Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-5nwft Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-13T08:34:44.568Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Law, Selfishness, and Signals: An Expansion of Posner’s Signaling Theory of Social Norms

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 July 2015

Get access

Extract

Eric Posner’s signaling theory of social norms holds that individuals adopt social norms in order to signal that they have a low discount rate (that is, they value the future more than the present), and are therefore reliable long-term cooperative partners. This paper radically expands Posner’s theory by incorporating internalization into his model (the sense that norms possess some sort of binding quality, an “ought to”). I do this by tethering Posner’s theory to an evolutionary model. I argue that internalization is an adaptive quality that enhances the individual’s ability to play Posner’s signaling game and was thus selected for. The idea that internalization is evolutionarily conditioned is not new; however, linking this to Posner’s theory of discount rate signals is, and doing so offers tremendous explanatory potential.

Part I identifies the limitations of Posner’s purely rational choice approach, argues for the necessity of including internalization, and then proposes a model that does so – what I call the Expanded Signaling Model of Norms (ESM). Part II examines the problems that arise when we embrace such a model. How this model answers some key criticisms plaguing sociobiology is also briefly explored. Part III then examines existing criticisms of Posner’s theory, demonstrating how the Expanded Signaling Model clearly resolves these issues. The paper concludes that incorporating internalization into Posner’s signaling model greatly broadens the explanatory reach of Posner’s theory, providing a measure of clarity and predictability regarding how and why norms are internalized – an important insight, as these beliefs form the normative underpinning to law.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Deepest thanks to Eric Posner at the University of Chicago for his helpful advice and suggestions. Thank you also to Neil Duxbury at the London School of Economics for reviewing an earlier draft of the present article.

1. Robert Ellickson writes, “ … the law-and-economics scholars believe that the law-and-society group is deficient in both sophistication and rigor, and the law-and-society scholars believe that the law-and-economics theorists are not only out of touch with reality but also short on humanity.” Ellickson, R.C., Order Without Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991) at 7.Google Scholar

2. McAdams, Richard H., “Signaling Discount Rates: Law, Norms, and Economic Methodology” (2001) 110 Yale L.J. 625 at 681CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3. As Posner says, “ … people bound by [norms] feel an emotional or psychological compulsion to obey the norms; norms have moral force.” Posner, Eric A., “Law, Economics, and Inefficient Norms” (1996) 144 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1697 at 1709CrossRefGoogle Scholar. The literature sometimes makes a distinction with regard to what I am here referring to broadly as internalization. For instance, Peter Huang speaks of emotions, specifically the moralistic kind. Huang, Peter H., “Reasons Within Passions: Affects and Attributions in Property Rights Bargaining” (2000) 79 Or. L. Rev. 435 Google Scholar; Huang, Peter & Wu, Ho-Mou, “More Order Without More Law: A Theory of Social Norms and Organizational Cultures” (1994) 10 J. L. Econ. & Org. 390 Google Scholar. McAdams cites the importance of the psychological need for esteem from others in his Esteem Theory of Norms. See McAdams, Richard H., “The Origin, Development, and Regulation of Norms” (1997) 96 Mich. L. Rev. 338 at 355-57CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4. “The rational-actor model has two basic underlying tenets. It assumes, first, that each individual pursues self-interested goals and, second, that each individual rationally chooses among various means for achieving those goals.” Ellickson, supra note 1 at 156.

5. Posner, Eric A., Law and Social Norms (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000).Google Scholar

6. Posner, supra note 5 at 24-25.

7. Ibid. at 19-21.

8. Ibid. at 8.

9. Ibid. at 46.

10. Indeed, internalization lies embedded at the heart of the natural law position, and it in fact explains the persistence of the embattled belief within jurisprudential circles.

11. Gintis, Herbert, “The Hitchhiker’s Guide to Altruism: Gene-culture Coevolution, and the Internalization of Norms” (2003) 220 J. Theor. Biol. 407 at 417CrossRefGoogle Scholar; see also Leary, Mark R., “Digging Deeper: The Fundamental Nature of ‘Self-Conscious’ Emotions” (2004) 15 Psych. Inquiry 129 at 129Google Scholar.

12. Leary, ibid. (“Since Darwin … all theories of emotion have assumed that the capacity for emotional experience evolved because it had adaptive value in helping organisms deal with recurrent challenges and opportunities in their physical and social environments.” [footnotes omitted]).

13. Scott, John, “Rational Choice Theory” in Browning, G., Halcli, A. & Webster, F., eds., Understanding Contemporary Society: Theories of the Present (London: Sage Publications, 2000) 126 at 133CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14. Scott, ibid.

15. For methodological individualism, see Elster, Jon, Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989) at 13 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Posner, supra note 5 at 39.

16. Posner, Eric A., “Signaling Model of Social Norms: Further Thoughts” (2002) 36 U. Rich. L. Rev. 465 at 467Google Scholar; see also Posner, supra note 5 at ch. 3.

17. Ibid.

18. Ibid.

19. This is not to deny that some norms may arise due to their inherent survival value, or as solutions to coordination dilemmas—but these norms are nevertheless also co-opted as signals. And their function as signals contributes greatly to their persistence. Not all norms may start off as signals, but all norms end that way. See infra notes 103-07 and accompanying text.

20. See Ellickson, Robert C., “The Evolution of Social Norms: A Perspective from the Legal Academy” in Hechter, Michael & Karl-Dieter, Opp, eds., Social Norms (New York: Russell Sage Foundation, 2005) 35 at 36Google Scholar (“The new norms scholars all hew to a rational-choice model of human behavior. This methodological individualism … supposes that each individual generally is both rational and self-interested.”).

21. Though, admittedly, what I go on to contend below might be accused of being no more than a slightly more nuanced foray into reductionism.

22. Of course, that the rational choice model is entirely safe even within the field of economics is debatable.

23. Elster, Jon, “Fairness and Norms” (2006) 73 Social Research 365 at 368Google Scholar.

24. For those unfamiliar with game theory, McAdams provides a concise summary: “ … two prisoners, A and B, are suspected of committing a crime together. If neither confesses, each knows they will each be convicted of a lesser offense and serve (say) three years in prison. The prosecutor then offers each the following deal, and each knows it is offered to the other: If you confess and the other does not, we will let you off with only one year in prison; if the other confesses and you do not, we will punish you with ten years in prison; if you both confess, you both will serve five years in prison. Confessing is the dominant strategy because it is the best strategy no matter what the other prisoner does. From A’s perspective, if B confesses, A is better off confessing and getting five years instead of ten; if B does not confess, A is better off confessing and getting one year instead of three. The reasoning is the same for B.” McAdams, supra note 2 at 628; see also Druzin, Bryan, “Law Without the State: The Theory of High Engagement and the Emergence of Spontaneous Legal Order within Commercial Systems” (2010) 41 Geo. J. Int’l L. 1 at 559, 599-605.Google Scholar

25. Axelrod, Robert & Hamilton, William D., “The Evolution of Cooperation” (1981) 211 Science 1390 at 1392CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

26. Mailath, George J. & Samuelson, Larry, Repeated Games and Reputations: Long-Run Relationships (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

