homophonous with the dative, instantiating a type of oblique DOM. The preposition is obligatory with animate definites, as in (1b); with animate indefinites (1c), as the traditional wisdom goes, the preposition is restricted to a specific interpretation (Rivero Reference Rivero and Rivero1979). In this article, I am precisely interested in investigating the nature of objects that take this prepositional marker and their syntactic relation to other direct objects.

Splits in the morpho-syntactic encoding of direct objects, based on features such as animacy, specificity, topicality, etc. are not rare cross-linguistically (Givón Reference Givón and Plank1984; Comrie Reference Comrie1989; Bossong Reference Bossong, Wanner and Kibbee1991, Reference Bossong and Feuillet1998; Aissen Reference Aissen2003; Rodríguez-Mondoñedo Reference Rodríguez-Mondoñedo2007; Haspelmath Reference Haspelmath2008; López Reference López2012; Bárány Reference Bárány2017). In order to capture the complexities of the (standard) Spanish data, it is generally assumed that both an animacy and a specificity scale are necessary (forming a multidimensional DOM system):

Recent formal work has, however, demonstrated that an account in terms of scales reveals several shortcomings. A serious problem is that the prepositional marker must override its ‘canonical’ animacy and specificity features in a variety of contexts, which can instead be unified structurally (López Reference López2012; Ormazabal and Romero Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013a, Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013b.). For example, Ormazabal and Romero (Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013a, Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013b) note that nominals in Exceptional Case Marking (ECM)-type contexts take obligatory oblique DOM in Spanish varieties, even irrespectively of animacy. López (Reference López2012) has, likewise, presented examples with obligatory DOM in the absence of specificity or animacy.Footnote 3

In order to provide a comprehensive account for these types of patterns, a more abstract condition on nominals has to be assumed, going beyond the encoding of animacy and specificity. Therefore, recent formal research has equated oblique DOM with the presence of an uninterpretable Case (uCase/uC) feature (Chomsky Reference Chomsky1995, et seq.) which requires licensing in sentential syntax, thus forcing the nominal to escape (pseudo-)incorporation (see especially López Reference López2012; Ormazabal and Romero Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013a, Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013b).

An important observation in this direction was made by Ormazabal and Romero (Reference Ormazabal and Romero2007; Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013a, Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013b) and takes into account interpretational shifts that lack of DOM triggers in some contexts. Staying with (continental) varieties of Spanish for now, DOM is not possible in a configuration that also contains an indirect object which is clitic doubled.Footnote 4 An example is provided in (4), from Ormazabal and Romero (Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013b, ex. 2b).Footnote 5 If both the indirect object (IO) and its dative (dat) clitic double are to be kept, then DOM must be removed.

Ormazabal and Romero (Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013b:157) mention the following with respect to the interpretation of the animate DOM-less direct object in examples similar to (4):

the availability of (4) [O&R's 2b, my note] is extremely restricted. Sentences like (4) – [O&R's 2b, my note] are only grammatical with nouns such as sick people, soldiers, slaves, kids, etc.; nouns whose referents are regularly treated as entities lacking free will. The range of animate nouns that can appear without dom in this context is, more or less, the same one that allows incorporation in polysynthetic languages….Footnote 7

In fact, DOM ungrammaticality is confirmed in contexts that flag (pseudo-) incorporationFootnote 8 cross-linguistically (such as existential clauses, individual level have predicates, transitives with bare plural objects, see Bleam Reference Bleam2005; López Reference López2012; Ormazabal and Romero Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013a, Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013b), as also summarized in Table 1 in subsection 3.2.

Table 1: DOM in Spanish and Romanian (fragment)

Based on remarks along these lines, Ormazabal and Romero assume that unmarked nominals either undergo complex predicate formation with the verb (plurals of type <e,t>, etc.) or simply stay unlicensed (definites), grouping together both NPs and DPs, as in (5a). DOM-ed nominals, on the other hand, have a more complex structure, projecting a KP layer which hosts the accusative Case feature, as in (5b). The latter needs to be valued in the syntax via raising to a position above VP, blocking pseudo-incorporation.

  1. (5)

As further discussed by López (Reference López2012), DOM as an anti-incorporation mechanism can also explain the obligatoriness of the oblique marker in Small Clauses (SC) and other clause union contexts (see also fn. 3). Generally, only objects in a complement position to V can undergo (pseudo-)incorporation (Baker Reference Baker1988, Massam Reference Massam2001, López Reference López2012). In SCs, on the other hand, the shared nominal is never found in a complement position to V, no matter whether these constructions are seen as projecting a reduced/small clausal structure, as in (6a) or as constructing complex predicates, as in (6b):

  1. (6)

2.1 López (Reference López2012) – DOM and other nominals with Case

Although the unlicensed/licensed divide can explain the many DOM exceptions to the scales, it also leaves some questions unanswered. For example, assuming that SCs block nominal (pseudo-)incorporation and require licensing on the nominal, the prediction would be that inanimate objects should always show DOM in this context. This appears to be borne out in several varieties of Spanish; but standard Spanish speakers judge DOM ungrammatical on inanimate nominals in SCs, as shown in (7). There is, however, an important restriction – bare forms of nominals are completely ungrammatical and thus, (in)definite morphology is obligatory on the shared argument.Footnote 9

To summarize, SCs show the following: i) DOM appears to be obligatory regardless of specificity (see López Reference López2012) on animates (which moreover cannot be bare); ii) inanimates do not allow DOM (in standard Spanish), but cannot be bare. The obligatory presence of overt (in)definiteness can be taken as indication of a licensing condition in these anti-incorporation contexts too; only nominals of a certain size are allowed. This, in turn, suggests that the basic split (pseudo-)incorporation vs. Case marking is not enough. López (Reference López2012) motivates a similar conclusion.

Thus, López (Reference López2012) has a more nuanced take on the (pseudo-)incorporation vs. Case licensing issue and its relevance to DOM. The author explicitly mentions that the grammar of Spanish contains other nominals which have a structural [uCase] feature, besides the DOM-ed ones. Objects that carry the oblique DOM preposition are a sub-type of the Case licensed structural accusatives; what sets them apart is their obligatory raising to a position above VP in order to have their [uCase] valued. For López (Reference López2012), other (unmarked) objects with a structural [uCase] feature are licensed only by v0. In the case of definites, it is the definite functional head that incorporates into V and is licensed after V raising to v0.Footnote 10

López (Reference López2012) provides arguments from binding, demonstrating that marked nominals are above the IO, but below the external argument (EA). Their accusative [uCase] is valued in a position above VP but below the EA. This is shown in (8a), where the DO raises to the specifier of an intermediate head α (which bundles aspectual and applicative features); in that position it can be probed by v 0. This short scrambling operation explains DOM presence in a position c-commanding the IO, and thus binding from DO into IO.Footnote 11

DOM-ed nominals contain a KP layer, where the Case feature, associated with a choice function (f), is housed (8b). According to López (Reference López2012), f switches the semantic type of the nominal from <e, t> to <e> (or a more complex type for quantifiers), and can only be interpreted in a position above VP.

Case valuation is understood as feature sharing under the Agree operation, which values or co-values all the uninterpretable features (uf) features on v 0 and DO, as in (9). López (Reference López2012) further assumes a locality restriction on Agree; the probe (v 0) can at most reach the specifier of its complement.

  1. (8)

  2. (9) Agree   (a[f], b[uf]) → (a[f], b[f])       (López Reference López2012: 35)

The differential preposition is inserted at PF if certain conditions are met, for example if an animate feature is present, as in (10a), or whether α is specified as telic, as in (10b).

  1. (10)

As already mentioned, López (Reference López2012) shows that there can be other nominals specified with a structural [uCase] feature, but which do not show the differential marker; nevertheless, all objects with [uCase], no matter whether differentially marked or not, have an accusative syntactic behaviour (hence the traditional label prepositional accusative for DOM). This observation is confirmed by a variety of diagnostics, such as the possibility of passivization, etc. (see also Bárány Reference Bárány2018). However, the more precise licensing mechanism for non-DOM-ed (and non-incorporated) direct objects with [uCase] needs further attention. An observation is that not all oblique DOM systems can be subsumed under the two theories presented above. In the next section, I turn to Romanian, a language which exhibits one of the most complex DOM systems not only within Romance, but also cross-linguistically.

