Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-ndw9j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T00:29:10.574Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

STYLE AND PERSONHOOD: THE CASE OF THE AMASIS PAINTER

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 September 2018

James Whitley*
Affiliation:
School of History, Archaeology and Religion, Cardiff University, UK
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

For archaeologists discussion of style is unavoidable. Within classical archaeology ‘style’ is closely associated with connoisseurship as practised by J. D. Beazley. Style identifies individuals, artistic personalities such as the Amasis Painter. This notion of style necessarily overlaps with another debate within both anthropology and prehistoric archaeology (personhood) which also touches on an older discussion within classical studies. These two debates have remained strangers to each other. The article explores these issues in relation to the iconography of hares and arming scenes. Notions of personhood and agency force us to re-evaluate such iconography and its effectiveness as narrative.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s) 2018. Published by Cambridge University Press 

Introduction: the centrality of style

‘Style’ is an indispensable term within archaeology. It has been argued, with some force, that without an implicit ‘theory of style’ the practice of both archaeology and art history would be impossible.Footnote 1 That is not to say that there is an agreed definition as to what the term means, since ‘style’ operates on several scales.Footnote 2 At the largest scale (what we might call the ‘macro-scale’) there is, for example, the La Tène art style of Iron Age Europe (usually thought of as Celtic).Footnote 3 At this level style is seen as an expression of a wider cultural (or perhaps less certainly) ethnic group. Notions of ‘Greek Art’, it could be argued, depend on a notion of Greek style – since, whatever Greek art is, it is not simply the sum total of art objects produced by Greek speakers.Footnote 4 Within the narrower confines of the archaic Aegean most of us are reasonably well acquainted with the regional styles of Orientalizing pottery in the seventh century BC – we talk quite easily of the East Greek ‘Wild Goat’ style, or Knossian Orientalizing, or Protocorinthian or Protoattic.Footnote 5

Scholars of Attic vase painting however are perhaps more familiar with another definition, forcefully put by J. D. Beazley:

The phrase ‘in the style of’ is used by some where I should write ‘in the manner of’; this has warrant, but I was brought to think of ‘style’ as a sacred thing, as the man himself.Footnote 6

Style is then what allows us to distinguish the work of one person (one painter) from another. Defining individual style is what connoisseurship and attribution is supposed to be all about. Insofar as there is a theory underlying this it is the idea that unconscious tricks of draughtsmanship – the way in which those fussy details such as eyes, ears, noses and chins are drawn – betray the presence of an individual, a definable ‘artistic personality’. This certainly works for Beazley's most celebrated case, the Berlin Painter – the first painter to be clearly distinguished by this means from his contemporary the Kleophrades Painter.Footnote 7

In the case of the Amasis Painter however one could argue that it is as much iconography as the ‘tricks of draftsmanship’ (style) that characterises this particular artistic personality. Strictly speaking, of course, the Amasis Painter (the painter who worked closely with the potter Amasis, and who was almost certainly the same person) has been defined partly through those vases signed ΑΜΑΣΙΣ ΜΕΠΟΙΕΣΕΝ, but more generally through Beazley's and Karouzou's attributions.Footnote 8 He (and let us go with ‘he’ for the time being) is thought to be responsible for around 140 vases datable to the mid-sixth century BC.Footnote 9 His main vehicle was not so much the krater (of which we have only a few examples) as the amphora (both the neck amphora and the belly amphora). He is also responsible for a number of cups with a very distinctly non-heroic subject matter. As painter working in the mid-sixth century he is thought of as being in some way in competition with his contemporaries, Lydos and Exekias.Footnote 10 The consensus is that, while ‘Amasis’ is as fine a painter as Lydos (and perhaps a more interesting one), he was not quite as good as Exekias in the two things that matter most to traditional classical archaeologists – the development of visual narrative and the development of more anatomically accurate renderings of the human figure. As John Boardman puts it:

The delicate touch and wit of the Amasis painter are an excellent foil to the workmanlike Lydos or the more statuesque dignity of Exekias.Footnote 11

This is a nice way of saying that the Amasis Painter seems to have had a greater interest than other painters in rather outré subjects, such as Dionysiac scenes with numerous satyrs and pictures of satyrs δεφόμενοι.Footnote 12 It is also, of course, a way of damning with faint praise – he is a fine painter, but no Exekias – not the master of narrative compression that we can see in the scene of Achilles and Ajax playing dice, or the ‘suicide of Ajax’ on a vase once in Boulogne.Footnote 13

This comparison may be unfair (as I hope to show towards the end of this article). What I want to emphasise here is the manner in which Boardman describes the Amasis Painter – as a defined, bounded individual, not only responsible for but more or less co-extensive with that body of painted pots that have been attributed to him. Boardman uses the active indicative throughout, with ‘the Amasis Painter’ and ‘he’ as the subject. This, you might say, is merely a matter of common sense. For were not vase painters individuals?

That depends of course on how we use the term ‘individual’. I am not seeking, in this paper, to undermine the general principle of attribution; most of Beazley's attributions have stood up pretty well, when looked at from different perspectives.Footnote 14 Painters were certainly persons. But that does not quite make them individuals in the modern sense, as bounded entities – especially not in the judicial sense as the ultimate locus of responsibility and agency. Beazley himself was not quite so ‘commonsensical’ when it came to the Amasis Painter:

He has much in common with the Heidelberg Painter, surpassing him, however, in all respects; a good deal also of Kleitias, if not the finest part, has passed into him – lightness, elegance, and precise technique.Footnote 15

Now one might say that this use of the passive, and the idea that a part of another painter ‘has passed into him’, might be seen as just a façon de parler, an aspect of Beazley's ‘scholarly personality’ – his style, as it were. Even so, this turn of phrase is not casual – Beazley was notably fastidious in everything he did, especially the way he wrote. If he was ever ambiguous he was purposefully so. His form of words moreover is strikingly similar to the way in which modern anthropologists talk, not about individuals, but partible and permeable persons – so-called ‘dividuals’ (see below). And it is also in keeping with some of Beazley's more famous bons mots:

My attributions have often been misquoted. I may perhaps be allowed to point out that I make a distinction between the vase by a painter and a vase in his manner; and that ‘manner’, ‘imitation’, ‘following’, ‘school’, ‘circle’, ‘group’, ‘influence’, ‘kinship’ are not, in my vocabulary, synonyms.Footnote 16

Beazley here is being characteristically precise in his terms (as he is with others, such as the distinction between ‘type’ and ‘specimen’). We are, after all, being instructed as much in the use of proper vocabulary as in the proper use of the book he has written. And yet it is not immediately clear – at least to me – how we should take his words. To put it at its most ‘theoretical’, is this statement an epistemological statement or an ontological one? It has mainly been read as epistemological – in an ideal world we would be able to attribute every piece to a definable individual, and the fact that we cannot is simply an indication of the limits of our current state of knowledge. Much excellent recent scholarship (building on Beazley's attributions) has sought more accurate estimates of the numbers of potters and painters working in archaic and classical Athens, for perfectly good historical reasons.Footnote 17 Philip Sapirstein in particular has emphasised that the some of the painters defined by Beazley are more individual than others; some, like the Amasis Painter, the Berlin Painter and Exekias, are well-defined ‘artistic personalities’; others are simply hands, where a small number of vases can be grouped by individual style. Sapirstein argues that several of these ‘hands’ (with only six or so vases attributed to them) might represent the work of the same painter. This suspicion is borne out by one black-figure painter, Sakonides (a contemporary of the Amasis Painter), of whom Beazley says:

The cups with this painter's signature divide into three groups. Without the signature no one would have guessed the three groups to be by one hand.Footnote 18

Many of these ‘hands’ should therefore be combined to give a more accurate picture of the number of craftsmen working in Athens in ancient times.

The significance of this distinction between artistic personalities and hands however goes beyond its utility in arriving at better, more accurate, estimates of the size of the Athenian pottery industry. For if we see this as a purely epistemological problem we would expect to be able to refine our attributions and eventually be able to relate almost all Attic vases to particular painters. An epistemological problem would become simply a problem of method: eventually all ‘hands’ would become definable ‘artistic personalities’. Is this really the case? Perhaps. But if so, it is interesting that we can more easily attribute vases to definable ‘artistic personalities’ in some areas of Greek archaeology than in others. Attribution to ‘individuals’ is much easier in the study of Attic vase painting than it is within the study of Protocorinthian, and this is not because of lack of either evidence or of scholarly effort. Somehow Protocorinthian vases yield fewer ‘individuals’ who are painters than do Athenian ones.Footnote 19 Even within Attic black figure there are some groups which are more resistant to attribution than others – the Tyrrhenian Group (for example) remains stubbornly a group, not a set of painters or workshops.Footnote 20

It may be helpful here to illustrate my argument, not in the normal way of providing examples of vases being discussed, but by expressing Beazley's statements in pictorial form, as Venn diagrams. Figure 1 shows his view of the Amasis Painter and his relations with Kleitias and the Heidelberg Painter. In Figure 2 Beazley's words in his ‘instructions for use’ become a series of concentric circles with ‘style’ at the centre, and kinship at the periphery. But these pictures do not quite resolve the ambiguity of his words. In some ways they highlight what may be called the ontological/epistemological dilemma.