27. Axelrod & Hamilton, supra note 25.

28. Of course the intensity of internalization is another matter: if the tip was fifteen thousand dollars, more people might be inclined to not tip. Murder is deeply internalized but most would still not murder someone for fifteen thousand dollars. For an interesting discussion of tipping practices in this respect, see Levmore, Saul, “Norms as Supplements” (2000) 86 Va. L. Rev. 1989 at 1997CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

29. This is the perennial problem for rational choice theorists of a second-order collective action problem—the irrationality of 3rd party norm enforcers willing to pay the cost of sanctioning with no clear individual benefit when they can simply free-ride on others enforcement. For second-order problems, see, e.g., Mahoney, Paul G. & Sanchirico, Chris. W., “Norms, Repeated Games, and the Role of Law” (2003) 91 Cal. L. Rev. 1281 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

30. Fehr, Ernst, Fischbacher, Urs & Gächter, Simon, “Strong Reciprocity, Human Cooperation, and the Enforcement of Social Norms” (2002) 13 Human Nature 1 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

31. Fehr, Ernst & Henrich, Joseph, “Is Strong Reciprocity a Maladaptation?” (2003) Cesifo Working Paper No. 859, 1 Google Scholar. For other studies along these lines, see, e.g., Fehr, E. & Gächter, S., “Altruistic Punishment in Humans” (2002) 415 Nature 137 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Fehr, E. & Gächter, S., “Reciprocity and Economics: the Economic Implications of Homo Reciprocans” (1998) 42 Eur. Econ. Rev. 845 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Henrich, J. et al., “In Search of Homo Economicus: Behavioral Experiments in 15 Small-Scale Societies” (2001) 91 Am. Econ. Rev. 73 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; McCabe, KA., Rassenti, J. & Smith, V.L., “Reciprocity, Trust, and Payoff Privacy in Extensive Form Bargaining” (1998) 24 Games Econ. Behav. 10 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. The term strong reciprocity has been used to refer to this form of deeply internalized behavior. Fehr et al., supra note 30; Gintis, H., “Strong Reciprocity and Human Sociality” (2000) 206 J. Theor. Biol. 169 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

32. See Thaler, Richard H., Quasi Rational Economics (New York: Russell Sage Foundation, 1991).Google Scholar

33. Bicchieri, Cristina, The Grammar of Society: The Nature and Dynamics of Social Norms (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006) at 102.Google Scholar

34. Guth, W. et al., “An Experimental Analysis of Ultimatum Bargaining” (1982) 3 J. Economic Behavior and Org. 367 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

35. This is perhaps a good example of where our emotions orchestrate our economic interactions far better than rational calculation. A player must deal with another player whose actions may be governed by emotion differently than a purely rational actor—in this instance, much more generously. Self-destructive acts of vengeance are another good example of this dynamic. Indeed, irrationality (read emotion) often accrues to one’s distinct benefit.

36. Sunstein, Cass R., “Social Norms and Social Roles” (1996) 96 Colum. L. Rev. 903 at 904CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

37. Bicchieri, supra note 33 at 104.

38. Sunstein, supra note 36 at 905.

39. Cameron, L., “Raising the Stakes in the Ultimatum Game: Experimental Evidence from Indonesia” (1999) 37 Economic Inquiry 47 at 47CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

40. Falk, Armin, Fehr, Ernst & Fischbacher, Urs, “Testing Theories of Fairness—Intentions Matter” (2008) 62 Games and Economic Behavior 287 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; see also Fehr, E. & Fischbacher, U., Third Party Punishment and Social Norms (Zurich, Switzerland: Inst. for Empirical Research in Economics, 2004)Google Scholar; Carpenter, J.P., Matthews, P.H. & Ong’ong’a, O., “Why Punish? Social Reciprocity and the Enforcement of Prosocial Norms” (2004) 14 J. Evolutionary Economics 407 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

41. Marwell, G. & Ames, R.E., “Economists Free Ride: Does Anyone Else?” (1981) 15 J. Public Economics 295 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; see also Kahan, Dan M., “Trust, Collective Action, and Law” (2001) 81 B.U.L. Rev. 333 at 33334 Google Scholar (citing studies that saw the emergence of cooperation beyond the levels predicted by just concerns for sanctions).

42. See Thaler, Richard H., The Winner’s Curse: Paradoxes and Anomalies of Economic Life (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996)Google Scholar, especially chapters two and three for a good review of these findings.

43. See, e.g., Korobkin, Russell B. & Ulen, Thomas S., “Law and Behavioral Science: Removing the Rationality Assumption from Law and Economics” (2000) 88 Cal. L. Rev. 1051 CrossRefGoogle Scholar (arguing for fundamental modifications to the assumption of rationality); Ostrom, Elinor, “A Behavioral Approach to the Rational Choice Theory of Collective Action,” Presidential Address Before the American Political Science Association (1997), in 92 Am. Pol. Sci. Rev. 1 (1998)Google Scholar (stating the need for a “second-generation” rational choice model).

44. Wendel, W. Bradley, “Mixed Signals: Rational-Choice Theories of Social Norms and the Pragmatics of Explanation” (2002) 77 Ind. L.J. 1 at 10Google Scholar.

45. Scott, supra note 13; see also Sunstein, supra note 36 at 909.

46. Ellickson, supra note 1 at 156, n.3. However, this failure is, perhaps, matched equally by those on the Law and Society side in their failure to adequately explain the nature of these preferences, simply adducing concepts like “norm of cooperation” to explain cooperation. See Wendel, supra note 44 at 6. Elster compares this approach to explaining the soporific effects of opium in terms of its “dormative principle.” Elster, supra note 13 at 186. Indeed, as Ellickson explains, “A key shortcoming of the law-and-society school has been its failure to develop a theory of the content of norms … sociologists and other law-and-society scholars have tended to treat observed norms as exogenous, rather than as dependent variables whose contents are to be explained.” Ellickson, supra note 1 at 149.

47. Scott, supra note 13 at 134; see also Cook, K.S. & Emerson, R.M., “Power, Equity and Commitment in Exchange Networks” (1978) 43 American Sociological Rev. 721 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

48. Duxbury, Neil, “Signaling and Social Norms” (2001) 21 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 719 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; see also, e.g., Rachlinsky, Jeffrey J., “The Limits of Social Norms” (2000) 74 Chicago-Kent L. Rev. 1537 Google Scholar; Scott, Robert E., “The Limits of Behavioural Theories of Law and Social Norms” (2000) 86 Va. L. Rev. 1603 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

49. Posner acknowledges that people do behave in this fashion. Posner, supra note 5 at 38, 43. Note that this dilemma applies equally to norm enforcement. Posner responds by stating that “rational choice theory can be used to explain some social phenomena but not other social phenomena.” Ibid.

50. Some norm scholars make a distinction between shame and guilt, pointing out that shame is related to compliance, while guilt brings up issues of voluntary conformity. See, e.g., ibid. at 43. For our purposes, however, both are expressions of internalization.

51. I am in good company: Cooter also asserts a norm only exists if it has been internalized. Cooter, Robert D., “Decentralized Law for a Complex Economy: The Structural Approach to Adjudicating the New Law Merchant” (1996) 144 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1643 at 166166 Google Scholar.