3. Differential object marking in Romanian

Similarly to Spanish, Romanian oblique DOM is sensitive to animacy (Niculescu Reference Niculescu and Niculescu1965; Dobrovie-Sorin Reference Dobrovie-Sorin1990, Reference Dobrovie-Sorin1994; Cornilescu Reference Cornilescu2000; Tigău Reference Tigău2011; Irimia Reference Irimia, Bárány and Kalin2020, a.o.). As illustrated in (11a), the animate definite can be introduced by a preposition which is homophonous with a locative.Footnote 12 In this type of context, an inanimate cannot take the differential preposition, as shown in (11b). The marked objects can (and in some configurations, must) also be clitic-doubled, using the accusative form of the clitic.Footnote 13

Example (11a) illustrates a first difference from Spanish:Romanian DOM is optional with referential definite animates, as opposed to obligatory in Spanish (1b). One cannot conclude, however, that DOM is optional in Romanian. The challenge is that there are many configurations where absence of DOM results in ungrammaticality, as in (12). They illustrate: i) the negative quantifier nimeni (‘nobody’); ii) the animate wh-element cine (‘who’);Footnote 14 iii) the elliptical demonstrative in its augmented form;Footnote 15 iv) the D-linked element care (‘which’). The latter two are also part of a large class of contexts where DOM is obligatory irrespective of animacy (and specificity). In turn, in (12e) we see the object of a psych-verb (interesa) with oblique DOM and clitic doubling that appear to be needed for most speakers.Footnote 16 In general, although Romanian and Spanish oblique DOM share a general profile, there are also important differences. In fact, given its many complications, Romanian DOM is still in need of an adequate formal explanation.

3.1 Romanian DOM and anti-incorporation

Given the obvious problems with accounts in terms of scales, we need to test the predictions of the two formal analyses introduced in the previous section for Spanish: i) oblique DOM as a licensing mechanism on nominals with a structural [uCase] feature, which need obligatory licensing in syntax (Ormazabal and Romero Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013a, Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013b); ii) DOM as a subclass of nominals with [uCase], signaled via overt raising (López Reference López2012).

A conclusion is clear. Contexts signalling nominals (of type <e,t>) which might undergo complex predicate formation with V, or which can stay unlicensed in Spanish or cross-linguistically (such as existential clauses, individual level have predicates, transitives with bare plural objects,Footnote 17 mentioned in section 2), do block oblique DOM in Romanian too (as seen in Table 1). For example, ungrammaticality of oblique DOM with possessive have under individual-level readings is illustrated below.Footnote 18

Turning now to contexts that signal anti-incorporation, namely SCs (or clause union more generally), we notice an important difference from Spanish. Remember from the discussion in section 2 (and fn. 3) that Spanish animates generally require DOM in these contexts. This was one of the arguments for associating oblique DOM with a more abstract licensing condition, namely [uCase]. In Romanian, however, animate definites are possible without DOM in SCs; but, crucially, nominal distribution is not completely free – just like in Spanish, bare nominalsFootnote 19 are strictly excluded, as in (14). Also note that categories which need obligatory DOM outside SCs also need to have it here (15). This latter observation supports the conclusion that SCs are not only anti-incorporation contexts, but also signal (in these languages) an abstract licensing need on the nominal.Footnote 20

In Romanian, some bare nominals can be found in contexts that are similar to complex predicate formation, more generally (be it pseudo-incorporation or some other mechanism); thus, one can assume that these latter classes lack an [uCase] feature, as they are probably NPs or NumPs. Definites and specific indefinites, on the other hand, (can) project a larger structure as DPs. The obligatoriness of overt (in)definiteness morphology in SC contexts such as (14) in turn indicates that that this piece of morphology is associated with a structural Case feature, which allows it to escape complex predication formation with V (under pseudo-incorporation, etc.).Footnote 21 The [uCase] feature is located in D0, under most accounts (see especially Giusti Reference Giusti1993). But this entails that: i) oblique DOM (which must be linked to a KP layer) signals some licensing constraint on the nominal independently of [uCase] per se, and ii) the split pseudo-incorporation vs. [uCase] licensing is not enough, thus confirming López’ (Reference López2012) observations. Moreover, as actually seen in the various examples presented in the article, the Romanian differential preposition is independent of definitenessFootnote 22 or indefiniteness morphology and is linearized in a position that precedes these morphemes.

3.2 Romanian oblique DOM and raising

Let's evaluate now the other observation made by López (Reference López2012), namely that DOM signals a subclass of nominals with [uCase], which must undergo overt raising to an intermediate position between VP and v 0. Romanian confirms that non-clitic-doubled oblique DOM is generated below the EA, as no binding into the EA is possible (see the various examples in Hill and Mardale Reference Hill and Mardale2021). However, if we examine binding and c-command relations between DOs and IOs, it cannot be concluded that DOM-ed objects are higher than IOs. In the example in (16a), binding from DOM into IO does not go through.Footnote 23 Binding from IO into DOM is fine, as demonstrated in (16b). This difference from Spanish indicates that Romanian differential objects can be lower than both the IO and the EA. Of course, this, in itself, does not prove that Romanian oblique DOM does not need raising. It could be that it raises, but to a position below the IO, which is still above VP. The problem is that unmarked nominals show the exact same behaviour, and it is moreover not easy to map this position.Footnote 24

Table 1 contains both similarities and differences regarding Spanish and Romanian DOM.Footnote 25 As Romanian DOM is not obligatory on definite animates in SCs (anti-incorporation contexts), and raising to Spec, α is not motivated, some other explanation needs to be found for Romanian oblique DOM beyond obligatory raising (for [uCase]).

3.3 Romanian DOM is not derived in the morphology

To summarize, Romanian objects indicate the following: i) some classes, such as the bare nominals, might pass diagnostics indicating pseudo-incorporation; ii) other classes, such as (certain types of) nominals with overt (in)definiteness morphology, as well as the prepositional accusatives, escape this process; instead, they give evidence for licensing in syntax – they contain a [uCase] feature, which can explain their (positional) restrictions; iii) as (in)definites with or without differential marking have a different shape on the surface, the question is what accounts for the presence of the differential marker with certain types of non-incorporating DOs; iv) an explanation according to which DOM signals just those nominals with [uCase] which undergo short scrambling to a position above the IO does not easily go through in the language. Although raising cannot be completely ruled out, in this regard, marked and unmarked objects behave similarly.Footnote 26

Some classical and some more recent discussions (Halle and Marantz Reference Halle, Marantz, Hale and Kayser1993, Keine and Müller Reference Keine, Müller, Richards and Malchukov2008, Keine Reference Keine2010, a.o.) have explored a morphological explanation for oblique DOM. Both oblique DOM and other [uC] objects are seen as having the same syntax as licensed objects; the only difference is given by the (obligatory) application of a morphological operation (e.g., Impoverishment) which removes the accusative case features and inserts an oblique marker, in the environment of certain features, such as animacy (for example, the schematic, simplified rule [acc] → [+obl]/_[+animate]).

Connecting oblique DOM to morphological Impoverishment explains the syntactic properties it shares with other objects with [uC] and might give the right results for some oblique DOM languages. But it proves problematic for Romanian; although DOM and other accusative objects with [uC] undergo Case licensing and can occupy the same position, there are syntactic properties they do not share. Illustrating with one example, Romanian DOM gives rise to co-occurrence restrictions with certain types of dative clitics.Footnote 27 The ungrammatical sentence in (17a) contains DOM and a dative clitic with a possessive reading. An unmarked DO is well-formed, as in (17b).Footnote 28

In (17a) ungrammaticality obtains under the possessor reading of the dative reflexive clitic. This same clitic can have many other interpretations in Romanian, such as the (high) applicative one. If we test a configuration in which the dative clitic cannot be interpreted as a possessor on DOM we obtain grammaticality. In (18), the negative quantifier, which takes obligatory DOM, does not allow a possessor reading of the dative possessor clitic.Footnote 29 These two examples demonstrate that the DOM restriction is not a morphological one and that DOM has a different syntax than the unmarked objects with a [uCase] feature. As this syntactic difference cannot be unambiguously tied to a different position for DOM in Romanian, we need to explore other explanations into its nature.

3.4 DOM as an additional licensing operation beyond Case

The solution I propose here links oblique DOM to an additional licensing operation beyond [uCase]. In a nutshell, I start from the assumption that the extended projection of nominals can contain other features that are merged above the functional projection which houses [uCase]. Building on and extending observations going back to Jaeggli (Reference Jaeggli1982), if the main licenser in a domain can value only [uCase], an additional licenser will be needed for an additional feature beyond [uCase]. The differential marker results from the activation of this additional licenser.

I build on decompositions in the higher left periphery of DPs (Ihsane and Puskás Reference Ihsane and Puskás2001, Harley and Ritter Reference Harley and Ritter2002, Ihsane Reference Ihsane2008, Hill and Mardale Reference Hill and Mardale2021), hypotheses related to stacking nominal speech act structures above the DP (Ritter and Wiltschko Reference Ritter and Wiltschko2019), as well as on observations regarding the importance of notions related to sentience and perspectivization in human language (Kuno and Kaburaki Reference Kuno and Kaburaki1977, Speas and Tenny Reference Speas, Tenny and Di Sciullo2003, Pancheva and Zubizarreta Reference Pancheva and Zubizarreta2018, Sundaresan Reference Sundaresan2018). It is not uncontroversial to assume that D0 is a phase edge in Romance, and the locus where interactions with the discourse are made available. In Romanian, referential nominal structures that project a D0 layer must escape incorporation, as they contain a [uCase] feature. What is relevant here is that, beyond Case, an expanded nominal structure can contain various other features, generally related to discourse (δ) and speech-act specifications. The structural organization of the discourse-related nominal periphery is not a trivial issue, and I cannot give an exhaustive cartography here. In (19), I only provide a very basic schema, including only specifications (such as Sentience) which are relevant for DOM in the languages discussed here.