Figure 1. Venn diagram showing the Amasis Painter's relationship to the Heidelberg Painter and Kleitias (after Beazley (Reference Beazley, von Bothmer and Moore1986) 52). Image prepared by Kirsty Harding. ‘He has much in common with the Heidelberg Painter, surpassing him, however, in all respects; a good deal also of Kleitias, if not the finest part, has passed into him – lightness, elegance, and precise technique.’

Figure 2. Venn diagram illustrating Beazley's use of the terms ‘style’, manner, kinship and so forth (after Beazley, ABV x). Image prepared by Kirsty Harding. ‘My attributions have often been misquoted. I may perhaps be allowed to point out that I make a distinction between the vase by a painter and a vase in his manner; and that “manner”, “imitation”, “following”, “school”, “circle”, “group”, “influence”, “kinship” are not, in my vocabulary, synonyms.’

I propose to read Beazley's statements ‘ontologically’, as saying something about the painters themselves, and their entanglements with both other persons and other things.Footnote 21 But to do this I first have to explain what the debate on personhood is all about.

Personhood: the debate in anthropology and prehistory

Though she did not coin the term, it was largely through Marilyn Strathern's ethnographic fieldwork in Melanesia (particularly New Guinea) that the term ‘dividual’ passed into anthropological discourse. Strathern conceived Melanesian persons – dividuals – as being radically different from Euro-American individuals. Whereas in our culture, clearly gendered persons are supposed to be the final locus of responsibility and identity, in Melanesia personhood is dispersed both among networks of other people (particularly kin) and among things (gifts, land). Melanesian persons are not so much discrete, bounded entities (individuals) as a locus of connexions of other people and things (dividuals) – assemblages of parts, if you will. As Strathern put it:

Far from being regarded as unique entities, Melanesian persons are as dividually as they are individually conceived. They contain a generalised sociality within. Indeed, persons are frequently constructed as the plural and composite side of the relationships that produced them. The singular person can be imagined as a social microcosm.Footnote 22

These ideas were taken up in anthropology, particularly in the work of Alfred Gell, who graphically explained some of Strathern's ideas in the form of diagrams.Footnote 23 For Strathern as for Gell, where we might simply (in ‘common sense’ terms) see an exchange of pigs between two Melanesian men as being a straightforward transaction between two individuals, from a Melanesian perspective it is not only the pig that is being exchanged but a whole history of earlier exchanges, containing within it parts of the previous owners of the pigs. The pig then is never wholly given away (and is not simply a pig) but contains within it a whole universe of relationships. Gell built upon these ideas (and those of Nicholas Thomas), notably in his discussion of the distributed person in his ‘Art and Agency’.Footnote 24 Dividuals have distributed agency.

These ideas were then taken up enthusiastically by British prehistorians, notably Chris Fowler. Personhood was central to his interpretation of Neolithic of the Isle of Man.Footnote 25 The notion of ‘dividual’ appealed to British prehistorians precisely because the concept seemed to explain some of the curious recurrent patterns we find in the British and Irish Neolithic. Chief among these was the division of body parts in burials in collective tombs such as West Kennet Long Barrow. Here there was no attempt to maintain the integrity of persons buried within the chambers; rather disarticulated body parts (crania, long bones, ribs) had been sorted into different chambers by age and sex.Footnote 26 British prehistorians have moreover resisted the inference that, with the coming of single grave inhumation at the end of the Neolithic, this form of personhood fundamentally changed. Beaker single inhumations in stone cists are no longer an index of the ‘rise of the individual’ in the Early Bronze Age.Footnote 27

In sum then the way that the notion of personhood was received within British prehistory served to reinforce the established division of types of society. On the one hand were ‘prehistoric and ethnographic’ societies, inhabited by dividuals; on the other were literate ‘historical and modern’ societies, inhabited by individuals. Personhood thus served to reinforce the ‘Great Divide’ between European prehistory and the classical world. And the idea gained traction that, the further away from the West (either geographically or chronologically) you went, the greater the likelihood of encountering radically different persons – that is. dividuals. Table 1 sums up the picture.

Table 1 The ontological divide between prehistory/ethnography and the study of historical societies.

Within anthropology however there were always scholars who thought this division a little too neat. The term ‘dividual’ was soon being qualified. Strathern had identified a ‘partible’ dividual in Melanesia; others were to discover ‘permeable’ ones in South India.Footnote 28 An investigation of Inka personhood revealed that neither ‘dividual’ nor ‘individual’ quite summed up how Inka persons were understood within their own culture.Footnote 29 The most penetrating critique however came from within Melanesian scholarship. Edward LiPuma observed that if all ‘Westerners’ were entirely individuals, and all Melanesians dividuals, then mutual understanding – and so the kind of cultural translation that ethnography represents – would be impossible.

A Westerner can have access to Melanesian intentionality, and a Melanesian can have access to Western forms of intentionality because both operate in terms of dividual and individual aspects of personhood.Footnote 30

The divide (Table 1) is then not so much ontological as ideological: Western political (democratic) and economic (capitalist) norms emphasise individualism; Maring (Melanesian) norms emphasise kinship, descent and dividualism. Within anthropology (and prehistory) the neat dichotomy represented by Table 1 has now completely broken down under the weight of explanation the concept has been required to bear. Dividual and individual are now seen as axes of personhood, rather than opposed essences. The latest article from Fowler makes this abundantly clear:

Personhood is not only relational and processual, it is multi-modal. More than one mode of relations, more than one mode of personhood, is likely to be present in any cultural context and one person may move between different modes of personhood as they engage in different activities.Footnote 31

Fowler's insight has direct bearing on how we should view the Amasis Painter (see below). What however neither prehistorians nor anthropologists can bring themselves to do is to acknowledge that this debate is not new. A ‘personhood’ debate had already taken place within classical studies several decades before it took off in anthropology.

The personhood debate: classics and classical archaeology

In 1949 E. R. Dodds, then Regius Professor of Greek at Oxford, gave the Sather lectures at Berkeley. He began with the subject of Agamemnon's apology – or rather non-apology – for his taking Briseis away from Achilles (the act that sets the whole plot of the Iliad – the ‘wrath of Achilles’ – going).Footnote 32 Agamemnon (Hom. Il. 19.86–9) does not really accept responsibility (ἐγὼ δ’οὐκ αἴτιός εἰμι) for his actions as an individual (in the Euro-American sense), but attributes his mistaken decision to a madness, an ἄτη sent down by Zeus. Now one might think here that ‘Homer’ is blackening Agamemnon's name – that he is a man and king uniquely incapable of accepting responsibility, as we understand the term. But Dodds shows that this is not the case – the point about this apology is not simply that it is made but also that it is accepted, and is couched in terms well understood by the moral community of Homer's heroes. Dodds then uses this example to build up a picture of the way that Homeric heroes talk about themselves – or rather don't. For they do not talk about themselves as whole, bounded entities so much as about their parts (liver, heart and so forth). A good example of this façon de parler is Odysseus’ reflection when, on his arrival on Ithaca, he is thinking back to his time in Polyphemus’ cave: τέτλαθι δή, κραδίη; καὶ κύντερον ἄλλο ποτ’ ἔτλης (‘bear up, heart, you've suffered much worse’, Hom. Od. 20.18).

Dodd's approach to Homeric heroes chimed in with that of another classical scholar writing at about the same time, Bruno Snell. Snell argued that early Greeks of the eight and seventh centuries BC did not have the concept of a body as a totality. It was rather an assemblage of parts, and one where the actual parts of the body (arms, legs) are no more essential what that body wears (helmets, spears, Dipylon shields). To support his point Snell drew attention to the way in which Geometric artists drew persons – particularly warriors:

Dass der substantielle Körper des Menschen nicht als Einheit sondern als Vielheit begriffen wird, lehren uns auch die Menschendarstellungen der frühgriechischen Kunst. Den organisch einheitlichen Körper, der in der Spannung von Tragendem und Lastendem, im Gegensatz von Stand- und Spielbein und in der Abhängigkeit aller Teile von solchem Kontrapost sichtbar wird, stellt erst die klassische Kunst des 5. Jhdt. dar. Vorher ist der Körper wirklich nur aufgebaut durch die Addition einzelner Teile, wie das vor allem Gerhard Krahmer gezeigt hat.Footnote 33

An example of such Geometric representations might be the early eighth-century Middle Geometric ii krater ‘from Attica’ in New York (Figure 3).Footnote 34 Here the persons – the warriors—and their shields are indistinguishable – shields are both shields and parts of bodies. The warrior is an assemblage of parts (helmet, shield, legs, pairs of javelin and spears).

Figure 3. Middle Geometric ii krater from Attica, now in New York (Metropolitan Museum of Art 34.11.2, Fletcher Fund 1934). Source Wikimedia Commons.