52. Posner, supra note 5 at 46.

53. Posner, supra note 16 at 477.

54. McAdams, supra note 2 at 679.

55. Posner, supra note 5 at 26.

56. Posner, supra note 16 at 472.

57. Posner, supra note 5 at 43.

58. Ibid. at 43-44.

59. Ibid. at 44.

60. Interestingly, Posner’s earlier work did not exhibit this rejection of all things normative: “ … even a complete game-theoretic account of cooperative behavior would miss some essential aspects of norms. We say about most norms that people bound by them feel an emotional or psychological compulsion to obey the norms; norms have moral force … Game theory does not explain these phenomena.” Posner, supra note 3 at 1709.

61. For a critique of Posner’s theory in this respect, see McAdams, supra note 2 at 678-87.

62. Besides Cooter, McAdams, and Elster are perhaps the two most prominent. See Elster, supra note 46; Elster, Jon, “Norms of Revenge” (1990) 100 Ethics 862 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; McAdams, supra note 3 at 338; see also Pettit, Philip, “Virtus Normativa: Rational Choice Perspectives” (1990) 100 Ethics 725 at 730CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

63. McAdams, supra note 3 at 338. Others also argue along these lines, see Bernheim, B.D., “A Theory of Conformity” (1994) 102 J. Pol. Economy 841 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Akerlof, George A., “Social Distance and Social Decisions” (1997) 65 Econometrica 1005 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

64. Bicchieri’s criticism of such an approach applies: “Yet to maintain that we conform to social norms because of the disapproval involved in violating them is of little help in explaining why norms are there, how they emerged, and why they persist.” Bicchieri, Cristina, “Norms of Cooperation” (1990) 100 Ethics 838 at 839CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

65. McAdams, supra note 2 at 687.

66. Cooter, Robert, “Do Good Laws Make Good Neighbors? An Economic Analysis of Internalized Norms” (2000) 86 Va. L. Rev. 1577 at 1601CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

67. Many rational choice theorists in fact employ evolutionary models that presuppose this kind of bounded rationality to explain norm emergence. See, e.g., Axelrod, Robert, The Complexity of Cooperation: Agent-Based Models of Competition and Collaboration (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1997)Google Scholar; Skyrms, Brian, Evolution of the Social Contract (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; H. Young, Peyton, Individual Strategy and Social Structure: An Evolutionary Theory of Institutions (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1998)Google Scholar. See also, e.g., Sunstein, Cass R., Behavioral Law & Economics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Korobkin & Ule, supra note 43.

68. Indeed, Frank sees the emotions as the progenitor of moral behavior rather than rational decisions. Frank, Robert H., Passions Within Reason: The Strategic Role of the Emotions (New York: W. W. Norton & Co., 1988) at 5156 Google Scholar.

69. “Individuals do not eat in response to a rational calculus of caloric need. Instead, a complex set of forces causes one to ‘feel hungry.’” Scott, Robert E., “The Limits of Behavioral Theories of Law and Social Norms” (2000) 86 Va. L. Rev. 1603 at 1606CrossRefGoogle Scholar (referencing Frank, supra note 68).

70. Robert Trivers famously presented a similar idea in his 1971 paper The Evolution of Reciprocal Altruism. Trivers argued that due to the difficulty involved in computing the complex cost-benefit ratios that underpin long-term reciprocity, human emotions evolved as a regulating mechanism. See Trivers, R.L., “The Evolution of Reciprocal Altruism” (1971) 46 Q. Rev. Biology 35 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. To facilitate this system of reciprocal altruism, “feelings and emotions—including guilt, fairness, moralistic aggression, gratitude, and sympathy—are part of the normal repertoire of human responses and are evoked in predictable situations.” Holcomb, Harmon & Bryon, Jason, “Sociobiology” (Stanford CA: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2005).Google ScholarPubMed

71. Posner, supra note 5 at 25.

72. See Gintis, supra note 11(arguing that the ability to internalize norms evolves as it enhances individual fitness in situations where social behavior has become too complex to be evaluated piecemeal through individual rational assessment).

73. McAdams, supra note 3 at 376; see also Franks, supra note 68 at 152-61; Ellickson, Robert, “Bringing Culture and Human Frailty to Rational Actors: A Critique of Classical Law and Economics” (1989) 65 Chicago-Kent L. Rev. 23 at 4546 Google Scholar.

74. Scott makes a similar point, though he is speaking about internalization in general: Scott, supra note 48 at 1621 (“There is long-term advantage in moral behavior. But in order for emotions, such as guilt, to work as self-enforcing commitments, satisfaction must be intrinsic in the act of compliance and not premised on the possibility that material gains may follow.”).

75. Trivers, supra note 70; Trivers, R.L., Social Evolution (San Francisco, CA: Benjamin/Cummings, 1985) at 38889 Google Scholar. See also Trivers, R.L., “Reciprocal Altruism: 30 Years Later” in Kappeler, P.K. & Schaik, C.P. Van, eds., Cooperation in Primates and Humans: Mechanisms and Evolution (Berlin: Springer, 2006) 67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

76. Nielsen, François, “Sociobiology and Sociology” (1994) 20 Ann’l Rev. Socio. 267 at 277CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

77. See Smith, J. Maynard & Price, G.R., “The Logic of Animal Conflict” (1973) 246 Nature 15 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Smith, J. Maynard, Evolution and the Theory of Games (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

78. Axelrod, Robert, The Evolution of Cooperation (New York: Basic Books) at 88105 Google ScholarPubMed; see also Axelrod & Hamilton, supra note 25.

79. See Hirshleifer, J., “On the Emotions as Guarantors of Threats and Promises” in Dupre, John, ed., The Latest on the Best: Essays on Evolution and Optimality (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1987) 307 Google Scholar; Hirshleifer, J., “The Affections and the Passions: Their Economic Logic” (1993) 5 Rationality Soc. 185 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hirshleifer, J., “Evolutionary Models in Economics and Law: Cooperation Versus Conflict Strategies” in Hirshleifer, J., ed., The Dark Side of the Force: Economic Foundations of Conflict Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001) 183 Google Scholar; see also Margolis, H., Selfishness, Altruism and Rationality: A Theory of Social Choice (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1982)Google Scholar; R. Frank, supra note 68; Sugden, Robert, The Economics of Rights, Co-Operation and Welfare (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986) at 14547 Google Scholar; Cooter, supra note 51 at 1662 (discussing the psychological underpinning that induces norm compliance).

80. See Plutchik, R., Emotion: A Psychoevolutionary Synthesis (New York: Harper & Row, 1980)Google Scholar (positing an evolutionary model of emotion in which primary emotions are distinguished from more complex emotions); see also Panskepp, J., “Toward a General Psychobiological Theory of Emotions” (1982) 5 Behavioral and Brain Sciences 407 Google Scholar.

81. See Elster, Jon, Strong Feelings: Emotion, Addiction, and Human Behavior (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2000) at 98 Google Scholar (citing emotions as supporting social norms).

82. See Mealey, L., “The Sociobiology of Sociopathy: An Integrated Evolutionary Model” in Baron-Cohen, Simon, ed., The Maladapted Mind: Classic Readings in Evolutionary Psychopathology (East Sussex, UK: Psychology Press, 1997) 133 at 170Google Scholar at n.2.

