Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-lvwk9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-24T23:55:33.927Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

LARGE CARDINALS AS PRINCIPLES OF STRUCTURAL REFLECTION

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 January 2023

JOAN BAGARIA*
Affiliation:
INSTITUCIÓ CATALANA DE RECERCA I ESTUDIS AVANÇATS (ICREA) BARCELONA, CATALONIA, SPAIN and DEPARTAMENT DE MATEMÀTIQUES I INFORMÀTICA UNIVERSITAT DE BARCELONA GRAN VIA DE LES CORTS CATALANES, 585 08007 BARCELONA, CATALONIA, SPAIN E-mail: joan.bagaria@icrea.cat E-mail: bagaria@ub.edu
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

After discussing the limitations inherent to all set-theoretic reflection principles akin to those studied by A. Lévy et. al. in the 1960s, we introduce new principles of reflection based on the general notion of Structural Reflection and argue that they are in strong agreement with the conception of reflection implicit in Cantor’s original idea of the unknowability of the Absolute, which was subsequently developed in the works of Ackermann, Lévy, Gödel, Reinhardt, and others. We then present a comprehensive survey of results showing that different forms of the new principle of Structural Reflection are equivalent to well-known large cardinal axioms covering all regions of the large-cardinal hierarchy, thereby justifying the naturalness of the latter.

Type
Articles
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

In the framework of Zermelo–Fraenkel (ZF) set theoryFootnote 1 the universe V of all sets is usually represented as a stratified cumulative hierarchy of sets indexed by the ordinal numbers. Namely, $V=\bigcup _{\alpha \in OR}V_{\alpha }$ , where

$$ \begin{align*} &V_0=\varnothing, \\ &V_{\alpha +1}=\mathcal{P}(V_{\alpha}),\; \mbox{ namely the set of all subsets of }V_{\alpha}, \mbox{ and} \\ &V_{\lambda}=\bigcup_{\alpha <\lambda}V_{\alpha},\mbox{ if } \lambda \mbox{ is a limit ordinal.} \end{align*} $$

This view of the set-theoretic universe justifies a posteriori the ZF axioms. For not only all ZF axioms are true in V, but they are also necessary to build V. Indeed, the axioms of Extensionality, Pairing, Union, Power-Set, and Separation are used to define the set-theoretic operation given by

$$ \begin{align*}G(x)=\bigcup \{ \mathcal{P}(y): \exists z (\langle z,y\rangle \in x)\}. \end{align*} $$

The axiom of Replacement is then needed to prove by transfinite recursion that the operation V on the ordinals given by $V(\alpha ) = G(V\restriction \alpha )$ is well-defined and unique. Then $V(\alpha )=V_{\alpha }$ is as defined above. The two remaining ZF axioms are easily justified: the axiom of Infinity leads the ordinal sequence into the transfinite, and is the essence of set theory, for its negation (namely, ZFC minus Infinity plus the negation of Infinity) yields a theory mutually interpretable with Peano Arithmetic; and the axiom of Regularity simply says, in the presence of the other ZF axioms, that there are no more sets beyond those in V.

In the context of ZFC (ZF plus the Axiom of Choice), the Axiom of Choice is clearly true in V, although it is not necessary to build V.

In ZF, or ZFC, other representations of V as a cumulative hierarchy are possible. By “a cumulative hierarchy” we mean a union of transitive sets $X_{\alpha }$ , defined by transfinite recursion on a club, i.e., closed and unbounded, class C of ordinals $\alpha $ , such that:

$$ \begin{align*} \alpha &\leq \beta \mbox{ implies }X_{\alpha}\subseteq X_{\beta}, \\ X_{\lambda} &= \bigcup_{\alpha <\lambda}X_{\alpha},\mbox{ if } \lambda \ \mbox{is a limit point of } C, \mbox{and} \\ V&=\bigcup_{\alpha\in C}X_{\alpha}. \end{align*} $$

For example, let $H_{\kappa }$ , for $\kappa $ an infinite cardinal, be the set of all sets whose transitive closure has cardinality less than $\kappa $ . Then the $H_{\kappa }$ also form a cumulative hierarchy indexed by the club class $C\!ARD$ of infinite cardinal numbers. (Note however that to prove $\bigcup _{\kappa \in C\!ARD}H_{\kappa } =V$ one needs the Axiom of Choice to guarantee that every (transitive) set has a cardinality, and therefore every set belongs to some $H_{\kappa }$ .) Nevertheless, all representations of V as a cumulative hierarchy are essentially the same, in the following sense: Suppose $V=\bigcup _{\alpha \in C}X_{\alpha }$ and $V=\bigcup _{\alpha \in D}Y_{\alpha }$ are two cumulative hierarchies, where C and D are club classes of ordinals. Then there is a club class of ordinals $E\subseteq C\cap D$ such that $X_{\alpha }=Y_{\alpha }$ , for all $\alpha \in E$ .