If animates are salient in the discourse and other participants/the speaker relate to them, the Sentience layer is projected on the nominal. In other words, these types of animates are entities to which the speaker relates and which the speaker acknowledges. Following several hypotheses about the encoding of animacy in syntax (Cornilescu Reference Cornilescu2000, Adger and Harbour Reference Adger and Harbour2007, Rodríguez-Mondoñedo Reference Rodríguez-Mondoñedo2007, Richards Reference Richards, Richards and Malchukov2008, Bárány Reference Bárány2017) we can assume that discourse-salient animatesFootnote 30 of this type are signaled in syntax by an interpretable [person] feature merged in Sentience. Thus, the nominal in (19) contains both [uCase] as well as δ-related [person] which need licensing. The differential marker results from the impossibility of the main licenser to license the two features; as a result, an additional licenser must be used.Footnote 31 To explain the observation that in Romanian, DOM-ed objects can be found in a relatively low position, I follow Pancheva and Zubizarreta (Reference Pancheva and Zubizarreta2018) in assuming that the additional licenser is recruited from the domain with discourse related specifications in the vP (see also Belletti Reference Belletti and Rizzi2004, Jayaseelan Reference Jayaseelan2001, Tsai 2015, a.o).Footnote 32 For Pancheva and Zubizarreta (Reference Pancheva and Zubizarreta2018), notions such as empathy, which they collapse with perspectivization and viewpoint, are encoded as an interpretable feature in the Appl0 head, situated above V0 but below the EA. This might explain the use of dative as DOM in languages like Spanish. As Romanian uses a locative preposition instead, I make recourse to a more general α projection with δ-specifications.

Decomposing the low verbal domain into v and Voice, the latter introducing the EA (see Legate Reference Legate2014), we obtain the configuration in (20a). Here v0 values [uCase], but cannot value δ-[person]. It is the discourse-related projection α that values the ð feature. The result of the latter operation is the spell-out of oblique DOM, as in (20b).Footnote 33, Footnote 34

The hypothesis put forward here shares some intuitions with a long standing analysis for Romanian DOM in terms of the Kayne/Jaeggli Generalization.Footnote 35 The latter was proposed to account for contexts such as (12c) and (12d) where oblique DOM also needs accusative clitic doubling. The generalization linked DOM to a last resort Case checking mechanism to avoid a violation of the Case Filter – the accusative clitic absorbs the case from V, leaving the nominal caseless. We have seen, however, that accusative clitic doubling is not obligatory with DOM across the board (and in fact, in some contexts it is ungrammatical). In my analysis, what triggers the activation of the additional licenser is not the clitic, but the initial [uCase] feature, which also needs licensing.

  1. (20)

This account presents clear similarities with formalisms that link DOM to an information-structure strategy beyond Case.Footnote 36 Generally, oblique DOM is correlated with topics (the so-called secondary topics, see especially Dalrymple and Nikolaeva Reference Dalrymple and Nikolaeva2011; Leonetti Reference Leonetti, Heusinger and Kaiser2003, Reference Leonetti2008 for Spanish; Iemmolo Reference Iemmolo2010 for western Romance; or very recently, Onea and Mardale's Reference Onea and Mardale2020 E-topics).Footnote 37 Topic-hood finds a correlate in the observation that, in some languages, differentially marked objects can only be found in overt dislocation configurations, which exclude focus. However, an account in these terms is hard to extend to Romanian (and the other languages discussed here), where dislocated topics are insensitive to the oblique marker. Moreover, for many speakers, DOM does not have the phonetic correlates of topics; and, for all speakers, it is well formed under focus. In (21b) the differential marker is necessary on the argument which is not given, while in (22) we see DOM-ed animates under contrastive focus.Footnote 38, Footnote 39

Isolating sentience as a separate category, and the presence of generalized δ-features beyond [uCase] derive DOM insensitivity to topicality; moreover, it is a more plausible starting point to an explanation regarding co-occurrence restrictions of the type seen in (17), which are equally not easy to derive under DOM as topic.Footnote 40

4. Differential object marking in Gujarati

Similar types of problems are seen in Gujarati, an Indo-Aryan language which exhibits aspect-based split ergativity (Cardona Reference Cardona1965, Mistry Reference Mistry and Verma1976, Magier Reference Magier1983, Woolford Reference Woolford and Boeckx2006). We are mostly interested in examining perfective paradigms, where object agreement is indicated overtly as an inflectional suffix on the verbal stem. In (23a–c) we see three examples with the unaccusative predicate come. The only argument is a subject that can only take the absolutive form and agrees with the perfective stem in gender and number, as seen from an examination of subjects with different genders:

In the perfective, direct objects exhibit a more complex morpho-syntactic behaviour (Cardona Reference Cardona1965; Mistry Reference Mistry and Verma1976, Reference Mistry, Hill, Mistry and Campbell1997, Reference Mistry, Bhaskararao and Subbarao2004; Comrie Reference Comrie1984; Woolford Reference Woolford and Boeckx2006; Wunderlich Reference Wunderlich2012; Grosz and Patel-Grosz Reference Grosz, Patel-Grosz, Chandra and Shrishti2014 for Kutchi Gujarati; Joshi Reference Joshi, Pinon and Roussarie2020 for Surati Gujarati). Transitive predicates require the external arguments (the agents) to be marked with ergative case (the ergative postposition -e). Agreement can either be with the object or show up in a default form, depending on the interpretation (and the structure) of the latter. First, in some contexts and for some speakers, a number-neutral reading and a non-referential interpretation appear to be possible, while agreement with the object is blocked. In example (24) the perfective stem instead shows default (neuter gender) inflection, irrespective of the gender of the direct object (DO).Footnote 41

A referential interpretation of the nominal is possible if the perfective stem shows object agreement, which is realized in gender and number. In the examples I present in (25), there is object agreement and the object has to be interpreted either as definiteFootnote 42 or indefinite. When the plural marker is present on the direct object, as in (25b), a referential plural reading is obtained and object agreement is obligatory (when the subject has ergative case).Footnote 43

As I also mention later, this split is captured in formal accounts under the assumption that the agreeing objects contain a [uCase] feature which requires valuation. The non-agreeing objects (for those speakers who accept them) can be assumed to be NPs which do not contain a Case feature undergoing pseudo-incorporation with the verb.

This basic split is challenged by the existence of a third class of objects. Similarly to Romanian and Spanish, certain types of animates (especially those at the higher end of the animacy and referentiality scales) can/must take an oblique postposition, as in (26), under yet another instantiation of oblique DOM. Just like in Spanish, the DOM postposition is homophonous with the dative case maker -ne. However, despite their oblique appearance on the surface, DOM-ed objects must show agreement just like the bare, non-incorporating absolutives in (25). Lack of agreement with a differentially marked object would result in ill-formedness/ungrammaticality in the examples in (26).

As such, oblique DOM does not appear to have the syntax of indirect/oblique objects, which never trigger agreement on the perfective stem.Footnote 44 The absolutive syntax of DOM is confirmed by other diagnostics (passivization, lack of Case preservation under nominalization, etc.) under which DOM-ed objects and agreeing bare absolutive objects pattern alike, to the exclusion of indirect objects. Moreover, their structural absolutive nature matches the structural accusative status of such objects in Romanian and Spanish. We are left with the same question: where is the distinction between the agreeing absolutive and DOM to be located?

4.1 A licensing operation beyond [uCase]

Object agreement in Indo-Aryan has received a great deal of attention. I will be presenting below two main hypotheses initially formulated for Hindi-Urdu, but which can be applied to Gujarati too. For Mahajan (Reference Mahajan, Laka and Mahajan1989), the perfective participles in examples like (25) or (26) cannot assign accusative Case, as they are deficient. The Case of the objects in transitives embedded under perfective participles is assigned instead by an Agr0 head together with the finite tense projection. Case assignment is followed by object raising to Spec, AgrP, as illustrated in (27):

Bhatt (Reference Bhatt2005), on the other hand, has provided various diagnostics dissociating object agreement from Case assigning deficiency. The objects of transitives receive accusative Case from v 0, irrespective of whether the participle is perfective or imperfective. Object agreement results instead from the need to value the uninterpretable φ-features of T. Bhatt (Reference Bhatt2005) proposes an AGREEFootnote 45 operation under which the goal XP does not have to be active, that is, have unvalued Case features; instead, AGREE can/must target Case licensed objects. In examples like (25)/(26), given that ergative morphology renders the EA non-available, the non-incorporated direct object is the nearest argument with visible interpretable φ-features T0 can use to value its uninterpretable φ-features. Pseudo-incorporated objects, as in (24), do not permit this type of agreement in Gujarati.