83. Posner gives an illuminating explanation of racist norms as discount rate signals. See Posner, supra note 5 at 133-43.

84. Ibid. at 112-19.

85. See infra notes 161-68 and accompanying text.

86. Asch, S.E., “Opinions and Social Pressure” (1955) 193 Scientific American 31 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Sherif, M., “An Experimental Approach to the Study of Attitudes” (1937) 1 Sociometry 90 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

87. Posner, supra note 5 at 46.

88. Ibid.

89. Buss, David M., Evolutionary Psychology: The New Science of the Mind (Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon, 2004) at 50.Google Scholar

90. See Frank, supra note 68 at 5-7.

91. Scott, supra note 48 at 1606 (“Salient emotional reactions-such as guilt, anger, or empathy-mark one as a ‘cooperator’ who is able to make credible commitments concerning her future actions.”).

92. A point adamantly made by Wendel in his critique of Posner, see Wendel, supra note 44 at 30 (“ … it matters critically whether the theory is radically at odds with one’s subjective experiences. In these contexts, we may have reason to reject the rational-choice model in favor of one that employs explanatory concepts that are congruent with those actually deployed by the deliberating individual.”).

93. Cooter, Robert, “The Normative Failure of Law” (1997) 82 Cornell L. Rev. 947 at 952Google Scholar; see, e.g., Grief, Avner, Milgrom, Paul & Weingast, Barry, “Coordination, Commitment, and Enforcement: The Case of the Merchant Guild” (1994) 102 J. Pol. Economy 745 at 76471 Google Scholar; Milgrom, Paul, North, Douglass, & Weingast, Barry, “The Role of Institutions in the Revival of Trade: The Law Merchant, Private Judges, and the Champagne Fairs” (1990) 2 Economy & Politics 1 at 614 Google Scholar.

94. Cooter being one notable exception. See Cooter, supra note 51 at 1690-94; Cooter, supra note 66; Cooter, supra note 93.

95. Baird, Douglas G., Gertner, Robert H., & Picker, Randal C., Game Theory and the Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994) at 125.Google Scholar

96. For example, animals certainly kill, but it is unclear if an animal can commit murder; we don’t have the moral language for this, as we don’t impose norms on animal behavior in the way we do for human conduct.

97. A bold assertion could be made here that follows from this line of reasoning: Morality does not exist outside the world of these discount signals. The arc of our moral universe is wholly constructed from this signaling game—morality is an emergent property. When one considers that approximately 4% of all males (sociopaths) do not experience moral sentiment at all, the onus would seem to rest with those claiming its objective validity—if they cannot meet this burden, one would have to conclude that it is not an objective truth but rather a subjective concoction. However, a Kantian universal moral truth is not necessarily denied here. One could equally make the case that evolution merely provides otherwise selfish organisms a degree of clarity in regards to certain moral truths where and when it confers an evolutionary advantage.

98. Sugden, Robert, “Spontaneous Order” (1989) J. Economic Perspectives 85 at 95CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Sugden uses the term “convention”.

99. An important point regarding rational choice theory should, however, be understood here. Arguably, behavior based upon self-interest is just as much a product of internalization as selfless behavior. It is simply the internationalization of a different order, one that imparts a normative quality to self-interest. Indeed, a rational calculus is employed, but it is predicated on a fundamental assumption that is no less normative in nature. The tremendous survival advantage of selfishness ensured it was evolutionarily selected for to a degree. The rationality of rational choice is that decisions are made through a careful cost benefit analysis; however, the basis for this analysis (self-interest) is still very much normative. My point here is that in either case—rational choice, or the blind internalization of norms—internalization is present. Even the most self-serving individuals believe they are normatively justified in their self-interest. Indeed, an argument could be made that the difference is more the nature of the internalization then the presence or absence of it.

100. See supra note 12.

101. Or not internalize as in the case of pure opportunists. What is therefore meant here is the degree of internalization has been selected for.

102. Posner, supra note 5 at 37 (“[W]hat might emerge as a conventional signal in any group is to a certain extent arbitrary.”).

103. For a good overview of the literature regarding this distinction, see Cialdini, Robert B. & Trost, Melanie R., “Social Influence: Social Norms, Conformity, and Compliance” in Gilbert, Daniel T., Fiske, Susan T. & Lindzey, Gardner, eds., The Handbook of Social Psychology, vol. 2 (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998) 151 at 152-53.Google Scholar

104. Posner, supra note 5 at 25.

105. Ibid. See also Sugden, supra note 79 at 47-52, where he speaks of “focal points.” Schelling was perhaps the first to articulate this idea of salience or focal points, facilitating coordination. See Schelling, Thomas C., The Strategy of Conflict (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1980) at 5380, 83-118Google Scholar.

106. Posner, supra note 5 at 29-32.

107. We can see this clearly with norms of an aesthetic nature. For example, the sexualizing of woman’s breasts might be explained in this manner. Likewise, aesthetic offenses such as facial pimples, obesity, and male-pattern baldness might be attributed to their common characteristic of obviousness. To be sure, it would be hard to imagine a norm of this nature arising that could not be plainly seen by others. Research regarding the difficulty in creating a brand image for “invisible” products that are not readily observable, such as men’s underwear, illustrates this point in the context of fashion norms (though even here a select few will see the product). See Yen, Jui-Yen & Chen, Mei-Liang, “Creating Brand Value in Third Countries: A Case of Underwear Industry” (2007) J. International Management Studies 133 Google Scholar (concluding that there is a necessity to place an inordinate emphasis on quality in marketing as a way of overcoming branding difficulties related to invisible products).

108. Smith, Eric A. & Bird, Rebecca Bliege, “Costly Signaling and Cooperative Behaviour” in Gintis, Herbert et al., eds., Moral Sentiments and Material Interests: The Foundations of Cooperation In Economic Life (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2005) 116.Google Scholar

109. Gintis, Herbert, Smith, Eric Alden & Bowles, Samuel, “Costly Signaling and Cooperation” (2001) 213 J. Theor. Biol. 103 at 103CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

110. Though Veblen in his study of conspicuous consumption should be credited with first postulating the idea of signaling. Veblen, Thorstein, The Theory of the Leisure Class: An Economic Study in the Evolution of Institutions, Indian ed. (New Delhi, India: Aakar Books, 2005 [1899]);Google Scholar Spence, A.M., “Job Market Signaling” (1973) 90 Quarterly J. Economics 225 Google Scholar; Zahavi, A., “Mate Selection—a Selection for a Handicap” (1975) 53 J. Theor. Biol. 205 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Zahavi, A., “Reliability in Communication Systems and the Evolution of Altruism” in Stonehouse, B. & Perrins, CM., eds., Evolutionary Ecology (Baltimore, MD: University Park Press, 1977) 253 Google Scholar; Grafen, A., “Biological Signals as Handicaps” (1990) 144 J. Theor. Biol. 517 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Godfray, H.C.J., “Signaling of Need by Offspring to Their Parents” (1991) 352 Nature 328 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