Now of course these ideas never found wide acceptance within classical studies. Art historians have found fault with Snell, who they believe mistook a series of iconographic conventions for an underlying notion of ‘the person’. Geometric artists may have been sophisticated in many ways but they were not interested in depicting people with any degree of anatomical accuracy.Footnote 35 Other classical scholars were equally critical of Dodds, albeit for different reasons. The philosopher Bernard Williams argued against them both. For Williams these iconographic (and verbal) conceptions of the body (Snell) or ways of talking about personal responsibility (Dodds) did not imply a radical ‘ontological’ difference between our ‘modern’ selves and the ancient Greeks.Footnote 36 While ancient Greek and modern senses of personhood might be different, and while ancient Greeks in general (and Homer's heroes in particular) might lack the words for ‘moral’ and ‘responsibility’, this does not imply that they could not act either morally or responsibly. Williams' critique of Snell is not so much of his notions of cultural difference between ourselves and archaic Greeks as of his ‘progressivism’ – that is, of Snell's moral teleology.Footnote 37 Though he may not have intended it however, Williams' critique did lead to a neglect of both Dodd's and Snell's ideas. It came to be widely believed that current classical scholarship had transcended them.Footnote 38

The debate about personhood in anthropology and prehistory has however inadvertently revived interest in both Dodds and Snell and aligned their insights with those of anthropologists. Gell's notion of distributed personhood seems particularly appropriate for understanding Homeric exchange – an antique Cypriot amphoroid krater such as the one from the ‘heröon’ at Lefkandi Toumba may have had a similar history of entanglements as the famous silver krater Achilles sets up as a prize in the funeral games of Patroclus (Hom. Il. 23.740–9).Footnote 39 Moreover, if there is something to Snell's interpretation of the ‘Dipylon shield’, then our relative ease in defining the ‘Dipylon workshop’ contrasts with the relative difficulty in defining the several hands that made up the ‘artistic personality’ of the Dipylon Master.Footnote 40 In Sapirstein's terms recent scholarship has broken up the ‘Dipylon Master’ into a series of hands, the opposite of what people imagine the epistemological imperative of attribution to be.

Outside of the study of Geometric pottery however the personhood debate (either within classics, or prehistory, or anthropology) has had very little apparent effect on how the practice of attribution was understood within classical archaeology. Scholars who have participated in the debate about Beazley's legacy disagree about much: whether Beazley owed his method primarily to Giovanni MorelliFootnote 41 or to Paul Hartwig;Footnote 42 whether or not attribution can be extended into prehistory;Footnote 43 and how ‘fuzzy’ the boundaries of artistic personalities might be.Footnote 44 But all appear to agree that artistic personalities (at least those responsible for painting Athenian black- and red-figure vases) were – straightforwardly and unambiguously – individuals. That this assumption is no longer warranted is part of the central argument of this paper.

To re-assure some of my readers: I am not proposing to break down the corpus of vases attributed to the Amasis Painter into a group of ‘hands’ working in the ‘Amasis workshop’. What follows is an iconographic study (where iconography is seen as an aspect of a painter's style), informed by these debates about both personhood and agency.

Iconography and agency in the Amasis Painter I: eros and the hare

Let us return to that distinctive sixth-century ‘artistic personality’, the Amasis Painter, and his iconography. I take it that a painter defined by style (‘tricks of draughtsmanship’) may also have a distinct iconography. If we can talk about the iconography of Titian, or Rembrandt, or El Greco, we can surely also talk about the iconography of Lydos, Exekias and the Amasis Painter. Let me reiterate the two main points of my argument. First, that Beazley's description of this painter allows an ‘ontological’ reading which sees him no less as dividual as individual (in Strathern's terms). In other words, the painter's personhood might be ‘multi-modal’ (to use Fowler's phrase). Second, that if we interpret this artistic personality in terms of ‘anthropological’ personhood we also have to imagine a more ‘anthropological’ understanding of his material entanglements, that is, the agency of the objects within the universe of the painter's iconography. Here I want to concentrate on two aspects of this: the hunting and giving of hares; and the handing over of shields (the so-called ‘arming scenes’).

Hares occur quite frequently on vases by the Amasis Painter. On an oenochoe in London a youth carries both a hare and a fox that he has hunted;Footnote 45 on an amphora in Geneva a youth carries a (hunted) hare.Footnote 46 But what have these hares been hunted for? A clue is provided on the paired images on either side of an unusually large drinking vessel, a cup-kotyle now in the Louvre:Footnote 47 on one side a man with a beard offers a cock to a young girl; on the other another bearded male offers a hare to a beardless youth. That hares had erotic overtones within the ancient world is suggested by a rather strange, late passage in Philostratus the Elder (Imag. 1.6.5): hares are the only animal that can be sacrificed to Aphrodite. That a hare is moreover a love gift appropriate for men (but not women) is confirmed by another image from an amphora in the Louvre where a younger man offers a hare to his older male lover.Footnote 48 That hares could even be gifts for (male) gods is underscored by perhaps the most celebrated of these representations, that to be found on the neck amphora in the Cabinet des Médailles, where two maenads, one holding a hare by his ears, the other grasping a small deer, offer both creatures to their patron deity, Dionysus (Figure 4).Footnote 49

Figure 4. Paris, Cabinet des Médailles 222 (from Vulci); Karouzou (Reference Karouzou1956) 31 no. 22; Beazley, ABV 152 no. 25, (Reference Beazley, von Bothmer and Moore1986) 52–3. Two maenads offer Dionysus a hare and a deer. Image courtesy Cabinet des Médailles, Paris.

Hares are wild creatures. To be given as gifts they first have to be hunted (Xen. Cyn. 2–8); in Greece then, as in Crete now, hares were hunted with dogs. Scenes of dogs chasing a hare occur on a number of Protocorinthian vases (such as the Chigi olpe, or the Macmillan aryballos). Such scenes are found on the lower registers of these vases beneath other scenes of fighting and hunting.Footnote 50 Hare, deer and agrimi (the Cretan wild goat) are represented on Archaic bronze plaques from the sanctuary of Hermes and Aphrodite at Kato Symi in Crete. On these plaques young men exchange love gifts, frequently of wild animals one of them has hunted. The excavator Angeliki Lebessi interprets these images as part of a much longer initiation process by which young men became citizens of a Cretan polis through institutions such as the andreion.Footnote 51 The gesture on one plaque (A.10) is almost identical to those found on the Louvre amphora and the one in the Cabinet des Médailles (Figure 4). Recent investigation of the civic centres of Cretan poleis (at Azoria, Dreros and Praisos) has revealed an unusually high proportion of hare bones, wild animals consumed in a communal civic and ritual setting.Footnote 52 In Crete then hares were much more than simply food – that is sustenance; their procurement and consumption were part of an exchange between men that strengthened civic bonds.

Hares are thus not only associated with homoerotic love but also with performative masculinity (since it takes both skill and effort to catch one). They are therefore invested with a particular kind of agency. Here we return to the link between personhood and agency advocated by Gell. Just as in the example of Melanesian exchange the pig being exchanged isn't just a pig but rather the nexus in a whole set of social relationships, so the hare found in these images is not just a hare but is entangled within a whole set of distinct relationships: in Athens the formation of bonds between erastēs and eromenos; and in Crete the formation of new generations of citizens within political communities. These apparently simple gestures contain multitudes.

Iconography and agency in the Amasis Painter ii: heroes and shields

A similar point can be made with the Amasis Painter's use of shields. As Boardman notes, this painter is very keen on shields, depicting both elaborately heroic Dipylon/Boeotian examples and more standard round hoplite shields.Footnote 53 The best known are two arming scenes, one (on an amphora in Berlin) apparently shows Thetis giving a Boeotian shield to Achilles,Footnote 54 another, a neck amphora from Orvieto in Boston, shows Thetis giving Achilles a round hoplite shieldFootnote 55 (Figure 5; Figure 6). Beazley is, interestingly, ambivalent in his interpretation of these depictions – while he is sure that the image depicted on the neck amphora from Orvieto represents the original gift of arms to Achilles (Figure 5), he is not so sure about the amphora once in Berlin.Footnote 56 I am convinced however that both represent the same event – the original gift of divine arms made by Hephaistos and given by Thetis to her son Achilles at Phthia in Thessaly, a tale that later came to form part of the Kypria (a part of the epic cycle that precedes the Iliad). My reasons are several; they relate both to the agency of the shield and the iconography of the scene.

Figure 5. Neck amphora: Boston 01.8027 (from Orvieto); Karouzou (Reference Karouzou1956) 31 no. 23 (also 19–20) and Plates 32, 34 and 35.1 and 2; Beazley, ABV 152 no. 27. Thetis gives Achilles his arms. Image courtesy Museum of Fine Arts, Boston.

Figure 6. Detail of image in Figure 5 (Boston 01.8027), showing crest of helmet and ram's head cheek piece. Image courtesy Museum of Fine Arts, Boston.