No matter which of the two accounts above is to be used, it is clear that oblique DOM has to be linked to a distinct operation beyond [uCase]/AGREE. The hypothesis I have entertained in this article derives these empirical facts without problems. Oblique DOM results from the matching of a δ-related (person) feature, beyond [uCase], by a discourse-related sentience functional head in the low verbal projection; this is a distinct licensing operation, dissociated from the valuation of [uCase]. The need for an additional licenser for δ is also motivated by the observation that the perfective stem can only show overt gender and number agreement, but not person. In fact, as the literature mentions, object agreement in person is not available with auxiliaries either (see also Bhatt Reference Bhatt2005). We see in (28a) that the present auxiliary displays person agreement with the subject, but in (28b) person agreement with the object is not possible.

One question that comes to mind is whether this is an instantiation of Baker's (Reference Baker2011) SCOPA,Footnote 46 which postulates special structural configurations for person agreement, presumably not met in contexts like (28). However, this issue requires more attention, as demonstrated by languages such as southern Basque, where absolutives agree in person. Higher animate objects carry dative morphology, under a type of oblique DOM, as in Spanish/Gujarati. Dialectally, they can show either person dative agreement (Fernández and Rezac Reference Fernández, Rezac, Fernández and de Urbina2016, Odria Reference Odria2019, a.o.) or co-occur with person absolutive agreement (dative displacement varieties, Odria Reference Odria2017).Footnote 47 The special shape of DOM indicates an important difference between φ-related person features and δ-related person. They both need licensing (Odria Reference Odria2017, Reference Odria2019), but by distinct types of licensers.Footnote 48

5. Differential object marking in Mandarin Chinese

The last case study I will be addressing comes from Mandarin Chinese, whose objects appear to be subject to complex positional (and licensing) restrictions.

Mandarin Chinese is a typical analytical language; there is no overt case morphology or agreement, and overt definiteness and number morphology are also lacking. The default word order is SVO, but objects can also be found in a preverbal position. Distinct locations for objects do have interpretive consequences. For example, the postverbal nominal in (29) can be interpreted either as a singular or a plural, and it can get either an indefinite interpretation or a definite one:

Despite the absence of overt definiteness, nominal phrases can contain various pieces of morphology, such as demonstratives, numerals, classifiers, etc.Footnote 49 Such nominals can either precede or follow the verb, as seen in (30).

Yet, direct objects can surface with an even more complex structure. In a preverbal position, some classes of nominals must or can be preceded by the ba Footnote 50 marker. The ba construction (‘baziju’, ‘the disposal form’) has been extensively studied in both descriptive and formal studies, encompassing a vast literature (Li Reference Li1990, Reference Li, Everaert and van Riemsdijk2006; Zou Reference Zou1993; Liu Reference Liu1997; Sybesma Reference Sybesma1999; van Bergen Reference van Bergen2006; Yang and van Bergen Reference Yang and van Bergen2007; Huang et al. Reference Huang, Li and Li2009; Kuo Reference Kuo2010; Paul Reference Paul2015; Sun Reference Sun2018). Similarly to Romanian or Spanish, its conditions of use are extremely complex. Providing an exhaustive account is beyond the scope of this article, which has a much more modest goal. I am interested in examining the syntactic relationship of ba nominals to other nominal phrases, supporting the hypothesis of a licensing operation beyond [uCase] for DOM.

Generally, animate nouns and pronouns must be preceded by ba, as seen in (31a–b), while with inanimates the marker is optional, as in (31c).Footnote 51 However, DPs that contain the numeral/indefinite morpheme and are found in a preverbal position must be preceded by ba, irrespective of animacy. This is illustrated in (31d). Sensitivity to both animacy and definiteness/specificity indicates that the ba construction instantiates a bi-dimensional type of oblique DOM (just like in Spanish, Romanian and Gujarati).

These examples make it clear that connecting the ba construction with raising to a preverbal position is not enough to derive its nature, as there are speakers who accept objects in preverbal position without DOM, as in (31c). Similarly, linking DOM to a preverbal position and animacy is not sufficient either – in (31d) we see that ba is obligatory even with inanimates that have a certain type of structure.Footnote 52 As in the other languages I have discussed, an account in terms of scales (Animacy/Specificity) does not explain the data in a non-stipulative way. I show below that connecting ba with the distinction Case licensed vs. (pseudo-) incorporation is also not sufficient.

5.1 Ba and (pseudo-)incorporation

One property of ba DPs is undisputed in all grammars – such objects are never possible in a postverbal position. Native speakers confirm this observation, unanimously indicating that examples such as (32) are clearly ungrammatical with ba:

The question is then why the postverbal position is incompatible with ba DPs. This is not a simple problem. As Huang (Reference Huang, Bennett, Hracs and Storoshenko2018) notices, nominals that can appear in a postverbal position are not homogeneous, syntactically nor semantically. One important split is given by nominals that can precede or follow postverbal directional phrases (DirP), such as three years/three days in the examples in (33).

Following Huang et al. (Reference Huang, Li and Li2009), Huang (Reference Huang, Bennett, Hracs and Storoshenko2018) assumes that there are two argument positions inside VP, namely Spec, VP and as a complement to V. DirPs are left adjoined to the first projection of V, as seen in (34). Another observation Huang (Reference Huang, Bennett, Hracs and Storoshenko2018) makes is that bare NPs with a non-referential interpretation are only possible to the right of the DirP, as in (33a). Nominals with a larger structure, encompassing demonstrative, numeral, classifier projections, etc. are ungrammatical in that position and must, instead, precede the DirP, as seen in (33c).

  1. (34) (based on Huang Reference Huang, Bennett, Hracs and Storoshenko2018: 204)

The examples in (35) demonstrate that the bare post-DirP NP can only take narrow scope (35a) and has a number neutral reading (35b).Footnote 53

These properties could, in principle, be explained under the assumption that the bare post-directional nominal undergoes noun incorporation with V. However, as Huang (Reference Huang, Bennett, Hracs and Storoshenko2018) also shows, in these contexts we are rather dealing with the process of pseudo-incorporation (in Massam's Reference Massam2001 terms). This conclusion is supported by two main diagnostics: i) bare post-directional nominals are phrase-level NPs and can be modified, as in (36); ii) Mandarin Chinese presents contexts of true head level incorporation, where N0 left-adjoins to V and constructs a complex predicate, as in (37):

Huang's (Reference Huang, Bennett, Hracs and Storoshenko2018) proposal is that bare post-directional nominals as in (33a) and (36) undergo pseudo-incorporation with V. Then V undergoes raising to a position above the directional phrase. More complex nominals (possibly DPs) as in (33c), on the other hand, contain a [uCase] feature, cannot compose directly with V and thus must raise to a position where they can get their [uCase] valued (see (34)). But if DPs such as those in (33c), that cannot take the -ba marker, have a [uCase] feature and must scramble to a position where their [uCase] can be valued, how exactly are the ba DPs to be explained? One could entertain the hypothesis that non-ba-marked DPs such as in (33c), even though escaping incorporation with V, do not have a [uCase] feature and stay unlicensed. But then the questions are: i) why do they need to raise above directional adverbials? ii) why can non-ba nominals raise even further and show up even in a preverbal position, as we see in (31c)? In examples such as (33c), in order to capture the position of DPs as preceding DirPs, following the structure in (34), it must be the case that V raises to v. The DP can have its Case feature valued in situ, in the specifier of VP. But, then, in order to capture the preverbal placement of the non-ba marked DPs in (31c), it must be the case that such objects raise even higher, above V.Footnote 54 This implies that a separate operation is needed for the ba objects, such as those in (31a–b) and (31d). Note that the ba marker is not optional in most contexts, such as with animate DPs, pronouns, etc. One way to interpret examples like (31c) is that they do not signal ba-optionality. Instead, we are dealing with [uC] objects which must scramble to a v 0 preceding position either as a result of an EPP feature on v 0 (objects showing up bare) or a result of a different operation (the ba-ones).