111. Exploration on the biological side tends to be far richer. Although not an exhaustive list, see, e.g., Smith, J. Maynard, “Honest Signaling: The Philip Sidney Game” (1991) 42 Animal Behaviour 1034 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Nur, N. & Hasson, O., “Phenotypic Plasticity and the Handicap Principle” (1984) 110 J. Theor. Biol. 275 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Enquist, M., “Communication During Aggressive Interactions with Particular Reference to Variation in Choice of Behaviour” (1985) 33 Animal Behaviour 1152 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Smith, J. Maynard & Harper, D.G.C., “The Evolution of Aggression: can Selection Generate Variability?” (1988) 319 Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, 557 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Johnstone, RA. & Grafen, A., “The Continuous Sir Philip Sidney Game: A Simple Model of Biological Signaling” (1992) 156 J. Theor. Biol. 215 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Lachmann, M. & Bergstrom, CT., “Signaling Among Relatives. II. Beyond the Tower of Babel” (1998) 54 Theoretical Population Biology 146 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hurd, PL., “Communication in Discrete Action-Response Games” (1995) 174 J. Theor. Biol. 217 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Számadó, S., “The Validity of the Handicap Principle in Discrete Action-Response Games” (1998) 198 J. Theor. Biol. 593 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Noldeke, G. & Samuelson, L., “How Costly is the Honest Signaling of Need?” (1999) 197 J. Theor. Biol. 527 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Johnstone, R.A., “Sexual Selection, Honest Advertisement and the Handicap Principle: Reviewing the Evidence” (1995) 70 Biological Reviews 1 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Gintis, supra note 72; McAndrew, Francis T., “New Evolutionary Perspectives on Altruism: Multilevel-Selection and Costly-Signaling Theories” (2002) 11 Current Directions In Psychological Science 79 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Gintis, Smith & Bowles, supra note 103; Fehr, Ernst & Fischbacher, Urs, “The Nature of Human Altruism” (2003) 425 Nature 785 at 785CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Boone, James L., “The Evolution of Magnanimity: When is it Better to give than to Receive?” (1998) 9 Human Nature 1 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Bowles, Samuel & Gintis, Herbert, “Can Self-Interest Explain Cooperation?” (2005) 2 Evol. Inst. Econ. Rev. 21 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Smith & Bliege Bird, supra note 108.

112. Spence, supra note 110.

113. Posner, supra note 5.

114. Posner, supra note 3; see also Mahoney, Paul & Sanchirico, Chris William, “Competing Norms and Social Evolution: Is the Fittest Norm Efficient?” (2001) 149 U. Pa. L. Rev. 2027 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Posner, supra note 5 at 169-84; Sugden, supra note 98; Bicchieri, supra note 33 at 838.

115. Sugden, supra note 98 at 93.

116. Posner, supra note 5 at 8.

117. Ibid. at 172.

118. Young, H. Peyton, “Social Norms6 (University of Oxford, Department of Economics, Discussion Paper Series No. 307, 2007)Google Scholar.

119. Ibid.

120. Mahoney et al., supra note 114 at 2027.

121. Ibid. at 2062.

122. Ibid. at 2027.

123. Sugden, supra note 98 at 97.

124. Elster, supra note 13 at 125-51.

125. Elster, supra note 81 at 88.

126. Bicchieri, supra note 64 at 838.

127. Ibid.

128. Smith, Eric A. & Winterhalder, Bruce, “Natural Selection and Decision Making: Some Fundamental Principles” in Smith, Eric A. & Winterhalder, Bruce, eds., Evolutionary Ecology and Human Behavior (New York: Walter de Gruyter, 1992) 49 Google Scholar; see also Hirshleifer, J., “Economics from a Biological Viewpoint” (1977) 20 J. L. Econ. 1 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hirshleifer, supra note 79; Hirshleifer, J., Economic Behavior in Adversity (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1987).Google Scholar

129. Posner, supra note 114 at 1723.

130. Nielsen, supra note 76 at 271.

131. Posner, supra note 114 at 1723.

132. A description of the act: “A samurai committing seppuku is expected to stab the left side of his abdomen first and then slit it open sideways. In the process he will also cut and slit the internal organs, causing excruciating pain. It usually takes hours before one dies successfully, thereby prolonging the excruciating pain and requiring a superhuman courage and perseverance.” Fusé, Toyomasa, “Suicide and Culture in Japan: A Study of Seppuku as an Institutionalized Form of Suicide” (1980) 15 Social Psychiatry 57 at 61CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

133. But we need not look so far, there are similar norms that are more familiar to the western reader, such as the practice of dueling in the American South. See Lessig, Lawrence, “The Regulation of Social Meaning” (1995) 62 U. Chicago L. Rev. 943 at 97172 Google Scholar.

134. Indeed, seppuku has been explained as being caused by “intense socialization into and dedication to, one’s social role.” Fusé, supra note 132.

135. Sober, E. & Wilson, D.S., Unto Others: Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998) at 165 Google Scholar; Roberts, S., Order and Dispute: An Introduction to Legal Anthropology (London: Martin Robertson, 1979)Google Scholar; Brown, D., Human Universals (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1991).Google Scholar

136. Sripada, Chandra Sekjar & Stich, Stephen, “A Framework for the Psychology of Norms” in Carruthers, Peter, Laurence, Stephen & Stich, Stephen P., eds., The Innate Mind: Culture and Cognition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007) 280 at 282CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

137. Ibid.

138. Elster, supra note 81 at 98.

139. Cialdini & Trost, supra note 103 at 151.

140. Sripada et al., supra note 136 at 282.

141. Elster, supra note 81 at 101.

142. McAdams, supra note 2 at 637.

143. Sripada et al., supra note 136 at 285; see also Kilborne, Benjamin & Langness, Lewis L., eds., Culture and Human Nature: Theoretical Papers of Melford E. Spiro (New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers, 1994) at 136.Google Scholar

144. See Mirante, Edith T., Burmese Looking Glass: A Human Rights Adventure and a Jungle Revolution (New York: The Atlantic Monthly Press, 1993).Google Scholar

145. Sripada et al., supra note 136 at 285.

146. Posner, supra note 114 at 1723.

147. Sripada et al., supra note 136 at 284.

148. Ibid. at 283.

149. Ibid. at 299.

150. Ibid.

151. Ibid.

152. Ibid. at 282.

153. Ibid.

154. Nucci, Larry, “Moral Development and Character Formation” in Pandey, V.C., ed., Value Education and Education for Human Rights (Delhi, India: Isha Books, 2005) 66 at 77Google Scholar; Sripada et al., supra note 136 at 284.

155. Ellickson, supra note 73 at 46; see Damon, W., Social and Personality Development: Infancy Through Adolescence (New York: W. W. Norton & Co., 1983) at 12837.Google Scholar

156. Nucci, L.P., Education in the Moral Domain (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Turiel, E., The Development of Social Knowledge: Morality & Convention (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983).Google Scholar

157. See Cooter, Robert D., “Law and Unified Social Theory” (1995) 22 J.L. & Soc’y. 50 at 61CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Cooter also references Freud’s theory of the “ghost in the nursery,” which holds that moral behavior is the consequence of childhood memory of parental punishment. See Freud, Sigmund, The Ego and the Id (New York: W. W. Norton & Co., 1990 [1927])Google Scholar.