First agency: of all the artefacts known in archaic and early classical Greece one could argue that it is shields that are invested with most agency. ‘Come back with your shield or on it’, say Spartan mothers to their sons;Footnote 57 shields are, after helmets, the preferred form of dedicatory offering commemorating military victories. The Phokians, who defeated the invading Thessalians at some point in the late sixth century BC, dedicated 2,000 of their captured shields at sanctuary of Apollo at Abai (Hdt. 8.27; Paus. 10.1.3–9); the Athenians pointedly displayed the shields they had captured at Pylos from the Spartans prominently in the Painted Stoa.Footnote 58 Shields are also depicted within shields – as on a number of Argive shield bands dedicated at Olympia (Figure 7).Footnote 59 And of all the shields we know of from literature, the one that Thetis gives to Achilles (the original arms) at Phthia in Thessaly is the one invested with most agency. The shield is originally a divine gift; then Achilles lends it to Patroclus; then Hector seizes it from Patroclus' dead body; and then finally (after obtaining his second suit of armour) Achilles recovers the original shield by killing Hector (Hom. Il. 17.194–7, 18.84–5, 22.322–3). From one point of view therefore, this armour, this shield can be viewed as one of the major dramatis personae of the Iliad itself.Footnote 60

Figure 7. Bol (Reference Bol1989) 67 and 153 no. cxiv H.40 no.γ (Olympia inventory B8150). This shows Thetis giving Achilles a Boeotian shield. Image redrawn by Kirsty Harding.

Is then the shield that the Amasis Painter depicts in Figure 5 this ‘original’ shield? Discussions of the iconography of arming scenes have now become a dense thicket of scholarly controversy. In his interpretation of the ‘arming’ scenes painted by the Amasis Painter Beazley was following Friis Johansen's comprehensive study.Footnote 61 Beazley neatly summarises his argument:

Johansen shews that the arms in the early vases (not the late archaic) are not the ‘replacement’ set of the 18th book, but the original set, Hephaistos-made like the other, brought the hero by Thetis and her sisters before he left Phthia for Troy.Footnote 62

A point in favour of this interpretation is a scene on a plate by Lydos, which shows Peleus, Achilles, Thetis and Neoptolemus all present in the ‘arming of Achilles’. This cannot be the scene recounted in the Iliad – ‘that the presence of Neoptolemos is a proleptic sin against the legendary tradition, did presumably not worry the artist’.Footnote 63 Friis Johansen's arguments were elaborated by Dietrich von Bothmer. Von Bothmer developed his interpretation through a close study of a vase by the Camtar Painter now in Boston (Figure 8).Footnote 64 This vase seems to have established the standard iconography for arming scenes.Footnote 65 Here Achilles receives a particularly elaborate Boeotian shield from Thetis, and the rest of his divine armour from a succession of named (and inscribed) nymphs: Kymatothea (for the cuirass); Neoptolome (for the greaves); and Panope (for the Corinthian helm).Footnote 66 This interpretation has been criticised by both Lowenstam and Giuliani.Footnote 67 Lowenstam provides a point-for-point rebuttal of Friis Johansen's (and von Bothmer's) original argument to the effect that these scenes must reflect the first arming at Phthia rather than the second before Troy. Lowenstam's view is that no particular mythological event – neither the first arming, nor the one in book 19 of the Iliad – can positively be identified on any of these generic arming scenes. Giuliani goes further, and doubts that there even was a widely known tale of an original gift of arms by Thetis to Achilles in Phthia.Footnote 68 The only gift of divine armour from Thetis to Achilles was the one that takes place in the Iliad (19.12–13).

Figure 8. Amphora by the Camtar Painter, in Boston (Museum of Fine Arts); Boston 21.21; Beazley, ABV 84 no. 3. Image courtesy Museum of Fine Arts, Boston.

Giuliani's interpretation is, in my view, not sustainable. First, if the only identifiable arming scene found on the iconography of archaic vases is the one that stems from this brief passage in the Iliad, then the scenes themselves are unaccountably rich in the kind of detail that points in a very different direction. In this passage in the Iliad (19.12–13) the only spectators present (apart from Thetis and Achilles) are the Myrmidons. The Nereids (Il. 18.39–49) who had accompanied Thetis when she visited the grieving Achilles are not mentioned; nor is their presence at all implied. Second, the ‘shield of Achilles’ (Il. 18.478–608) must have been a round shield, and not the Boeotian shield depicted in Figure 8. The inscriptions on the vase by the Camtar Painter rule out any of the other three arming scenes in the Iliad – those of Paris, Agamemnon and Patroclus.Footnote 69 Indeed, what Giuliani's cursory exclusion of the Phthia hypothesis ignoresFootnote 70 is the way in which the agency of objects, both within the Iliad itself and within the iconography of heroic scenes on sixth-century Athenian vases, look beyond the immediate episode depicted and reference earlier and later episodes in the Trojan War Cycle. This applies to the spear taken from the original ‘arms of Achilles’ that Patroclus cannot wield, a spear made of ash from Mt Pelion (Πηλιάδα μελίην), which Cheiron gave to Peleus and then Peleus to Achilles (Il. 16.140–4) and whose size and weight make it a particularly deadly instrument (φονον ἔμμεναι ἡρώεσσιν) in single combat. The way the spear is described thus foreshadows Achilles slaying of Hector. These original weapons and arms of Achilles act as major dramatis personae within the Iliad itself (see above). Their origin and their agency are thus key to the Cycle as a whole. It is then not surprising that the original gift of arms by Thetis to Achilles is something that very much preoccupied early vase painters interested not in the Iliad in particular but the Trojan War Cycle in general.Footnote 71

In brief, sixth-century vase painting is full of Friis Johansen's ‘proleptic sins’. The problem of how Bild relates to Lied is not ‘how do painters evoke Homer’; Homer's Lied was not at this point some fixed text but rather a corpus of oral tale cycles which were only taking definitive shape around the middle of the sixth century BC (that is, the time of the Amasis Painter).Footnote 72 The problem vase painters faced was how to make a scene look, like the ‘objects with agency’ within the Iliad, both back to what had gone before and forward to how the story ends.Footnote 73

Giuliani's argument of course is that Bild does not depend directly on Lied. Artists faced different problems from poets, and in the move from Geometric to black-figure they began with the generic (an arming scene) and added features (including inscriptions) that lead to the particular (the arming of Achilles). In Giuliani's evolutionary account, Figure 7 precedes Figure 8; the first is a generic scene, the second the ‘arming of Achilles’. But if this is so then almost all the ‘myth’ scenes we find on Archaic metalwork (including all of those found on so-called ‘Argive’ shields) must be generic – both Bol and Kunze must have been wrong in all of their interpretations of the scenes that appear on the interior bands of these round hoplite shields.Footnote 74 The Argive depictions within shields are, if anything, later in date than the Camtar Painter (they are more or less contemporary with the Amasis Painter). In this light is it not more likely that the images on the shields are derived from more complex images on vases, rather than the other way around?

If so, we should reverse Giuliani's interpretation. It is the developed iconography on Figure 8 which is ‘abbreviated’ on the image of the ‘shield within a shield’ on the Argive shield band (Figure 7), and it is this ‘abbreviated’ iconography which the Amasis Painter would be working with (or against) on other scenes involving the ‘arms of Achilles’. On another amphora in Boston from Orvieto, two warriors (Achilles and Hector) are seen battling, one holding a Boeotian shield with a scene of two rams butting each other;Footnote 75 a third in New YorkFootnote 76 shows two arming scenes. On one side of the vase in New York a man gives a warrior (Achilles? – not named) who is putting on his greaves a metal ring, while another holds his (round, hoplite) shield; on the other a man again puts on his greaves, a female figure (Thetis?) holds an aryballos, while a man behind her holds another (round, hoplite) shield. In all these scenes the Amasis Painter is playing with the ancient (and modern) viewers’ expectations of what is heroic (round shield or Boeotian shield), underpinned by a wide understanding of the continued agency of the ‘arms of Achilles’.Footnote 77

It is then the agency of the shield (the original divine armour) that is reflected in its iconography (rather than the other way around). Let us return to the Boston vase in Figure 5, and look again at the agency and iconography of the objects within it. This ensemble of images comprises the following: a curious blazon on the centre of the round shield that Thetis gives to Achilles (and which cannot correspond to the shield described in book 18 of the Iliad); the odd ‘serpent support’ for the crest of the helm; and the image of the ram's head on the cheek piece of the same helm (Figure 5). All these elements look forward to the full ‘object biography’ of these arms, arms which act as agents, as dramatis personae within the wider narrative of the Trojan War Cycle. These details then are supplied in the service of a prospective narrative – hints of what is to come. Once we take all this into account we must recognise that the Amasis Painter, in his serial committal of multiple narrative ‘proleptic sins’, is fully the equal of his great contemporary, Exekias.

A provisional conclusion

This article began with a consideration of personal style. Style has often been taken to betray the presence of an individual – not merely an identifiable person, but also someone whose personality infuses his (or her) work. It went on to consider how the uncertainties in defining ‘artistic personalities’ from a mass of hands raises questions which are as much ontological as epistemological. If personal style is considered ‘ontologically’ that in turn raises issues of personhood, and this paper considers how parallel debates about personhood have developed, first in classics and then in anthropology (and prehistory). It suggested that we are not really forced to choose whether ancient Greeks (and ancient Greek vase painters) were more dividual than individual, since personhood could be ‘multi-modal’. While the practice of signing works is (rightly) seen as an indication of ancient Greek ‘individualism’,Footnote 78 the entanglements between persons and things evident equally in Homeric narratives and in archaic iconography are more consistent with a notion of the ‘dividual’ or ‘distributed person’ (in Gell's sense).

