Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-vsgnj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-16T09:32:44.965Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Justice and the Individual in the Hippocratic Tradition

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 July 2009

Richard M. Zaner
Affiliation:
Ann Geddes Stahlman Professor of Medical Ethics and Philosophy of Medicine, and Director of the Center for Clinical and Research Ethics at Vanderbilt University Medical Center, Nashville.

Extract

Among the many striking features of modern medicine is one that has rarely received its due, save by those specialists in the arcane and remote: medical historians. Medicine is a profoundly historical enterprise, deeply marked by and in continuous, if only implicit, dialogue with its own history. Historical reflection on medicine is therefore an especially compelling undertaking. A case in point: scratch almost any physician today and you find an abiding commitment to “Hippocmtic morality.”

Type
Special Section: Can Justice Endure Healthcare Reform?: From Patient Care to Policy (and Back Again)
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1996

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Notes

1. Liddle, GW. The mores of clinical investigation. Journal of Clinical bwestigation 1967; 46:1028–30.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

2. Siegler, M. Clinical ethics and clinical medicine. Archives of Internal Medicine 1979; 139:914–5.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

3. Pellegrino, ED. Humanism and the Physician. Knoxville, Tennessee: University of Tennessee Press, 1979.Google ScholarPubMed

4. Pellegrino, ED. The healing relationship: the architectonics of clinical medicine. In: Shelp, EE, Ed. The Clinical Encounter: The Moral Fabric of the Physician-Patient Relationship. Dordrecht and Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Co., 1983:153–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

5. Pellegrino, ED. Medicine and philosophy: some notes on the flirtations of Minerva and Aesculapius. Presidential Address, Society for Health and Human Values, Philadelphia, 1974.Google Scholar

6. Pellegrino, ED. The anatomy of clinical judgments: some notes on right reason and right action. In: Engelhardt, HT Jr, Spicker, SF, Towers, B, Eds. Clinical Judgment: A Critical Appraisal. Dordrecht and Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Co., 1979:2944.Google Scholar

7. See, among others, Starr, P. The Social Transformation of American Medicine. New York: Basic Books, Inc., 1988.Google ScholarPubMed

8. Seldin, D. The medical model: biomedical science as the basis for medicine. In: Seldin, D. Beyond Tomorrow. New York: The Rockefeller University Press, 1977:3140.Google Scholar

9. Forstram, LA. The scientific autonomy of clinical medicine. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 1977; 2(1):819.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

10. Pellegrino, ED, Thomasma, D. The Philosophical Basis of Medical Practice. New York: Oxford University Press, 1987.Google Scholar

11. Kleinman, A. The Illness Narratives: Healing, Suffering & the Human Condition. New York: Basic Books, 1988.Google Scholar

12. Cassell, EJ. The nature of suffering and the goals of medicine. New England Journal of Medicine 1982; 306:639–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

13. White, KL, Ed. The Task of Medicine: Dialogue at Wickenburg. Menlo Park, California: The Henry J. Kaiser Family Foundation, 1988.Google Scholar

14. Engelhardt, HT Jr, Spicker, SF, Towers, B, Eds. Clinical Judgment: A Critical Appraisal. Dordrecht and Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Co., 1979.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

15. Shelp, EE, Ed. The Clinical Encounter: The Moral Fabric of the Physician-Patient Relationship. Dordrecht and Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Co., 1983.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

16. Edelstein, L. Ancient Medicine. Tempkin, CL (trans.) Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1967:351.Google Scholar

17. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:53, 37.Google Scholar

18. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:350.Google Scholar

19. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:201.Google Scholar

20. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:201, n. 18.Google Scholar

21. For a more detailed analysis, see Zaner, RM. Ethics and the Clinical Encounter. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, 1988; Chapters 7, 8.Google ScholarPubMed

22. Zaner, RM. Parted bodies, departed souls: the body in ancient medicine and anatomy. In: Leder, D, Ed. The Body in Medical Thought and Practice. Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1992:101–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

23. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:333–47.Google Scholar

24. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:347.Google Scholar

25. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:348.Google Scholar

26. For further analysis, see note 16. Edelstein, 1967:663.Google Scholar

27. The prohibitions on giving “deadly drugs” and any “abortive remedy,” as well as the use of dietetics and certain drugs, and the ban on “cutting” (lithotomy); see note 16. Edelstein, 1967:6, 915.Google Scholar

28. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:6.Google Scholar

29. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:22–3.Google Scholar

30. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:23.Google Scholar

31. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:329.Google Scholar

32. Pellegrino, ED. Being ill and being healed: some reflections on the grounding of medical morality. In: Kestenbaum, V, Ed. The Humanity of the III: Phenomenological Perspectives. Knoxville, Tennessee: University of Tennessee Press, 1982:157–66.Google Scholar

33. See note 21. Zaner, 1988:5391.Google Scholar

34. Lenrow, PB. The work of helping strangers. In: Rubenstein, H, Bloch, MH, Eds. Things That Matter: Influences on Helping Relationships. New York: Macmillan Publishing Company, 1982:4257.Google Scholar

35. Zaner, RM. Encountering the other. In: Campbell, CS, Lustig, A, Eds. Duties to Others. Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, Inc., 1994:1738. (Medicine and Theology Series,vol. xx.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

36. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:35.Google Scholar

37. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:3637.Google Scholar

38. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:37.Google Scholar

39. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:321.Google Scholar

40. See also Coulter, H. The Divided Legacy, vol. I. Washington, D.C.: Wehawken Book Company, 1975:282.Google Scholar

41. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:321;Google Scholar “love of man” includes, as mentioned in other texts of the Hippocratic corpus (On the Physician and On Decorum especially), respect, gentleness, kindheartedness, charity, and regularity of habits.

42. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:351.Google Scholar

43. See note 20. Zaner, 1988:283320.Google Scholar

44. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:40.Google Scholar

45. The Oath. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:6.Google Scholar

46. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:326–7.Google Scholar

47. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:201.Google Scholar

48. Cited in Edelstein. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:284.Google Scholar

49. See note 40. Coulter, 1975:viii.Google Scholar

50. See note 20. Zaner, 1988:182–4, 219–21.Google Scholar

51. These stand in interesting contrast to the other medical traditions, especially Dogmatism, which emphasized causal (diagnosis) and analogical (analogismos) reasoning.

52. See note 20. Zaner, 1988:330–1.Google Scholar

53. See note 16. Edelstein, 1967:347.Google Scholar