158. Kilborne & Langness, eds., supra note 143 at 137.

159. Nucci, supra note 154.

160. Ibid. at 78.

161. For a broad survey of this literature, see Cialdini & Trost, supra note 103 at 152-68; Eagly, Alice H. & Chaiken, Shelly, The Psychology of Attitudes (London: Thomson Learning, 1993) at 63034, 642-44Google ScholarPubMed.

162. Asch, supra note 86; Sherif, supra note 86.

163. Sherif, supra note 86.

164. Stangor, Charles, Social Groups in Action and Interaction (New York: Psychology Press, 2004) at 86.Google Scholar

165. Rohrer, J.H. et al., ”The Stability of Autokinetic Judgment” (1954) 49 J. Abnormal & Social Psychology 595 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

166. Gintis, Herbert, “A Framework for the Unification of the Behavioral Sciences” (2007) 30 Behavioral & Brain Sciences 1 at 2CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

167. Ibid.

168. See Hurley, S.L. & Chater, N., Perspectives on Imitation: From Neuroscience to Social Science (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2005)Google Scholar; Raafat, R.M., Chater, N., Frith, C., “Herding in Humans” (2009) 13 Trends in Cognitive Sciences 420 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Berns, G.S. et al., “Neurobiological Correlates of Social Conformity and Independence During Mental Rotation” (2005) 58 Biol. Psychiatry 245 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Klucharev, V. et al., Reinforcement Learning Signal Predicts Social Conformity (2009) 61 Neuron 140 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Wild, B., Erb, M., & Bartels, M., “Are Emotions Contagious? Evoked Emotions While Viewing Emotionally Expressive Faces: Quality, Quantity, Time Course and Gender Differences” (2001) 102 Psychiatry Res. 109 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Nummenmaa, L. et al., “Is Emotional Contagion Special? An MRI Study on Neural Systems for Affective and Cognitive Empathy” (2008) 43 Neuroimage 571 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Guyer, A.E., “Probing the Neural Correlates of Anticipated Peer Evaluation in Adolescence” (2009) 80 Child Dev. 1000 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; see also Damasio, Antonio, Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain (New York: G.P. Putnam, 1994) at 17380 Google Scholar.

169. Posner, supra note 3 at 1724. Norms that are fitness-reducing for the group and/or the individual may nevertheless persist. See Boyd, R. & Richerson, P., “Punishment Allows the Evolution of Cooperation (or anything else) in Sizeable Groups” (1992) 13 Ethol. Sociobiol. 171 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Edgerton, R.B., Sick Societies: Challenging the Myth of Primitive Harmony (New York: Free Press, 1992).Google Scholar

170. See supra notes 116-19 and accompanying text.

171. Malinowski, Bronislaw, Crime and Custom in Savage Society (Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld, 1985 [1926])Google Scholar; Merton, Robert K., Social Theory and Social Structure, 3rd ed. (New York: Free Press, 1968 (1957)) at 184 Google Scholar; Parsons, Talcott, The Social System (London: Routledge, 1951)Google Scholar; Durkheim, Emile, The Division of Labor in Society, trans. by Simpson, George (New York: The Free Press, 1933) at 49229 Google Scholar; Ehrlich, Eugen, Fundamental Principles of the Sociology of Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1936)Google Scholar; Hayek, Friedrich A., The Constitution of Liberty (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1978) at 36 Google Scholar; see also Thibaut, John W & Kelley, Harold H., The Social Psychology of Groups (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1959) at 13542 Google Scholar.

172. See, e.g., Dawkins, Richard, The Selfish Gene (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976) at 812 Google Scholar; Wilson, Edward O., Sociobiology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1975) at 10629 Google ScholarPubMed; Smith, J. Maynard, “Group Selection and Kin Selection” (1964) 201 Nature 1145 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Williams, G.C., Adaptation and Natural Selection: A Critique of Some Current Evolutionary Thought (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996)Google Scholar; Wynne-Edwards, V.C., Evolution Through Group Selection (Oxford: Blackwell Scientific Publications, 1986)Google Scholar. However, group selection theories have recently seen a minor resurgence although not as a fundamental mechanism for selection. Multi-level selection theory (MST) has been proposed as an evolutionary model that supports group selection. See Wilson, D.S. & Sober, E., “Reintroducing Group Selection to the Human Behavioral Sciences” (1994) 17 Behavioral and Brain Sciences 585 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Wilson, D.S. & Wilson, E.O., “Evolution “for the good of the group” (2008) 96 American Scientist 378 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; See also Koeslag, J.H., “Sex, the Prisoner’s Dilemma Game, and the Evolutionary Inevitability of Cooperation” (1997) 189 J. Theor. Biol. 53 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Wade, M.J., “An Experimental Study of Group Selection” (1977) 31 Evolution 134 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Koeslag, J.H., “Evolution of Cooperation: Cooperation Defeats Defection in the Cornfield Model” (2003) 224 J. Theor. Biol. 399 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

173. Ellickson, supra note 1 at 152.

174. Fehr & Fischbacher, supra note 111.

175. Dawkins, supra note 172; Wilson, supra note 172; Smith, supra note 172.

176. Gintis et al., supra note 103; see also McAndrew, supra note 111; Fehr & Fischbacher, supra note 111 at 789.

177. Using both hands when presenting someone with money or a gift is a norm in some parts of China. Having lived in China for the better part of decade, I personally internalized this norm.

178. Lewontin, R.C., “Sociobiology—A of Darwinism” (1976) 2 Philosophy of Science Association 22 at 24Google Scholar; see also Rose, Steven, Kamin, Leon J. & Lewontin, R.C., Not in our Genes: Biology, Ideology and Human Nature (New York: Pantheon, 1984) at 248 Google Scholar; Lewontin, Richard, It Ain’t Necessarily So: The Dream of the Human Genome and Other Illusions (New York: New York Review of Books, 2001).Google Scholar

179. Lewontin, supra note 178.

180. Ruse, Michael, Sociobiology: Sense or Nonsense?, 2nd ed. (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, 1985) at 103.Google Scholar

181. Lewontin, supra note 178 at 25. Some critics of evolutionary psychology claim that there simply aren’t enough genes to code for a large number of innate cognitive adaptations. See Ehrlich, Paul & Feldman, Marcus, “Genes and Cultures: What Creates Our Behavioral Phenome?” (2003) 44 Current Anthropology 87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

182. Sociobiology Study Group, Sociobiology—A New Biological Determinism” in The Ann Arbor Science for the People Editorial Collective, eds., in Biology as a Social Weapon (Minneapolis, MN: Burgess Publishing Company, 1977) 134 at 143Google Scholar.