The Amasis Painter is central to all these debates. His visual narratives are caught up with the wider agency of both persons and things. We could speak of the Trojan War Cycle as an entangled narrative,Footnote 79 played out in poetry and the visual arts, that links people and objects together. Just as agency is invested in objects, so personhood is entangled with things. In this sense both personhood and agency are not only ‘multi-modal’ (in Fowler's terms) but also ‘polythetic’ (in David Clarke's). This brings us back to the wider definitions of style mentioned at the beginning of this paper. Style also operates at a macro-level and has traditionally been linked to ethnicity – La Tène style with the Celts, and Classical style with the Greeks. But this notion of style also depends on a more general theory of – or assumptions about – culture in general. Insofar as style, at a macro-scale, is an integral part of culture (and culture too is, in part, a particular configuration of material entanglements), it too is polythetic. As David Clarke saw (with great perspicacity) fifty years ago,Footnote 80 culture is polythetic all the way down (Figure 9).

Figure 9. The ‘culture brick’, ‘radial contour’ and ‘polythetic set’ models of archaeological cultures (prepared by K. Harding, after Clarke (Reference Clarke1978) 264 Figure 67).

Footnotes

This article stems from a talk I gave in Oxford on the 1 May 2017, in a seminar series on ‘style’. I would like to thank Peter Stewart for inviting me, largely it seems on the basis that I once (long ago) produced a book with the word ‘style’ in the title. Peter assured me that not having thought much about style for a very long time was not an impediment to my being there. At the very least I can say that my talk had a cast of very distinguished Oxonians, who have (at various points) commented on either style or personhood. In revising my paper for publication, I have taken advantage of advice from Laurence Totelin (on hares), of the comments of Robin Osborne, Anthony Snodgrass and the two anonymous CCJ referees on earlier drafts, and I am also (as ever) grateful to Kirsty Harding for preparing some fine illustrations.

1 Neer (Reference Neer2010) 6–11.

2 See Gell (Reference Gell1998a) 155–9.

3 As in Jacobsthal (Reference Jacobsthal1944).

4 Defining Greek ‘style’ and art is less straightforward than one might think, especially in relation to ‘the Orient’. See now the excellent discussion by Martin (Reference Martin2017).

5 Cook (Reference Cook1972) 41–160 remains fundamental to these definitions.

6 Beazley, ABV x (emphasis added).

7 Beazley (Reference Beazley1911), (Reference Beazley1922). See now Padgett (Reference Padgett2017). The debate on the role of attribution and connoisseurship within classical archaeology is now a developed one. Milestones in this discussion include Kurtz (Reference Kurtz1985); Beard (Reference Beard, Rasmussen and Spivey1991); Neer (Reference Neer1997); Whitley (Reference Whitley1997); Lynch (Reference Lynch and Nevett2017).

8 Beazley, ABV 150–8; Karouzou (Reference Karouzou1956). Of the ten signed vases, five are signed ΑΜΑΣΙΣ ΜΕΠΟΙΕΣΕΝ and three ΑΜΑΣΙΣ ΕΠΟΙΕΣΕΝ; on two others the full inscription is missing. Sapirstein (Reference Sapirstein2013, 501; Reference Sapirstein and Oakley2014) reckons that the potter Amasis and the painter must be one and the same (see also Hurwit (Reference Hurwit2015) 79 and 180 n. 31). The whole question of the ‘foreign’ connotations of the name Amasis (Boardman (Reference Boardman1987)) is not germane to my argument.

9 Beazley (ABV 150–8 and 697–8) lists ninety-two vases; Karouzou (Reference Karouzou1956) only seventy-eight (including one krater (no. 29) not in Beazley's lists). Sapirstein (Reference Sapirstein2013; Reference Sapirstein and Oakley2014) gives a maximum of 145 vases which can be attributed to the Amasis Painter, of which five are uncertain.

10 This at least seems to be the view of most of the contributions to True (Reference True1987), i.e. Mertens (Reference Mertens1987); Moore (Reference Moore1987); Robertson (Reference Robertson1987); Stewart (Reference Stewart1987).

11 Boardman (Reference Boardman1975) 54; general discussion on Amasis and the Amasis Painter: ibid., 52 and 54–6.

12 This is the cup in Boston 10.651 (Karouzou (Reference Karouzou1956) 36 no. 66; Beazley, ABV 157 no. 86 δύο ἄνδρες δέφομενοι). On Dionysiac scenes see Carpenter (Reference Carpenter1986); Heinrichs (Reference Heinrichs1987). Carpenter makes it clear that we would probably not have a developed iconography of satyrs without the Amasis Painter.

13 Beazley, ABV 145 nos. 13 and 18 respectively; on narrative compression see Moore (Reference Moore1987).

14 That is, when we try to look ‘underneath’ the apparent straightforward nature of attribution and explore the implicit theoretical assumptions underlying Beazley's practice. Αttempts to do this (e.g. Whitley (Reference Whitley1997)) have often be misconstrued as being ‘anti-Beazley’ (as in Oakley (Reference Oakley1998), (Reference Oakley2009)). For useful recent discussions see Arrington Reference Arrington and Padgett2017; Lynch Reference Lynch and Nevett2017.

15 Beazley (Reference Beazley, von Bothmer and Moore1986) 52 (emphasis added; see ibid., 52–7 for more on the ‘style’ of the Amasis Painter).

16 Beazley, ABV x (‘Instructions for use’).

17 Sapirstein (Reference Sapirstein2013), (Reference Sapirstein and Oakley2014); contra Cook (Reference Cook1972) 270–8. Arrington's (Reference Arrington and Padgett2017, 30–2) concern with ‘fuzzy edges’ does not, in my view, undermine the main thrust of Sapirstein's argument.

18 Beazley, ABV 170. To clarify, each of the three groups (ABV 170–3) has at least one cup signed ΣΑΚΟΝΙΔΕΣΕΓΡΑΦΣΕΜΕ, though none of them share the same ‘style’. Sakonides was a ‘Little Master’ cup painter (Beazley (Reference Beazley1932)).

19 Shanks (Reference Shanks1996) 35. Of the painters defined by Dunbabin and Robertson (Reference Dunbabin and Robertson1953) only the Sacrifice Painter and the Macmillan Painter (Amyx's Chigi Painter) can be seen to have ‘authored’ more than ten vases – putting them in Sapirstein's category of ‘hands’ rather than artistic personalities. The same is true of the numerous ‘groups’ of Corinthian painters isolated by Amyx (Reference Amyx1988, 757–61). Few if any would pass Sapirstein's test for an ‘artistic personality’. See now remarks by Arrington (Reference Arrington and Padgett2017, 30–2 and 35–6).

20 Beazley, ABV 94–106. There are groups within the Tyrrhenian Group, but only one painter (the Goltyr Painter), in Sapirstein's terms more a ‘hand’ than an ‘artistic personality’. Beazley (Reference Beazley, von Bothmer and Moore1986) does not even deign to mention the group in his general account of the development of black figure.

21 I should clarify that I do not quite mean ‘ontology’ in Descola's (Reference Descola and Lloyd2013) sense (as one of his four ontologies). But I do mean it in a related sense that does not correspond to its general use in philosophy – as a statement about a particular (cultural and historical) relationship between persons and things.

22 Strathern (Reference Strathern1988) 13.

23 Gell (Reference Gell and Gell1998b). For the application Gell's notion of agency in classical archaeology and art history see the papers in Osborne and Tanner (Reference Osborne and Tanner2007).

24 Gell (Reference Gell1998a) 96–154 (‘the distributed person’), building on Thomas (Reference Thomas1991).

26 Piggott (Reference Piggott1962).

29 Wilkinson (Reference Wilkinson2013).

31 Fowler (Reference Fowler2016) 408 (emphasis original).

32 Dodds (Reference Dodds1951) 1–27.

33 Snell (Reference Snell1975) 17; cf. Snell (Reference Snell1953) (English translation of 1st edn). Vernant (Reference Vernant1989, 11–12) seems to follow Snell to some extent, without acknowledging his source, in his discussion of ancient conceptions of the body.

34 These early kraters are discussed in Whitley (Reference Whitley1991) 137–43 (see also ibid., Plate 27).

35 There is a kind of proxy debate about personhood in the ‘Dipylon shield’ controversy: are these shields real shields? Or are they meant to connote some notion of a generalised heroic past? For this see Snodgrass (Reference Snodgrass1980); Boardman (Reference Boardman and Moon1983); Hurwit (Reference Hurwit1985); Whitley (Reference Whitley1991) 45–53; on the continued relevance of Snell to this debate see Haug (Reference Haug2012) 19.

36 Williams (Reference Williams1993). Williams' interest of course was primarily in moral philosophy and in ethics, not in personhood as such. His arguments are principally directed against thinkers such as MacIntyre (Reference MacIntyre1985), who argued that modernity is morally incoherent. This raises still broader issues (see Latour (Reference Latour and Porter1993)) which cannot be pursued here.