I propose that this second operation is connected with a feature that is present in the composition of ba objects. Similarly to what we have seen in the other oblique DOM languages I have discussed, one instantiation of this additional specification is a δ-related ([person]) feature, which requires additional valuation by a discourse-related functional head, namely the α (Sentience) related projection, in vP domain.Footnote 55 This is illustrated in (38). This type of reasoning captures repeated remarks made in the literature with respect to ba objects being connected to affectedness, prominence, as well as their insensitivity to specificity in some contexts (Sybesma Reference Sybesma1999, Sun Reference Sun2018 for detailed discussion). As we have also seen for Romanian, Spanish (and Gujarati), oblique DOM is not a marker of specificity. It results, instead, from a licensing operation needed to value a [person] feature or other discourse specifications on complex nominals, beyond Case. It also captures the observation that ba objects are not to be understood in terms of a scrambling operation to the left periphery, for reasons of topicalization. As discussed in the literature and as confirmed by native speakers, dislocated topics are possible without ba in Mandarin Chinese.Footnote 56

Of course, much more needs to be said about the ba marker in order to derive its non-trivial interactions with telicity, transitivity, genericity, etc.; many of its properties are also seen in the other languages examined in this article, suggesting a common core. Here, I was mainly interested in showing that this type of DOM is an operation beyond [uCase] and that the split (pseudo-)incorporation vs. [uCase] licensing is not enough.

  1. (38)

6. Concluding remarks

In this article I have examined some instances of (animacy-based) oblique DOM against two main theoretical backgrounds: i) oblique DOM as a nominal licensing strategy on objects specified with a structural Case feature which needs valuation in syntax (López Reference López2012; Ormazabal and Romero Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013a, Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013b; a.o.); and ii) oblique DOM as connected with information structure (topic) specifications, beyond Case (Leonetti Reference Leonetti, Heusinger and Kaiser2003, Reference Leonetti2008; Iemmolo Reference Iemmolo2010; Dalrymple and Nikolaeva Reference Dalrymple and Nikolaeva2011; Belletti Reference Belletti, Petrosino, Pietro and van der Hulst2018). I have shown that in some languages, such as Romanian, Gujarati and Mandarin Chinese nominals show a more complex behaviour than what the split licensed/unlicensed would predict. In Romanian there are DPs (definites and certain types of indefinites) which need [uCase] licensing, independently DOM. In Gujarati, oblique DOM co-occurs with object agreement, which results from an independent licensing operation. And in Mandarin Chinese, DOM-ed objects are spelled out in a higher position than other scrambled DPs which give equal indication of [uCase] licensing.

I have also demonstrated that reducing oblique DOM to a morphological operation is not an adequate explanation, as these objects are syntactically distinct from other (accusative) Case licensed DPs, either positionally (Mandarin Chinese) or with respect to co-occurrence syntactic restrictions DOM gives rise to (Romanian, Spanish). These observations appear to provide support to the second line of analysis. However, in none of languages examined here is oblique DOM similar to (left dislocated) topics; for example, it also appears under focus or on elements which are not given. Building on hypotheses of DOM as an additional licenser on the same nominal (following Jaeggli Reference Jaeggli1982), I have proposed instead that the differential marker signals an additional licensing operation beyond [uCase] on nominals with complex structure. For example, animates that are relevant in the discourse are linked to a δ-related ([person]) feature which is valued by a δ-related functional projection in the mid verbal domain (Pancheva and Zubizaretta Reference Pancheva and Zubizarreta2018), below the EA.

This account makes various predictions and raises several questions. As the relevant licensing operation is independent but can co-occur with [uCase] licensing mechanisms, oblique DOM contexts discussed here are similar to case stacking configurations. This seems to be borne out in Romanian (as well as across Romance), where pronouns have independent accusative case morphology, but they additionally require the DOM preposition, and accusative clitic doubling. Similarly, Sun (Reference Sun2018) discusses stacking configurations with DOM and pronominals across Chinese varieties.

The observation that the difference between differentially marked nominals and unmarked nominals is not just the split structural Case vs. (pseudo-) incorporation/unlicensed has been discussed for other families of languages, matching the picture presented here. For example, various works have shown that across Altaic, (certain types of) unmarked nominals give evidence of the presence of structural [uCase], similarly to differentially marked objects (Taylan Reference Taylan, Slobin and Zimmer1986, Kamali Reference Kamali and Meinunger2015, Öztürk Reference Öztürk2005).

Two questions that need further investigation are the precise status of the δ–related ([person]) feature and restrictions to objects. If oblique marking were simply a reflex of highly complex nominal structure, we would expect to see it on subjects/EAs too (signalling additional licensing in the TP domain for features beyond [uCase]). While it is indeed true that DOM can appear with certain subjects across Romance, Indo-Aryan or Mandarin Chinese, it is impossible with various types of agents. A preliminary answer to this problem could start from the observation that T is a different type of licenser than v 0, in that it can contain the relevant type of δ–related feature that is more easily transmitted from C (Miyagawa Reference Miyagawa2017), such that recourse to an additional licenser is not needed. A better understanding of the nature of subjects where the differential marker is permitted is thus needed. Another possibility is that subject licensing interacts with information-structural notions in more restricted ways, permitting only certain types of topics, which might clash with the specifications in the δ-layer, so that the latter must remain unlicensed. Another big picture question relates, of course, to the notion of nominal licensing itself, its typology and its precise nature.

Footnotes

I would like to thank Michael Barrie, Virginia Hill, András Bárány, Mark Baker, Sampada Deshpande, the audience at the Nominals at the interfaces conference (Sogang University, Seoul, November 1-4 2018), as well as three anonymous reviewers for their very insightful feedback and suggestions. A special thank you also goes to the native speaker consultants for their help with the data. Parts of this work have been supported by a grant from the University of Modena and Reggio Emilia. All errors are my own.

1 Abbreviations: abs: absolutive; acc: accusative; asp: aspect; aug: augmented; aux: auxiliary; cl: clitic; cls: classifier; dat: dative; desid: desiderative; DO: direct object; DOM/dom: differential object marking; EA: external argument; ECM: exceptional case marking; EPP: extended projection principle; erg: ergative; f: feminine; IO: indirect object; kp: Case Projection; lk: linker; loc: locative; m: masculine; neg: negation; n: neuter; pfv: perfective; pl: plural; refl: reflexive; pst: past; SC: small clause; sg: singular; 1/2/3: person.

2 As is custom, the capital is used on Case in order to indicate the abstract licensing condition on the nominal, irrespective of its morphological realization.

3 For several native speakers the sentence in (i) requires DOM, even though the most accessible reading of nominals with modal adjectives like necessary is the non-specific one. Here we see a different behaviour from that of animate indefinites in examples such as (1c) above, where oblique DOM appears to be possible only on indefinite animates with specific readings. Other contexts where DOM overrides specificity (and also extends to inanimates) come from telicity inducing predicates (Torrego Reference Torrego1998, García García Reference García García, Kaiser and Leonetti2007, Rodríguez-Mondoñedo Reference Rodríguez-Mondoñedo2007). As we will see in the other languages discussed in this article, oblique DOM is, in fact, not a specificity mechanism, contrary to traditional assumptions.

4 As also shown later, DOM gives rise to non-trivial co-occurrence restrictions cross-linguistically.

5 Remember that Spanish indirect objects (IOs) are introduced by the preposition a, which is homophonous with DOM. Moreover, Spanish IOs can be doubled using the dative form of the clitic.

6 The co-occurrence restriction is not due to haplology caused by identical shape of DOM and DAT. If the DAT clitic is removed, the structure is well formed (i); so is a context with just the DAT clitic (ii).

7 Ormazabal and Romero's observations seem to be confirmed by other contexts. For example, animate definites lacking DOM appear to allow only a non-specific interpretation. Compare the example in (i) with the DOM animate definite in (1). Some speakers also accept DOM-less definites in Quine-contexts such as (ii); but note that there are speakers who might use DOM in both (i) and (ii), irrespectively of specificity.

8 Incorporation is a vast phenomenon in human language grammar, with many syntactic (e.g., head level merge, strict adjacency to V, etc.) and semantic correlates (non-referential interpretations, number-neutral readings, etc.), which cannot always be easily unified (Farkas and de Swart Reference Farkas and de Swart2003). So is the process of pseudo-incorporation (Massam Reference Massam2001, Dayal Reference Dayal2011, Borik and Gehrke Reference Borik and Gehrke2015). In this article, I cannot exhaustively discuss these two vast phenomena (see section 5 for some further observations). Instead, what I am interested in showing is that, at least in some languages, (oblique) DOM as well as types of unmarked objects have properties (such as positional flexibility, obligatory raising, syntactic co-occurrence effects, etc.) which cannot be explained under (pseudo-)incorporation. The question is how to set aside oblique DOM from those objects which are equally not subject to what might qualify as (pseudo-) incorporation, which do not get inherent/lexical Case either and which similarly appear to require licensing in syntax.

9 Blocking of bare nominals cannot be (entirely) due to a putative subject nature of the nominal inside SCs. Although Spanish subjects normally show overt (in)definiteness, there are many contexts in which they can show up bare. This contrasts with SCs where bare nominals are ungrammatical across the board.

10 Of course, as also noticed by López (Reference López2012), nominals can contain a case feature introduced even lower in the structure. However, this is not uninterpretable Case (and might be abbreviated just as Case).