183. Lewontin, supra note 178 at 25.

184. Ibid.

185. Ibid.

186. Ibid.

187. For an example of some scholars who make such claims, see, e.g., Pugh, George Edwin, The Biological Origin of Human Values (London: Routledge, 1977)Google Scholar; Lumsden, Charles L. & Wilson, Edward O., Promethean Fire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1983)Google Scholar; in the field of economics, see Schotter, A., The Economic Theory of Social Institutions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981) at 16064 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Rubin, Paul H., “Evolved Ethics and Efficient Ethics” (1982) 3 J. Econ. Behav. & Org. 161 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; closer to the field of law, see Hirshleifer, Jack, “Privacy: Its Origin, Function, and Future” (1980) 9 J. Legal Stud. 649 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; see also Jones, Owen D. & Goldsmith, Timothy H., “Law and Behavioral Biology” (2005) 105 Colum. L. Rev. 405 Google Scholar; Epstein, Richard A., “A Taste for Privacy? Evolution and the Emergence of a Naturalistic Ethic” (1980) 9 J. Legal Stud. 665 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

188. Lewontin, supra note 178 at 25.

189. Evolutionist Paul R. Ehrlich referring to evolutionary psychology. Hagen, Edward H., “Controversial Issues in Evolutionary Psychology” in Buss, David M., ed., The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 2005) 151.Google Scholar

190. See Posner, supra note 5 at 71.

191. In terms of human normative behavior.

192. For social learning, see Bandura, A., Social Learning Theory (Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1977)Google ScholarPubMed (giving an overview of theoretical and experimental advances in the field of social learning); see also Zentall, T.R., “Imitation: Definitions, Evidence, and Mechanisms” (2006) 9 Animal Cognition 335 CrossRefGoogle Scholar (presenting an overview of various types of social learning).

193. Gintis, supra note 72 at 407. See also R. O’Gorman, Wilson, D. & Miller, R., “An Evolved Cognitive Bias for Social Norms” (2008) 29 Evolution & Human Behavior 71 Google Scholar.

194. The basic premise of Dual Inheritance Theory is that human behavior evolves through both genetic and cultural processes. For Dual Inheritance Theory, see Lumsden, C. & Wilson, E., Genes, Mind and Culture: The Coevolutionary Process (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981)Google Scholar (formulating a series of mathematical models for how genes and culture might coevolve); Cavalli-Sforza, L. & Feldman, M., Cultural Transmission and Evolution: A Quantitative Approach (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1981)Google Scholar (presenting a mathematical theory concerning the spread of cultural traits); Boyd, R. & Richerson, P., Culture and the Evolutionary Process (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1985)Google Scholar (examining the relationship between culture as a transmission system and genetic evolution); see also Richerson, Peter J. & Boyd, Robert Not by Genes Alone: How Culture Transformed Human Evolution (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar (presenting an excellent overview of the current state of cultural evolution research).

195. For the concept of an evolutionarily stable strategy (ESS), see Smith, supra note 77.

196. The existence of sociopaths, perhaps the quintessential pure opportunist, attests to the viability of a non-cooperative strategy in evolutionary game theoretical terms. Sociopaths comprise a sizable percentage of the population, roughly 3-4% of the male population and approximately 1% of the female population. Davison, G.C. & Neale, J.M., Abnormal Psychology, 6th ed., (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1994)Google Scholar; Robins, L.N., Tipp, J. & Przybeck, T., “Antisocial Personality” in Robins, L.N. & Regier, D.A., eds., Psychiatric Disorders in America (New York: Free Press, 1991) 258.Google Scholar Sociopaths demonstrate a “marked degree of impulsivity,” which makes sense for an individual with an enormously high discount rate. See Mealey, supra note 82 at 134.

197. See Posner, supra note 5 at 112-19.

198. Madison, Kristen, “Government, Signaling, and Social Norms” (2001) 2001 U. Ill. L. Rev. 867 at 875Google Scholar.

199. See Posner, supra note 5 at 18.

200. Kahan, Dan M., “Signaling or Reciprocating? A Response to Eric Posner’s Law and Social Norms” (2002) 36 U. Rich. L. Rev. 367 at 374Google Scholar; see also Wendel, supra note 44 at 38.

201. See, e.g., Thaler, supra note 42 at 92-106.

202. Posner, supra note 16 at 476.

203. Kahan, supra note 200.

204. Hardin, Russell, “Law and Social Norms in the Large” (2000) 86 Va. L. Rev. 1821 at 1822CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

205. See Jones, E.E., Wells, H.H. & Torrey, R, “Some Effects of Feedback from the Experimenter on Conformity Behaviour” (1958) 57 J. Abnormal and Social Psychology 207 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Thibaut, J.W. & Strickland, L.H., “Psychological Set and Social Conformity” (1956) 25 J. Personality 115 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

206. Deutsch, M. & Gerard, H.G.A Study of Normative and Informational Social Influence upon Individual Judgment” (1955) 51 J. Abnormal and Social Psychology 629 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

207. Cialdini & Trost, supra note 103 at 166; See Hatfield, E., Cacioppo, J.T. & Rapson, R.L., Emotional Contagion (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994).Google Scholar

208. Berry, J.W, “Independence and Conformity in Subsistence-Level Societies” (1967) 7 J. Personality & Social Psychology 415 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

209. Posner, supra note 5 at 36.

210. Indeed, the “defining characteristic of sociopaths is their apparent lack of sincere social emotions ….” Mealey, supra note 82 at 135. In the context of our present discussion sociopathy can thus be understood as adaptive; it is a viable evolutionary strategy, accounting for its resilient presence in human psychology.

211. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders Dsm-Iv-Tr 701, 4th ed. (Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric Association, 1994)Google Scholar.

212. Hare, Robert D., Hart, Stephen D. & Harpur, Timothy J., “Psychopathy and the DSM—IV Criteria for Antisocial Personality Disorder” (1991) 100 J. Abnormal Psychology 391 at 398CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

213. Ibid. at 397.

214. Ibid. at 398.

215. Ibid. at 397.

216. Ibid. at 398.

217. Ibid.

218. Ibid.

219. Cleckley, Hervey, Mask of Sanity: An Attempt to Clarify Some Issues about the so-called Psychopathic Personality, 5th ed. (Augusta, GA: 1988 [1941]) at 33839 Google Scholar.

220. Pulkkinen, L., “The Role of Impulse Control in the Development of Antisocial and Prosocial Behavior” in Olweus, D., Block, J. & Radke-Yarrow, M., eds., Development of Antisocial and Prosocial Behavior: Research, Theories, and Issues (New York: Academic Press, 1985).Google Scholar

221. Mealey, supra note 82 at 166; see also Christie, R & Geis, F.L., Studies in Machiavellianism (New York: Academic Press, 1970)Google Scholar; Mccord, J.The Psychopath & Moral Development” in Laufer, W.S. & Day, J.M., eds., Personality Theory, Moral Development, and Criminal Behavior (Toronto, ON: Lexington Books, 1983) 357 Google Scholar; Raine, A., “Antisocial Behavior and Social Psychophysiology” in Wagner, H.L., ed., Social Psychophysiology and Emotion: Theory and Clinical Application (New York: Wiley, 1988) 231 Google Scholar; Raine, A., “Evoked Potentials and Psychopathy” (1989) 8 Int’l J. Psychophysiology 1 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Forth, A.E. & Hare, R.D, “The Contingent Negative Variation in Psychopaths” (1989) 26 Psychophysiology 676 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

222. Gintis, Herbert et al., “Gene-Culture Coevolution and the Emergence of Altruistic Behaviour in Humans” in Crawford, Charles B. & Krebs, Dennis, eds., Foundations of Evolutionary Psychology (Florence, KY: Psychology Press 2008) 325 Google Scholar. See Mealey, supra note 82 at 133.