37 So one could read Williams (Reference Williams1993) as allowing for the possibility of ‘moral’ and ‘responsible’ dividuals, or allowing for the exploration of different kinds of responsibility within different ‘ontologies’ (sensu Descola (Reference Descola and Lloyd2013)). Vernant (Reference Vernant1983, 343–74) is equally critical of Snell's teleology.

38 Finkelberg (Reference Finkelberg2012) represents a recent consensus.

39 Cf. Hom. Od. 4. 611–55, the krater given by Menelaus to Telemachus. All these are discussed in Grethlein (Reference Grethlein2008); Whitley (Reference Whitley2013). For entangled objects see Thomas (Reference Thomas1991); for material entanglements Hodder (Reference Hodder2011).

40 For the ‘Dipylon Master’ as an ‘artistic personality’ see Nottbohm (Reference Nottbohm1943). For the ‘hands’ in the Dipylon workshop see Coldstream (Reference Coldstream1968) 29–32; Coulié (Reference Coulié2015). It seems more and more likely that this workshop is a collection of hands, rather than one dominated by a single ‘artistic personality’. Similar observations have been made about the Hirschfeld workshop, where an ‘artistic personality’ has become a brand (Vlachou (Reference Vlachou2015b)). For more on personhood and Geometric pottery see Whitley (Reference Whitley2015) 109–11.

41 As argued by Kurtz (Reference Kurtz1985). Beard (Reference Beard, Rasmussen and Spivey1991), Neer (Reference Neer1997) and Whitley (Reference Whitley1997) largely accept Kurtz's view. For a comprehensive overview see Rouet (Reference Rouet2001).

42 Williams (Reference Williams1996).

43 As argued by Morris (Reference Morris1993).

45 London: BM B 52 from Rhodes; Karouzou (Reference Karouzou1956) 32 no. 30 and Plate 15; Beazley, ABV 153 no. 31.

46 Geneva: i.4; Karouzou (Reference Karouzou1956) 30 no. 6 and Plates 4 and 5; Beazley, ABV 150 no. 8.

47 Louvre: A 479 from Rhodes (Camirus); Karouzou (Reference Karouzou1956) 37 no. 71 and Plates 12.2, 13 and 14; Beazley, ABV 156 no. 80. Beazley rather mysteriously calls the hare a ‘panther cub’, which it is not. All these erotic scenes are discussed by Schnapp (Reference Schnapp1997) 239–41.

48 Amphora type B, Louvre F26; Karouzou (Reference Karouzou1956) 30 no. 17; Beazley, ABV 150 no. 5.

49 Paris, Cabinet des Médailles 222 (from Vulci); Karouzou (Reference Karouzou1956) 31 no. 22 (see also discussion pp. 18–19) and Plates 31 and 32; Beazley, ABV 152 no. 25, (1986) 52–3 and Plate 51. Beazley calls the hare (and the deer) ‘pet animals’; that maenads would have pets might surprise anyone who knows anything of Euripides’ Bacchae. This vessel has many inscriptions: ΔΙΟΝΥΣΟΣ; ΑΜΑΣΙΣ ΜΕΠΟΙΕΣΕΝ; ΑΘΕΝΑΙΑ ΠΟΣΕΙΔΟΝ; ΑΜΑΣΙΣ ΜΕΠΟΙΕΣΕΝ.

50 Chigi vase: Hurwit (Reference Hurwit2002); Macmillan aryballos and other vases: Amyx (Reference Amyx1988) 368–72, Plate 11. Similar scenes are to be found on a number of Attic black-figure vases that predate the Amasis Painter; see Schnapp (Reference Schnapp1997) 212–18. On ‘performative masculinity’ on Protocorinthian perfume flasks see Shanks (Reference Shanks1999) 73–168.

51 Lebessi (Reference Lebessi1985) 26 no. A10, Plates 6 and 48. Lebessi goes on (ibid., 188–98) to discuss how these plaques relate to the rituals associated with the formation of the Cretan ‘troops’ based on the well-known passage in Strabo (10.4.20–1), who in turn paraphrases Ephoros (FGrH 10.149). It is not necessary (contra Koehl (Reference Koehl1986)) to infer that such rituals have ‘Minoan roots’; see Whitley and Madgwick (Reference Whitley, Madgwick, Blok, van den Eijnde and Strootman2018).

53 Boardman (Reference Boardman1975) 54–6; on Archaic shields generally see Snodgrass (Reference Snodgrass1964) 58–68.

54 Amphora type A: Berlin 3210; Karouzou (Reference Karouzou1956) 29 no. 2 and Plates 25 and 26 (also discussed pp. 14–16 and note 3); Beazley, ABV 151 no. 21. This amphora is now lost.

55 Neck amphora: Boston 01.8027 (from Orvieto); Karouzou (Reference Karouzou1956) 31 no. 23 (also 19–20) and Plates 32, 34 and 35.1 and 2; Beazley, ABV 152 no. 27.

57 This tradition is, of course, very late; it is only recorded in Ps.-Plutarch, Moralia (Apophthegmata Laconica) 241. F. no. 16. I would argue that it is however implied by Thucydides' account (especially 4.36.3; 4.37.2–38.1; 4.40.1) of the Sphakteria episode and his incredulity that Spartans had actually given up their arms (and in particular their shields).

58 Paus. 1.15.4. The inscription on the one surviving shield could not be more pointed: ΑΘΗΝΑΙΟΙ ΑΠΟ ΛΑΚΕΔΑΙΜ[ΟΝ]ΙΟΝ ΕΚ [ΠΥ]ΛΟ ‘The Athenians [took these] from the Lacedaemonians from Pylos’; on the discovery of this shield, see Shear (Reference Shear1937); on the agency of its inscription, Whitley (Reference Whitley and Stambolidis2006) 229–32.

59 Bol (Reference Bol1989) 67 and 153 no. cxiv H.40 no.γ (Olympia inventory B8150); Kunze (Reference Kunze1950) 171. Whether this image is simply an arming scene or something more has been the subject of much debate, see below.

60 Grethlein (Reference Grethlein2008); Whitley (Reference Whitley2013) 399.

61 Friis Johansen (Reference Friis Johansen and Christensen1967) 92–113, original Danish version reviewed by Beazley (Reference Beazley1934).

62 Beazley (Reference Beazley1934) 84–5.

63 Friis Johansen (Reference Friis Johansen and Christensen1967) 113. The vase (Athens NM 507; Beazley, ABV 112 no. 56) is illustrated ibid., 109 Figure 35.

64 Boston 21.21; Beazley, ABV 84 no. 3; Friis Johansen (Reference Friis Johansen and Christensen1967) 93–6 Figures 23–5.

65 See discussion by von Bothmer (Reference von Bothmer1949); Beazley (Reference Beazley, von Bothmer and Moore1986) 53–5; Lissarrague (Reference Lissarrague1990) 43–7; Giuliani (Reference Giuliani and O'Donnell2013) 107 Figure 22.

66 Kymothoe and Panope (but not Neoptoleme) occur in the list of thirty-three Nereids who accompany Thetis when she visits the grieving Achilles (Hom. Il. 18. 39–49). No Nereids however seem to be present when Thetis hands over the second set of arms (Hom. Il. 19.12–13). See discussion by von Bothmer (Reference von Bothmer1949).

68 Giuliani (Reference Giuliani and O'Donnell2013) 287 n. 70.

69 Il. 3.328–38 (Paris); 11.15–55 (Agamemnon); 16.130–54 (Patroclus). As Armstrong (Reference Armstrong1958) argues, these scenes are successively more elaborate and refer back (and forward) to each other.

70 Quite apart, that is, from any discussion of the plate by Lydos (see above).

71 Snodgrass (Reference Snodgrass1998), esp. 144–5. Snodgrass, unlike Giuliani, also considers the (highly ambiguous) evidence for the ‘Chest of Kypselos’ on this point (Snodgrass (Reference Snodgrass2006) 422–42). I myself do not find the alternative explanation for the apparent absence of specific imagery relating to the Iliad in particular (rather than the Trojan War Cycle in general) put forward by Osborne (Reference Osborne2018) at all convincing.

72 Burkert (Reference Burkert1987); Nagy (Reference Nagy1990), (Reference Nagy and Langdon1997); for further implications see Burgess (Reference Burgess2009).

73 See the classic account of Snodgrass (Reference Snodgrass2006) 381–406.

74 Bol (Reference Bol1989) 63–76; Kunze (Reference Kunze1950) 139–73. See discussion by Giuliani (Reference Giuliani and O'Donnell2013) 105 Figure 21.

75 Neck amphora: Boston 01.8026 from Orvieto; Karouzou (Reference Karouzou1956) 32 no. 24 (discussed 20–1) and Plates 35.3, 36 and 37; Beazley, ABV 152 no. 26. Signed twice.

76 Amphora type B: New York 06.1021.69; Karouzou Reference Karouzou1956, 29 no. 4 & plates 1 and 2.1; Beazley ABV 150 no. 2.