11 As seen in the following examples:

12 As seen, for example, in the locative in fn. 16.

13 Clitic doubling is independent of oblique DOM (see especially Cornilescu Reference Cornilescu2000) and we do not discuss it in detail in this article. Besides contexts where clitic doubling is obligatory for many speakers, as in (12d), there are several DOM configurations where clitic doubling is, in fact, not possible, such as (12a–b).

14 Note that these two categories cannot be analyzed in terms of specificity; they are thus further confirmation that DOM is not a specificity-inducing mechanism. See also fn. 3.

15 The augmented demonstrative contains the so-called ‘augment’ -a.

16 We know that the locative preposition pe is not a lexical marker in (12e), as the object is also clitic doubled, using the accusative form of the clitic. Pe as a locative preposition or as a marker indicating lexical selection by various predicates never allows clitic doubling and is not sensitive to animacy:

17 Lack of DOM with bare plurals is attributed to the reduced structure of these classes, which can only project up to NumP. Remember that oblique DOM signals a larger size of the nominal, normally a KP.

18 Differential marking is possible with possessive have, but only under a stage level interpretation; in that case, the nominal will only be interpreted as specific, and in Romanian will require clitic doubling.

19 Bare nouns are possible only under the attributive construal of the adjective, which is irrelevant here.

20 If we wanted to assume that SCs only signal lack of (pseudo-)incorporation and not necessarily nominal licensing (hypothesizing that the nominals must escape incorporation but can stay unlicensed), it is not clear how to explain obligatory presence of DOM in some SCs, in a non stipulative way. Moreover, as we will see later in the article, the assumption that (all types of) unmarked (and non-incorporating) objects stay unlicensed (Ormazabal and Romero Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013 a, Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013 b; Kalin Reference Kalin2018) is problematic for the other two languages discussed in this article, namely Gujarati and Mandarin Chinese.

21 As we have seen in (6), SCs do not permit pseudo-incorporation because the object is never found in a complement position to V.

22 Although it interacts with it, blocking it in some contexts (see especially Hill and Mardale Reference Hill and Mardale2021).

23 Binding from the marked object into IO might go through for some speakers, if the former is also clitic-doubled (with the accusative clitic). See also Hill and Mardale (Reference Hill and Mardale2021) for similar examples.

24 Another test used by López (Reference López2012), namely coordination between marked and unmarked objects, is not a reliable diagnostic in Romanian, due to the numerous confounds in the data.

25 Restricting our attention to the facts under discussion. Of course, there might be other differences, which are either orthogonal to the point made here or simply unproblematic under the present analysis.

26 Another problem is that the Choice Function mechanim used by López (Reference López2012) to explain the fact that DOM can take scope outside islands is independently needed for Romanian unmarked indefinites too. The latter can easily take scope outside islands; thus, it appears that the presence of a Choice Function is not what sets DOM aside in the language.

27 Remember from example (4) that DOM gives rise to co-occurrence restrictions in Spanish too. Ormazabal and Romero (Reference Ormazabal and Romero2007, Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013a, Reference Ormazabal and Romero2013b) derive these effects in the syntax, under the broader class of Person Case Constraint (PCC) effects.

28 The alternation in the dative form of the (reflexive) clitic (îşi/şi) is purely phonological.

29 Thus, the sentence cannot mean that the sender sent as his aid somebody who is found in a possessive relation with the sender. A possessor interpretation of the dative reflexive clitic is still possible, but not into DOM. For example, the sentence can mean that he has sent somebody to/as his own aid.

30 Also encoding specifications related to Kuno and Kaburaki's (Reference Kuno and Kaburaki1977: 3) notion of Empathy: ‘Empathy is the speaker's identification (which may vary in degrees) with a person/thing that participates in the event or state that he describes in a sentence.’

31 As a nominal may contain several features that need valuation, one should not conclude that such operations are not restricted. In the system explored here, a domain (VoiceP, TP, CP, etc.) has only one main licenser. As canonically assumed in the literature, an additional licenser can be made available, but the operation is not unrestricted; it is generally more like last resort. This implies that for objects that do not raise, there can only be two licensing operations inside VoiceP. A third licensing operation can apply when the object raises above this domain. It is difficult to find yet other licensers – the subject might also contain complex sets of features that might need the activation of an additional licenser beyond T. If we examine tonic pronoun direct objects in Romance, we indeed notice three co-occurring layers of accusative case, each resulting from an independent licensing operation – at v (accusative inflection), at α (resulting in DOM), and above Voice (accusative clitics). See also the brief remarks in the conclusions.

32 This, however, raises the question of whether speech-act functional projections, which are generally a hallmark of CP, can be found in the vP. One promising hypothesis, suggested by an anonymous reviewer, is that they are realized structurally adjacent to phasal projections (e.g., vPs, CPs, and DPs).

33 Assuming that the δ-[person] Agree (licensing) operation can access goals at a distance, as it does not have the locality restriction imposed by López (Reference López2012) on the α head.

34 The question is how to extend the analysis to inanimates, as in (12c) and (12d). This is a complex issue and I cannot fully solve it in the space available here. However, a careful examination of those contexts reveals categories containing double definiteness, D-linking, other person or discourse-related features beyond [uCase] in D0 (see also Cornilescu Reference Cornilescu2000, or Irimia Reference Irimia, Bárány and Kalin2020), for which an additional licenser is needed. The relevant configurations thus reduce to the presence of a feature which needs licensing beyond [uCase].

35 Kayne/Jaeggli's Generalization (Jaeggli Reference Jaeggli1982: 20): ‘An object NP may be doubled by a clitic only if the NP is preceded by a preposition.’

36 A recent last-resort account for DOM has been provided by Kalin (Reference Kalin2018), where the licensing competition is mainly triggered by subject licensing. The languages discussed here are harder to accommodate under Kalin's (Reference Kalin2018) system; an adaptation of Kayne/Jaeggli's Generalization gives better results, while also explaining other independent facts about nominals and structural Case. For example, in the next section we can see that overt object agreement (a differential marking strategy) in Gujarati is sensitive to competition with subject licensing. However, oblique DOM is an independent mechanism. Similar problems are clear in Mandarin Chinese. Moreover, in the languages discussed here, oblique DOM is not a matter of licensing competition with the subject – it can, in fact, be seen in contexts where subjects stay unlicensed, in passives that lack an overt or implicit external argument projected in the syntax, even on subjects themselves, in certain types of configurations. We also see that an obligatory licensing need is not what sets oblique DOM aside from unmarked nominals. The latter do undergo licensing too. Also, there are various contexts where oblique DOM obtains in the absence of the expected licensers, indicating that it should not always be equated with an obligatory licensing operation.

37 See also Belletti (Reference Belletti, Petrosino, Pietro and van der Hulst2018: 452) with respect to overtly dislocated a-marked objects in Italian, which are prohibited in focal positions. These objects are equated with a-Topics that ‘express some psychological affectedness/involvement of the object in the action/feeling/overall event expressed by the verb.’

38 In (i) we see a topicalized augmented demonstrative which is unmarked (it only needs the accusative resumptive clitic). In (12c), on the other hand, we have seen the same augmented form of the demonstrative, in situ, with obligatory dom.

39 Data of this type also compelled López (Reference López2012) to reject an analysis of DOM in terms of topical objects. The aboutness topic/E-topic is also difficult to extend to all the oblique DOM languages discussed here.

40 Of course, much more needs to be said about these co-occurrence restrictions, the precise morpho-syntactic status of the DOM preposition, or the timing of insertion and interaction with other functional heads. We leave these important facts aside here, for lack of space.

41 Thus, this Gujarati variety is different from Hindi (see Dayal Reference Dayal2011), where agreement obtains even with pseudo-incorporated objects.

42 Gujarati does not have overt definiteness morphology.

43 Under referential readings, object agreement is not optional in the language (when the subject is ergative).

44 In the example below I illustrate a lexical dative. The verb can only show up with neuter inflection.

45 ‘AGREE is the process by which a head X0 with unvalued uninterpretable features (the Probe) identifies the closest Y0/YP in its c-command domain with the relevant set of visible matching (i.e. nondistinct) interpretable features (the Goal), and uses the interpretable features of Y0/YP to value its uninterpretable features.’ (Bhatt Reference Bhatt2005: 758).

46 Structural Condition on Person Agreement (SCOPA): ‘A category F can bear the features +1 or +2 if and only if a projection of F merges with a phrase that has that feature and F is taken as the label of the resulting phrase.’ (Baker Reference Baker2011: 878)

47 In (i) we see Basque object agreement in person with absolutives; in (ii) DOM agreement in person.

48 Basque oblique DOM behaves like structural accusatives/absolutives under various syntactic diagnostics (see Odria Reference Odria2017, Reference Odria2019 for detailed discussion), indicating that it does not have oblique syntax.