223. Correctional Service of Canada, A Mental Health Profile of Federally Sentenced Offenders” (1990) 2 Forum on Corrections Research 7 Google Scholar. Note that I am here using antisocial personality disorder synonymously with sociopathy.

224. Becker, Gary S., Grossman, Michael & Murphy, Kevin M., “Rational Addiction and the Effect of Price on Consumption” (1991) 81 Aea Papers and Proceedings 237 Google Scholar; see also Glaeser, Edward L., “Economic approach to crime and punishment” in Newman, Peter, ed., The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 1998).Google Scholar

225. Posner, supra note 5 at 1-8, 49-50, 122-24, 133.

226. Ibid. at 35.

227. McAdams, supra note 2 at 672.

228. See Posner, supra note 5 at 18.

229. Ibid. at 43.

230. Ibid. at 44.

231. See Mealey, L., “The Sociobiology of Sociopathy: An Integrated Model” (1995) 18 Behavioral and Brain Sciences 523 CrossRefGoogle Scholar (identifying hypothetical ancestral conditions that would make sociopathy adaptive); but see Crusio, Wim E., “The Sociopathy of Sociobiology” (1995) 18 Behavioral & Brain Sciences 552 CrossRefGoogle Scholar (charging that Mealey’s evolutionary reasoning is logically flawed, and the import of the cited genetic evidence exaggerated).

232. The gender gap in sociopathy rates is interesting (“3%-4% of the male population and less than 1% of the female population”). See Mealey, supra note 82 at 133. One possible explanation for this gap is that as the physically stronger gender, males were evolutionarily better positioned to pursue an opportunist strategy based on aggression. This could go far in explaining the higher rates of criminality and propensity towards violence found in males.

233. The limits of even deeply internalized norms speaks to this fact. Even the strongest cooperators may abandon their moral convictions given the right circumstances. Consider situations of mass panic, or life and death me-or-you situations, where feelings of right and wrong fall by the wayside to facilitate survival. We even accept this inherent normative flexibility to a degree in others; for instance, we judge less harshly an individual who takes an innocent life when a gun is held to their own head. This assumption is so deep-seated in fact, this is a legal defense, i.e. the defense of necessity. See infra notes 241-42 and accompanying text.

234. Posner, supra note 5 at 19.

235. See Mealey’s concept of secondary sociopaths, Mealey, supra note 82 at 163; see also the “Mach” scale (as in Machiavellian) developed by Christie & Geis, supra note 221.

236. Smith, J. Maynard, Evolutionary Genetics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989) at 12636 Google ScholarPubMed; see also Hawkes, K., “Sharing and Collective Action” in Smith, Eric A. & Winterhalder, Bruce, eds., Evolutionary Ecology and Human Behavior (New York: Walter de Gruyter, 1992) 269 Google Scholar at 281.

237. Nielsen, supra note 76 at 278.

238. See Smith, supra note 77 at 164-66.

239. Mealey, supra note 82 at 135 (speaking about sociopathy).

240. Schulsinger, F., “Psychopathy: Heredity and Environment” (1972) 1 Int’l J. Mental Health 190 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Cadoret, R.J., “Psychopathology of Adopted-Away Offspring of Biologic Parents with Antisocial Personality” (1978) 35 Archives of General Psychiatry 176 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Crowe, R.R., “An Adoption Study of Anti-Social Personality” (1974) 31 Archives of General Psychiatry 785 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Cadoret, R.J. & Cain, , “C. Sex Differences in Predictors of Antisocial Behavior in Adoptees” (1980) 37 Archives of General Psychiatry 1171 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Cadoret, R.J., Troughton, E. & O’Gorman, T.W., “Genetic and Environmental Factors in Alcohol Abuse and Antisocial Personality” (1987) 48 J. Studies on Alcohol 1 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Cadoret, R.J. & Stewart, M.A., “An Adoption Study of Attention Deficit/Hyperactivity/Aggression and their Relationship to Adult Antisocial Personality” (1991) 32 Comprehensive Psychiatry 73 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

241. Mealey, supra note 82 at 135.

242. Ibid.

243. Cooke, David J. et al., “Searching for the Pan-Cultural Core of Psychopathic Personality Disorder” (2005) 39 Personality and Individual Differences 283 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

244. Cooke, David J., “Psychopathy Across Cultures” in Cooke, David J., Forth, Adelle E. & Hare, Robert D., eds., Psychopathy: Theory, Research, and Implications for Society (Boston, MA: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1997) 13 at 14Google Scholar.

245. Robins, Tipp & Przybeck, supra note 196 at 259.

246. Mealey, supra note 82 at 163.

247. Ibid. at 138.

248. Posner, supra note 5 at 22.

249. Pitchford, Ian, “The Origins of Violence: Is Psychopathy an Adaptation?” (2001) 1 The Human Nature Rev. 28 at 28Google Scholar.

250. Posner, supra note 5 at 22.

251. Ibid. 19-21.

252. Wendel, supra note 44 at 40.

253. Kahan, supra note 200.

254. Posner, Eric A., “Law and Social Norms: The Case of Tax Compliance” (2000) 86 Va. L. Rev. 1781 at 1807CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

255. See Wendel, supra note 44 at 27; Duxbury, supra note 48 at 725-33.

256. Wendel, supra note 44 at 36.

257. Duxbury, supra note 48 at 732.

258. Ibid. at 725.

259. Ibid. at 727.

260. Ibid. at 733.

261. See Wendel, supra note 44 at 25, 29; Madison, supra note 198.

262. Wendel, supra note 44 at 37.

263. Madison, supra note 198; see also Schaefer, Elmer J., “Predicting Defection” (2002) 36 U. Rich. L. Rev. 443 at 445-46Google Scholar (pointing out that people signal to communicate other characteristics besides discount rates).

264. Wendel, supra note 44 at 29.

265. Ibid. at 25.

266. Ibid. at 34.

267. See supra notes 161-68, 205-08 and accompanying text.

268. Wendel, supra note 44 at 32.

269. McAdams, supra note 2 at 666.

270. Ibid.

271. See Luce, R. & Raiffa, H., Games and Decisions: An Introduction and Critical Survey (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1957) at 9899 Google Scholar.

272. McAdams, supra note 2 at 664.

273. Mahoney, Paul G., “Norms and Signals: Some Skeptical Observations” (2002) 36 U. Rich. L. Rev. 387 at 392Google Scholar.

274. Ibid. at 391.

275. Ibid. at 394.

276. McAdams, supra note 2 at 666.

277. Ibid. at 655.

278. Wendel, supra note 44 at 31.

279. McAdams, supra note 2 at 655.

280. Wendel, supra note 44 at 31.

281. Hardin, supra note 204 at 1826.

282. Ibid. at 1826-27.

283. Ibid. at 1826.

284. McAdams agrees: “Absent a highly predictive alternative theory, I think one can justify cutting normative motivations out of the explanation only if one of the following is true: (1) normative motivations do not actually exist, or (2) normative motivations, while they exist, are unrelated to the behavior we call norms. Posner explicitly rejects the first proposition, and the second is simply not tenable.” McAdams, supra note 2 at 681.

285. Cooter, supra note 157.