77 This of course raises the question of who constituted the original ancient audience – the ancient viewers – of these vases. I cannot agree here with the view, widely held (e.g. Neer (Reference Neer2002), criticised in Whitley (Reference Whitley2018) 63–70), that this ancient audience was primarily an Athenian one. Twenty-two of the vases listed in Beazley, ABV 150–8 come from Etruscan contexts, fifteen from elsewhere in the Mediterranean, and only eleven from Attica. Prominent among the proveniences of those larger vases (such as amphoras) with the more elaborate ‘mythological’ scenes are the sites of Orvieto and Vulci. The distribution of the Amasis Painter's wares is thus very similar to that of the Berlin Painter's (Saunders (Reference Saunders2017)).

78 As in Hurwit (Reference Hurwit2015), esp. 3–30 and 147–56.

79 In view of the shift in scholarly consensus that Nagy (Reference Nagy1990; Reference Nagy and Langdon1997) represents it seems best to talk about the Trojan War Cycle (understood as a loose collection of tales, which vary according to oral performance) rather than ‘Homer’ (understood as the sole author of two fixed and definitive texts).

80 Clarke (Reference Clarke1978) 245–362 (1st edn 1968).

References

Works cited

ABV = Beazley (1956)Google Scholar
Amyx, D. A. (1988) Corinthian vase painting of the Archaic period, 3 vols., Berkeley and Los Angeles.Google Scholar
Armstrong, J. I. (1958) ‘The arming motif in the Iliad’, AJPh 79, 337–54.Google Scholar
Arrington, N. (2017) ‘Connoisseurship, vases, and Greek art and archaeology’, in. Padgett, J. M. (ed.), The Berlin Painter and his world: Athenian vase painting in the early fifth century BC, New Haven and London, 2139.Google Scholar
Beard, M. (1991) ‘Adopting an approach ii’, in Rasmussen, T. and Spivey, N. (eds.), Looking at Greek vases, Cambridge, 1235.Google Scholar
Beazley, J. D. (1911) ‘The Master of the Berlin amphora’, JHS 31, 276–95.Google Scholar
Beazley, J. D. (1922) ‘Citharoedus’, JHS 42, 7098.Google Scholar
Beazley, J. D. (1932) ‘Little Master cups’, JHS 52, 167204.Google Scholar
Beazley, J. D. (1934) Review of ‘Iliaden i tidlig graesk Kunst’ by K. Friis Johansen, JHS 54, 84–5.Google Scholar
Beazley, J. D. (1956) Athenian black figure vase painters, Oxford. (= ABV)Google Scholar
Beazley, J. D. (1986) The development of Attic black-figure, rev. edn by von Bothmer, D. and Moore, M. B., Berkeley and Los Angeles.Google Scholar
Boardman, J. (1975) Athenian black figure vases, London.Google Scholar
Boardman, J. (1983) ‘Symbol and story in Geometric art’, in Moon, W. G. (ed.), Ancient Greek art and iconography, Madison, 1536.Google Scholar
Boardman, J. (1987) ‘Amasis: the implications of his name’, in True (1987) 141–52.Google Scholar
Bol, P. C. (1989) Argivische Schilde, Olympische Forschungen xvii, Berlin and New York.Google Scholar
Brück, J. (2004) ‘Material metaphors: the relational construction of identity in Early Bronze Age burials in Ireland and Britain’, Journal of Social Archaeology 4, 307–33.Google Scholar
Burgess, J. S. (2009) The death and afterlife of Achilles, Baltimore.Google Scholar
Burkert, W. (1987) ‘The making of Homer in the sixth century BC: rhapsodes versus Stesichoros’, in True (1987) 43–62.Google Scholar
Busby, C. (1997) ‘Permeable and partible persons: a comparative analysis of gender and body in South India and Melanesia’, Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 3, 261–78.Google Scholar
Carpenter, T. H. (1986) Dionysian imagery in Archaic Greek art: its development in black-figure vase painting, Oxford.Google Scholar
Clarke, D. L. (1978) Analytical archaeology, 2nd edn, London.Google Scholar
Coldstream, J. N. (1968) Greek Geometric pottery: a survey of ten local styles and their chronology, London.Google Scholar
Cook, R. M. (1972) Greek painted pottery, 2nd edn, London.Google Scholar
Coulié, A. (2015) ‘L'atelier du Dipylon: style, typologie et chronologie relative’, in Vlachou (2015a) 37–47.Google Scholar
Descola, P. (2013) Beyond nature and culture, tr. Lloyd, J., Chicago and London.Google Scholar
Dodds, E. R. (1951) The Greeks and the irrational, Sather Classical Lectures 25, Berkeley and Los Angeles.Google Scholar
Dunbabin, T. J. and Robertson, M. (1953) ‘Some Protocorinthian vase painters’, ABSA 48, 172–81.Google Scholar
Finkelberg, M. (2012) ‘E.R. Dodds and the irrational: Agamemnon's apology re-visited’, SCI 31, 101–8.Google Scholar
Fowler, C. (2004) The archaeology of personhood: an anthropological approach, London and New York.Google Scholar
Fowler, C. (2016) ‘Relational personhood revisited’, CArchJ 26, 397412.Google Scholar
Friis Johansen, K. (1967) The Iliad in early Greek art, tr. Christensen, L., Copenhagen.Google Scholar
Gell, A. (1998a). Art and agency: an anthropological theory, Oxford.Google Scholar
Gell, A. (1998b) ‘Strathernograms, or the semiotics of mixed metaphors’, in Gell, A., The art of anthropology: essays and diagrams, London, 2975.Google Scholar
Giuliani, L. (2013) Image and myth: a history of pictorial narration in Greek art, tr. O'Donnell, J., Chicago.Google Scholar
Grethlein, J. (2008) ‘Memory and material objects in the Iliad and the Odyssey’, JHS 128, 2751.Google Scholar
Haug, A. (2012) Die Entdeckung des Körpers: Körper- und Rollenbbilder im Athen des 8. und 7. Jahrhunderts v. Chr., Image and Context 10, Berlin and Boston.Google Scholar
Heinrichs, A. (1987) ‘Myth visualized: Dionysos and his circle in sixth-century Attic vase painting’, in True (1987) 92–124.Google Scholar
Hodder, I. (2011) ‘Human-thing entanglement: towards an integrated archaeological perspective’, Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 17, 154–77.Google Scholar
Hurwit, J. M. (1985) ‘The Dipylon shield once more’, ClAnt 4, 121–6.Google Scholar
Hurwit, J. M. (2002) ‘Reading the Chigi Vase’, Hesperia 71, 122.Google Scholar
Hurwit, J. M. (2015) Artists and signatures in ancient Greece, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Jacobsthal, P. (1944) Early Celtic art, Oxford.Google Scholar
Karouzou, S. (1956) The Amasis Painter, Oxford.Google Scholar
Koehl, R. B. (1986) ‘The chieftain cup and a Minoan rite of passage’, JHS 106, 99110.Google Scholar
Kunze, E. (1950) Archaische Schildbänder, Olympische Forschungen ii, Berlin.Google Scholar
Kurtz, D. (1985) ‘Beazley and the connoisseurship of Greek vases’, in Greek vases in the J. Paul Getty Museum 2, Malibu, CA, 237–50.Google Scholar
Latour, B. (1993) We have never been modern, tr. Porter, C., London and Hemel Hempstead.Google Scholar
Lebessi, A. (1985) Το ιερό του Ερμή και της Αφροδίτης στη Σύμη Βιάννου i: χάλκινα κρητικά τορεύματα, Βιβλιοθήκη της εν Αθήναις Αρχαιολογικής Εταιρείας 102, Athens.Google Scholar
LiPuma, E. (1998) ‘Modernity and forms of personhood in Melanesia’, in Lambek, M. and Strathern, A. (eds.), Bodies and persons: comparative perspectives from Africa and Melanesia, Cambridge, 5379.Google Scholar
Lissarrague, F. (1990) L'autre guerrier: archers, peltastes, cavaliers dans l'imagerie Attique, Images à l'Appui 3, Paris and Rome.Google Scholar
Lowenstam, S. (1993) ‘The arming of Achilleus on early Greek vases’, ClAnt 12, 199218.Google Scholar
Lynch, K. (2017) ‘Reception, intention and Attic vases’, in Nevett, L. C. (ed.), Theoretical approaches to the archaeology of ancient Greece, Ann Arbor, MI, 124–42.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, A. (1985) After virtue: a study in moral theory, 2nd edn, London.Google Scholar
Martin, S. R. (2017). The art of contact: comparative approaches to Greek and Phoenician art, Philadelphia.Google Scholar
Mertens, J. M. (1987) ‘The Amasis Painter: artist and tradition’, in True (1987) 167–83.Google Scholar
Moore, M. B. (1987) ‘The Amasis Painter and Exekias: approaches to narrative’, in True (1987) 153–67.Google Scholar
Morris, C. (1993) ‘Hands up for the individual! The role of attribution studies in Aegean prehistory’, CArchJ 3, 4166.Google Scholar
Nagy, G. (1990) Pindar's Homer: the lyric possession of an epic past, Baltimore and London.Google Scholar
Nagy, G. (1997) ‘The Shield of Achilles: ends of the Iliad and beginnings of the polis’, in Langdon, S., New light on a dark age: exploring the culture of Geometric Greece, Columbia, MO and London, 194207.Google Scholar
Neer, R. (1997) ‘Beazley and the language of connoisseurship’, Hephaistos 15, 730.Google Scholar
Neer, R. (2002) Style and politics in Athenian vase painting: the craft of democracy 530–460 BCE, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Neer, R. (2010) The emergence of the Classical style in Greek sculpture, Chicago and London.Google Scholar
Nevett, L. and Whitley, J. (eds.) (2018) An age of experiment: classical archaeology transformed, McDonald Institute Monographs, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Nottbohm, G. (1943) ‘Der Meister der grossen Dipylon-Amphora in Athen’, JDAI 58, 131.Google Scholar
Oakley, J. (1998) ‘Why study a Greek vase painter? A response to Whitley's “Beazley as theorist”’, Antiquity 72, 209–13.Google Scholar
Oakley, J. (2009) ‘Greek vase painting’, AJA 113, 599627.Google Scholar
Osborne, R. (2018) ‘Homeric imagery’, in Nevett and Whitley (2018) 75–85.Google Scholar
Osborne, R. and Tanner, J. (eds.) (2007) Art's agency and art history, Oxford and Malden, MA.Google Scholar
Padgett, J. M. (ed.) (2017) The Berlin Painter and his world: Athenian vase painting in the early fifth century BC, New Haven and London.Google Scholar
Piggott, S. (1962) The West Kennet Long Barrow: excavations 1955–56, London.Google Scholar
Robertson, M. (1987) ‘The state of Attic vase-painting in the mid-sixth century’, in True (1987) 13–28.Google Scholar
Rouet, P. (2001) Approaches to the study of Greek vases: Beazley and Pottier, Oxford.Google Scholar
Sapirstein, P. (2013) ‘Painters, potters and the scale of the Attic vase-painting industry’, AJA 117, 493510.Google Scholar
Sapirstein, P. (2014) ‘Demographics and productivity in the ancient Athenian pottery industry’, in Oakley, J. H. (ed.), Athenian potters and painters. Volume iii, Oxford and Philadelphia, 175–86.Google Scholar
Saunders, D. (2017) ‘The distribution of the Berlin Painter's vases’, in Padgett (2017) 107–31.Google Scholar
Schnapp, A. (1997) Le chasseur et la cité: chasse et érotique en Grèce ancienne, Paris.Google Scholar
Shanks, M. (1996) Classical archaeology of Greece: experiences of the discipline, London.Google Scholar
Shanks, M. (1999) Art and the Greek city state: an interpretive archaeology, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Shear, T. L. (1937) ‘A Spartan shield from Pylos’, AEph 1937, 140–43.Google Scholar
Snell, B. (1953) The discovery of the mind: the Greek origins of European thought, Oxford.Google Scholar
Snell, B. (1975) Die Entdeckung des Geistes: Studien zur Entstehung des europäischen Denkens bei den Griechen, 5th edn, Göttingen.Google Scholar
Snodgrass, A. M. (1964) Early Greek armour and weapons, Edinburgh.Google Scholar
Snodgrass, A. M. (1980) ‘Towards the interpretation of the Geometric figure scenes’, MDAI(A) 95, 51–8.Google Scholar
Snodgrass, A. M. (1998) Homer and the artists: text and picture in early Greek art, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Snodgrass, A. M. (2006) Archaeology and the emergence of Greece: collected papers on early Greece and related topics, Edinburgh.Google Scholar
Stewart, A. F. (1987) ‘Narrative, genre and realism in the work of the Amasis Painter’, in True (1987) 29–42.Google Scholar
Strathern, M. (1988) The gender of the gift: problems with women and problems with society in Melanesia, Berkeley and Los Angeles.Google Scholar
Thomas, N. (1991) Entangled objects: exchange, material culture and colonialism in the Pacific, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
True, M. (ed.) (1987) Papers on the Amasis Painter and his world, Malibu, CA.Google Scholar
Vernant, J. P. (1983) Myth and thought among the Greeks, London.Google Scholar
Vernant, J. P. (1989) L'individu, la mort, l'amour: soi-même et l'autre en Grèce ancienne, Paris.Google Scholar
Vlachou, V. (ed.) (2015a) Pots, workshops and Early Iron Age society: function and role of ceramics in early Greece, Brussels.Google Scholar
Vlachou, V. (2015b) ‘From pots to workshops: the Hirschfeld Painter and the Late Geometric i context of Attic pottery production’, in Vlachou (2015a) 49–74.Google Scholar
von Bothmer, D. (1949) ‘The arming of Achilles’, Bulletin of the Museum of Fine Arts (Boston) 47, 8490.Google Scholar
Whitley, J. (1991) Style and society in Dark Age Greece: the changing face of a pre-literate society, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Whitley, J. (1997) ‘Beazley as theorist’, Antiquity 71, 40–7.Google Scholar
Whitley, J. (2006) ‘Classical art and human agency: a tale of two objects in fifth-century Greece’, in Stambolidis, N. C. (ed.), ΓΕΝΕΘΛΙΟΝ: Αναμνηστικός τόμος για την συμπλήρωση είκοσι χρόνων λειτουργίας του Μουσείου Κυκλαδικής Τεχνής, Athens, 227–36.Google Scholar
Whitley, J. (2013) ‘Homer's entangled objects: narrative, agency and personhood in and out of Iron Age texts’, CArchJ 23, 395416.Google Scholar
Whitley, J. (2015) ‘Agency, personhood and the belly-handled amphora: exchange and society in the ninth-century Aegean’, in Vlachou (2015a) 107–26.Google Scholar
Whitley, J. (2018) ‘The krater and the pithos: two kinds of agency’, in Nevett and Whitley (2018) 59–73.Google Scholar
Whitley, J. and Madgwick, R. (2018) ‘Consuming the wild: more thoughts on the andreion’, in Blok, J., van den Eijnde, F. and Strootman, R. (eds.), Feasting and polis institutions, Memnosyne Supplement 414, Leiden, 125–48.Google Scholar
Wilkinson, D. (2013) ‘The emperor's new body: personhood, ontology and the Inka sovereign’, CArchJ 23, 417–32.Google Scholar
Williams, B. (1993) Shame and necessity, Sather Classical Lectures 57, Berkeley and Los Angeles.Google Scholar
Williams, D. (1996) ‘Refiguring Attic Red Figure: a review article’, RA 1996 (2), 227–52.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. Venn diagram showing the Amasis Painter's relationship to the Heidelberg Painter and Kleitias (after Beazley (1986) 52). Image prepared by Kirsty Harding. ‘He has much in common with the Heidelberg Painter, surpassing him, however, in all respects; a good deal also of Kleitias, if not the finest part, has passed into him – lightness, elegance, and precise technique.’