49 The behaviour of such nominals might indicate a DP status. See especially Wu and Bodomo (Reference Wu and Bodomo2009) for the DP hypothesis in Mandarin and Cantonese. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for discussion and clarification on this matter.

50 In classical Chinese, ba functioned as a verb meaning ‘hold, take’. In modern formal studies it has been associated with a preposition, a case marker, or (more rarely) a verb (see Yang and van Bergen Reference Yang and van Bergen2007).

51 Note that not all speakers accept nominals in preverbal position without ba.

52 van Bergen (Reference van Bergen2006) and Yang and van Bergen (Reference Yang and van Bergen2007) propose to add another constraint to the scales, one related to scrambling. We show below, however, that there are various types of A scrambling to various positions within VoiceP (or below TP) in Mandarin Chinese. This implies that yet another constraint will have to be added to the scales to isolate the ba-marked DPs from other scrambled DPs. But, as all these constraints are different in nature, it is not obvious how ba will be derived in a non stipulative way.

53 Huang (Reference Huang, Bennett, Hracs and Storoshenko2018) also shows that such NPs cannot antecede a discourse anaphor in the singular.

54 It can be, preliminarily, assumed that in these instances scrambling is triggered by an Extended Projection Principle (EPP) feature on v 0, which targets just the nominals with [uC]. However, these examples need further attention.

55 Sun (Reference Sun2018) demonstrates that ba objects must be located below the EA (thus, below Voice in (38)), but higher than v 0. Sun (Reference Sun2018) also presents evidence for raising for ba objects, instead of base generation.