Figure 1

Figure 2. Venn diagram illustrating Beazley's use of the terms ‘style’, manner, kinship and so forth (after Beazley, ABV x). Image prepared by Kirsty Harding. ‘My attributions have often been misquoted. I may perhaps be allowed to point out that I make a distinction between the vase by a painter and a vase in his manner; and that “manner”, “imitation”, “following”, “school”, “circle”, “group”, “influence”, “kinship” are not, in my vocabulary, synonyms.’

Figure 2

Table 1 The ontological divide between prehistory/ethnography and the study of historical societies.

Figure 3

Figure 3. Middle Geometric ii krater from Attica, now in New York (Metropolitan Museum of Art 34.11.2, Fletcher Fund 1934). Source Wikimedia Commons.

Figure 4

Figure 4. Paris, Cabinet des Médailles 222 (from Vulci); Karouzou (1956) 31 no. 22; Beazley, ABV 152 no. 25, (1986) 52–3. Two maenads offer Dionysus a hare and a deer. Image courtesy Cabinet des Médailles, Paris.

Figure 5

Figure 5. Neck amphora: Boston 01.8027 (from Orvieto); Karouzou (1956) 31 no. 23 (also 19–20) and Plates 32, 34 and 35.1 and 2; Beazley, ABV 152 no. 27. Thetis gives Achilles his arms. Image courtesy Museum of Fine Arts, Boston.

Figure 6

Figure 6. Detail of image in Figure 5 (Boston 01.8027), showing crest of helmet and ram's head cheek piece. Image courtesy Museum of Fine Arts, Boston.

Figure 7

Figure 7. Bol (1989) 67 and 153 no. cxiv H.40 no.γ (Olympia inventory B8150). This shows Thetis giving Achilles a Boeotian shield. Image redrawn by Kirsty Harding.

Figure 8

Figure 8. Amphora by the Camtar Painter, in Boston (Museum of Fine Arts); Boston 21.21; Beazley, ABV 84 no. 3. Image courtesy Museum of Fine Arts, Boston.

Figure 9

Figure 9. The ‘culture brick’, ‘radial contour’ and ‘polythetic set’ models of archaeological cultures (prepared by K. Harding, after Clarke (1978) 264 Figure 67).