56 As in the following example, which involves a left dislocated topic:

References

Adger, David, and Harbour, Daniel. 2007. Syntax and syncretisms of the Person Case Constraint. Syntax 10(1): 237. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9612.2007.00095.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aissen, Judith. 2003. Differential object marking: Iconicity vs. economy. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 21(3): 435483.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baker, Mark. 1988. Incorporation. A theory of grammatical function changing. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Baker, Mark. 2011. When agreement is for number and gender but not person. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 29(4): 875915.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bárány, András. 2017. Person, case and agreement. The morpho-syntax of inverse agreement and global case splits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bárány, András. 2018. DOM and dative case. Glossa 3(1)97: 140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Belletti, Adriana. 2004. Aspects of the low IP area. In The structure of CP and IP, ed. Rizzi, Luigi, 1651. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Belletti, Adriana. 2018. Objects and subjects in the left periphery: The case of a-Topics. In From sounds to structures. Beyond the veil of Maya, ed. Petrosino, Roberto, Pietro, Cerrone, and van der Hulst, Harry, 445466. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Bergen, Geertjie. 2006. To ba or not to ba: Differential object marking in Chinese Master's thesis, Radboud University Njemegen.Google Scholar
Bhatt, Rajesh. 2005. Long distance agreement in Hindi Urdu. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 23(4): 757807. < https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-004-4136-0>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bleam, Tonia. 2005. The role of semantic type in differential object marking. Belgian Journal of Linguistics 19(1): 327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bittner, Maria, and Hale, Kenneth. 1996. The structural determination of case and agreement. Linguistic Inquiry 27(1): 168.Google Scholar
Borik, Olga, and Gehrke, Berit, eds. 2015. The syntax and semantics of pseudo-incorporation. Leiden: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bossong, Georg. 1991. Differential Object Marking in Romance and beyond. In New Analyses in Romance Linguistics: Selected Papers from the XVIII Linguistic Symposium on Romance Languages, ed. Wanner, Dieter, and Kibbee, Douglas A., 143170, Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bossong, Georg. 1998. Le marquage différentiel de l'objet dans les langues d'Europe. In Actance et valence dans les langues de l'Europe, ed. Feuillet, Jack, 259294. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cardona, George. 1965. A Gujarati reference grammar. Philadelphia: The University of Pennsylvania Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, Noam. 1995. The minimalist program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Comrie, Bernard. 1984. Reflections on verb agreement in Hindi and related languages. Linguistics 22(6): 857864.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Comrie, Bernard. 1989. Language universals and linguistic typology. 2nd ed. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Cornilescu, Alexandra. 2000. On the interpretation of the prepositional accusative in Romanian. Bucharest Working Papers in Linguistics 2(1): 91110.Google Scholar
Danon, Gabi. 2006. Caseless nominals and the projection of DP. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 24(4): 9771008. <https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-006-9005-6>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dalrymple, Mary, and Nikolaeva, Irina. 2011. Objects and information structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dayal, Veneeta. 2011. Hindi pseudo-incorporation. Natural language and linguistic Theory 29(1): 123167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dobrovie-Sorin, Carmen. 1990. Clitic doubling, wh-movement and quantification. Linguistic Inquiry 21(3): 351397. <https://www.jstor.org/stable/4178681>Google Scholar
Dobrovie-Sorin, Carmen. 1994. The syntax of Romanian. Comparative studies in Romance. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farkas, Donka, and de Swart, Henriëtte. 2003. The semantics of incorporation. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Fernández, Beatriz, and Rezac, Milan. 2016. Differential object marking in Basque varieties. In Microparameters in the grammar of Basque, ed. Fernández, Beatriz and de Urbina, Jon Ortiz, 93138. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
García García, Marco. 2007. Differential object marking with inanimate objects. In Proceedings of the Workshop ‘Definiteness, specificity and animacy in Ibero Romance languages’. Arbetspapier 122, ed. Kaiser, Georg A. and Leonetti, Manuel, 6384. Universität Konstanz: Fachbereich Sprachwissenschaft.Google Scholar
Ghomeshi, Jila. 2008. Markedness and bare nouns in Persian. In Aspects of Iranian linguistics, ed. Karimi, Simin, Samiian, Vida, and Stilo, Donald, 85111. Newcastle upon Tyne, UK: Cambridge Scholars Press.Google Scholar
Giusti, Giuliana. 1993. La sintassi dei determinanti. Unipress: Padua.Google Scholar
Givón, Talmy. 1984. Direct objects and dative shifting: Semantic and pragmatic case. In Objects. Towards a theory of grammatical relations, ed. Plank, Frank, 151183. London: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Grosz, Patrick, and Patel-Grosz, Pritty. 2014. Agreement and verb types in Kutchi Gujarati. In The lexicon-syntax interface. Perspectives from South Asian languages, ed. Chandra, Pritha, and Shrishti, Richa, 217243. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halle, Morris, and Marantz, Alec. 1993. Distributed morphology and the pieces of inflection. In The view from Building 20, ed. Hale, Ken and Kayser, Samuel Jay, 111176. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Harley, Heidi, and Ritter, Elisabeth. 2002. Person and number in pronouns. A feature geometric approach. Language 78(3): 482526. <doi: 10.1353/lan.2002.0158>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haspelmath, Martin. 2008. Object marking, definiteness and animacy. Handout available at: <https://www.eva.mpg.de/lingua/conference/08_springschool/pdf/course_materials/Haspelmath_Objects.pdf>>Google Scholar
Hill, Virginia, and Mardale, Alexandru. 2021. The diachrony of differential object marking in Romanian. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huang, Hsin-Lun. 2018. Revisiting pseudo-incorporation: Post-verbal non-referential bare NPs in Mandarin. In Proceedings of the 35th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed. Bennett, Wm. G., Hracs, Lindsay, and Storoshenko, Dennis Ryan, 203213. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Proceedings Project.Google Scholar
Huang, C.-T. James, Li, Audrey, and Li, Yafei. 2009. The syntax of Chinese. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iemmolo, Giorgo. 2010. Topicality and DOM: Evidence from Romance and beyond. Studies in Language 34(2): 239272.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ihsane, Tabea. 2008. The layered DP. Form and meaning of French indefinites. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ihsane, Tabea, and Puskás, Genoveva. 2001. Specific is not definite. Generative Grammar in Geneva 2: 3954.Google Scholar
Irimia, Monica Alexandrina. 2020. Types of structural objects. Some remarks on differential object marking in Romanian. In Case, agreement and their interactions. New perspectives on differential argument marking, ed. Bárány, András and Kalin, Laura, 77126. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jayaseelan, K. A. 2001. IP-internal topic and focus phrases. Studia Linguistica 55(1): 3975. <https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9582.00074>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jaeggli, Osvaldo. 1982. Topics in Romance syntax. Dordrecht: Foris.Google Scholar
Joshi, Kinjal. 2020. Agreememt and information structure in Surati Gujarati. In Empirical issues in syntax and semantics 13 (EISS 13), ed. Pinon, Christopher and Roussarie, Laurent, 124. Paris: CSSP.Google Scholar
Kalin, Laura. 2018. Licensing and differential object marking: the view from Neo-Aramaic. Syntax 21(2): 112159.<https://doi.org/10.1111/synt.12153>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kamali, Beste. 2015. Caseless direct objects in Turkish revisited. In Byproducts and side effects: Nebenprodukte und Nebeneffekte (ZAS Papers in Linguistics 58), ed. Meinunger, André, 107123.Google Scholar
Keine, Stefan. 2010. Case and agreement from fringe to core: A minimalist approach. Berlin: de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keine, Stefan, and Müller, Gereon. 2008. Differential argument encoding by impoverishment. In Scales, ed. Richards, Marc and Malchukov, Andrej L., 83136, Linguistische Arbeits Berichte volume 86, Universität Leipzig.Google Scholar
Kornfilt, Jaklin. 2003. Scrambling, subscrambling and case in Turkish. In Word order and scrambling, ed. Karimi, Simin, 127155. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Kuno, Susumo, and Kaburaki, Etsuko. 1977. Empathy and syntax. Linguistic Inquiry 8(4): 627672.Google Scholar
Kuo, Pei-Jung. 2010. Transitivity and the ba construction. Taiwan Journal of Linguistics 8(1): 95128.Google Scholar
Laca, Brenda. 2006. El objeto direto. La marcación prepositional. In Sintaxis historica de la lengua española. Primera parte. La frase verbal. Volumen I, ed. Company Company, Concepción, 423475. México: Universidad Nacional Autonóma de México/Fondo de cultura económica.Google Scholar
Legate, Julie A. 2014. Voice and v. Lessons from Acehnese. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leonetti, Manuel. 2003. Specificity and object marking: The case of Spanish a. In Proceedings of the workshop Semantic and syntactic aspects of specificity in Romance languages. Arbeitspapier 113, ed. Heusinger, Klaus von, and Kaiser, Georg A., 6799. Konstanz: Fachbereich Sprachwissenschaft.Google Scholar
Leonetti, Manuel. 2008. Specificity in clitic doubling and in differential object marking. Probus 20(1): 3366. <https://doi.org/10.1515/PROBUS.2008.002>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levin, Ted. 2015. Licensing without Case. Doctoral dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Google Scholar
Li, Y. Audrey. 1990. Order and constituency in Mandarin Chinese. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Li, Y. Audrey. 2006. Chinese ba. In The Blackwell companion to syntax, ed. Everaert, Martin and van Riemsdijk, Henk, vol. 1, 374468. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Liu, Feng-Shi. 1997. An aspectual analysis of ba. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 6 (1): 5199. <https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1008287920948>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
López, Luis. 2012. Indefinite objects: scrambling, choice functions and differential marking. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Magier, David. 1983. Topics in the grammar of Marwari. Doctoral Dissertation, University of California, Berkeley.Google Scholar
Mahajan, Anoup Kumar. 1989. Agreement and agreement phrases. In Functional heads and clause structure, ed. Laka, Itziar, and Mahajan, Anoup Kumar, MIT Working Papers in Linguistics, No. 10, 217252. Cambridge, MA: MITWPL.Google Scholar
Massam, Diane. 2001. Pseudo noun incorporation in Niuean. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory. 19(1): 153197. <https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1006465130442>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mistry, P. J. 1976. Subject in Gujarati: An examination of verb agreement phenomenon. In The notion of subject in South Asian languages, ed. Verma, M., 240268. Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin.Google Scholar
Mistry, P. J. 1997. Objecthood and specificity in Gujarati. In The life of language, ed. Hill, Jane H., Mistry, P. J., and Campbell, Lyle, 425442. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Mistry, P. J. 2004. Subjecthood of non-nominatives in Gujarati. In Non-nominative subjects, ed. Bhaskararao, Peri, and Subbarao, Karumuri Venkata, vol. 2, 132. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Miyagawa, Shigeru. 2017. Agreement beyond phi. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mursell, Johannes. 2018. Object agreement in Swahili is topic agreement. Jezikoslovlje (3): 427455.Google Scholar
Niculescu, Alexandru. 1965. Obiectul direct prepozitional în limbile romanice [Prepositional direct objects in Romance languages]. In Individualitatea limbii române între limbile romanice [The particularity of Romanian among Romance languages], ed. Niculescu, Alexandru, 7799. Bucureşti: Editura Ştiintifică şi Enciclopedică.Google Scholar
Odria, Ane. 2017. Differential Object Marking and datives in Basque syntax. Doctoral dissertation, Universidad del País Vasco/Euskal Herriko Unibertsitatea.Google Scholar
Odria, Ane. 2019. DOM and datives in Basque: not as homogeneous as they might seem. Lingvisticae Investigationes 42(1): 730.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Onea, Edgar, and Mardale, Alexandru. 2020. From topic to object: Grammaticalization of differential object marking in Romanian. Canadian Journal of Linguistics 65(3): 350392.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ormazabal, Juan, and Romero, Javier. 2007. The object agreement constraints. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 25(2): 315347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ormazabal, Juan, and Romero, Javier. 2013a. Differential Object Marking, Case and Agreement. Borealis 2 (2): 221239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ormazabal, Juan, and Romero, Javier. 2013b. Non accusative objects. Catalan Journal of Linguistics 12(2): 155173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Öztürk, Balkız. 2005. Case, referentiality and phrase structure. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pancheva, Roumyana, and Zubizarreta, Maria Luisa. 2018. The Person Case Constraint. The syntactic encoding of perspective. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 36(4): 12911337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paul, Waltraud. 2015. New perspectives on Chinese syntax. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richards, Marc. 2008. Defective agree: Case Alternations, and the prominence of Person. In Linguistische Arbeits Berichte [ ](volume on Scales), ed. Richards, Marc and Malchukov, Andrej L., volume 86, 137161. Universität Leipzig.Google Scholar
Ritter, Elisabeth, and Wiltschko, Martina. 2019. Nominal speech act structure: Evidence from the structural deficiency of impersonal pronouns. Canadian Journal of Linguistics 64(4): 709729.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rivero, María Luisa. 1979. Referencia y especificidad. In Estudios de gramática generativa del español, ed. Rivero, María Luisa, 123161. Madrid: Catédra.Google Scholar
Rodríguez-Mondoñedo, Miguel. 2007. The syntax of objects. Agree and differential object marking. Doctoral dissertation, University of Connecticut.Google Scholar
Speas, Margaret, and Tenny, Carol. 2003. Configurational properties and point of view roles. In Asymmetry in grammar, ed. Di Sciullo, Anna Maria, vol. 1. Syntax and semantics, 315343. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sun, Yangyu. 2018. A cartographic analysis of the syntactic structure of Mandarin ba, MA Thesis, University of Padova.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sundaresan, Sandhya. 2018. Perspective is syntactic: evidence from anaphora. Glossa 3 (1)128: 140. <http://doi.org/10.5334/gjgl.81>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sybesma, R. P. E. 1999. The Mandarin VP. Dordrecht/Boston: Kluwer Academic Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylan, Eser E. 1986. Pronominal vs. zero representation anaphora in Turkish. In Studies in Turkish Linguistics, ed. Slobin, Dan I. and Zimmer, Karl, 209232. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tigău, Alina. 2011. Syntax and interpretation of the direct object in Romance and Germanic languages. Bucureşti: Editura Universităţii din București.Google Scholar
Torrego, Esther. 1998. The dependencies of objects. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tsai, Wei-Tien Dylan. 2015. A tale of two peripheries: Evidence from Chinese adverbials, light verbs and object fronting. In The cartography of Chinese syntax. The cartography of syntactic structures, ed. Tsai, Wei-Tien Dylan, vol. 11, 132. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Woolford, Ellen. 2006. Case agreement mismatches. In Agreement systems, ed. Boeckx, Cedric, 299316. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wu, Yicheng, and Bodomo, Adams. 2009. Classifiers ≠ determiners. Linguistic Inquiry 40(3): 487503.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wunderlich, Dieter. 2012. Case and agreement variation in Indo-Aryan. Ms.Google Scholar
Yang, Ning, and van Bergen, Geertjie. 2007. Scrambled objects and case marking in Mandarin Chinese. Lingua 117: 16171635.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zou, Ke. 1993. The syntax of the Chinese ba construction. Linguistics 31(7): 1536.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

(1)

Figure 1

(2)

Figure 2

(4)

Figure 3

Table 1: DOM in Spanish and Romanian (fragment)

Figure 4

(7)

Figure 5

(11) a.

Figure 6

(12) a.

Figure 7

(13)

Figure 8

(14)

Figure 9

a.

Figure 10

(17) a.

Figure 11

(18)

Figure 12

(19)

Figure 13

(21) a.

Figure 14

(23)

Figure 15

(24)

Figure 16

(25)

Figure 17

(26)

Figure 18

(27)

Figure 19

(28)

Figure 20

(29)

Figure 21

a.

Figure 22

(31) a.

Figure 23

(32)

Figure 24

(33)

Figure 25

(35)

Figure 26

(36)