Every representation of V as a cumulative hierarchy is subject to the reflection phenomenon, namely the fact that every sentence of the first-order language of set theory that holds in V holds already at some stage $V_{\alpha }$ of the hierarchy. Indeed, the Principle of Reflection of Montague and Lévy [Reference Lévy20], provable in $ZF$ , asserts that every formula of the first-order language of set theory true in V holds in some $V_{\alpha }$ . In fact, for every formula $\varphi (x_1,\ldots ,x_n)$ of the language of set theory, ZF proves that there exists an ordinal $\alpha $ such that for every $a_1,\ldots ,a_n\in V_{\alpha }$ ,

$$ \begin{align*}\varphi (a_1,\ldots ,a_n)\quad \mbox{ if and only if }\quad V_{\alpha}\models \varphi(a_1,\ldots ,a_n).\end{align*} $$

Even more is true: for each natural number n, there is a definable club proper class $C^{(n)}$ of ordinals such that ZF proves that for every $\kappa \in C^{(n)}$ , every $\Sigma _n$ formula $\varphi (x_1,\ldots ,x_n)$ , and every $a_1,\ldots ,a_n\in V_{\kappa }$ ,

$$ \begin{align*}\varphi (a_1,\ldots ,a_n)\quad \mbox{ if and only if }\quad V_{\kappa}\models \varphi(a_1,\ldots ,a_n).\end{align*} $$

That is, $(V_{\kappa },\in )$ is a $\Sigma _n$ -elementary substructure of $(V,\in )$ , henceforth written as , or simply as .

The import of the Principle of Reflection is highlighted by the result of Lévy [Reference Lévy20] showing that the ZF axioms of Extensionality, Separation, and Regularity, together with the principle of Complete Reflection (CR), imply ZF. The CR principle is the schema asserting that for every formula $\varphi (x_1,\ldots ,x_n)$ of the language of set theory there exists a transitive set A closed under subsets (i.e., all subsets of elements of A belong to A) such that for every $a_1,\ldots ,a_n\in A$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \varphi (a_1,\ldots ,a_n)\leftrightarrow A\models \varphi(a_1,\ldots ,a_n). \end{align*} $$

Since the $V_{\alpha }$ are transitive and closed under subsets, this shows that the reflection phenomenon, as expressed by the CR principle or the Reflection Theorem (given the existence of the $V_{\alpha }$ ’s), is not only deeply ingrained in the ZF axioms, but it captures the main content of ZF.

In the series of papers [Reference Lévy20Reference Lévy22] Lévy considers stronger principles of reflection, formulated as axiom schemata, and he shows them equivalent to the existence of inaccessible, Mahlo, and Hyper-Mahlo cardinals. The unifying idea behind such principles is clearly stated by Lévy at the beginning of [Reference Lévy21]:

If we start with the idea of the impossibility of distinguishing, by specific means, the universe from partial universes we shall be led to the following axiom schemata, listed according to increasing strength. These axiom schemata will be called principles of reflection since they state the existence of standard models (by models we shall mean, for the time being, models whose universes are sets) which reflect in some sense the state of the universe.

This idea of reflection, namely the impossibility of distinguishing the universe from its partial universes (such as the $V_{\alpha }$ ), is also implicit in earlier work of Ackermann [Reference Ackermann1], but it is Lévy who demonstrates how it can be used to find new natural theories strengthening ZF. Indeed, in his review of Levy’s article [Reference Lévy22], Feferman [Reference Feferman12] writes:

The author’s earlier work demonstrated very well that the diversity of known set-theories could be viewed with more uniformity in the light of various reflection principles, and that these also provided a natural way to “manufacture” new theories. The present paper can only be regarded as a beginning of a systematic attempt to compare the results.

More recently, it has been argued by many authors that any intrinsic justification of new set-theoretic axioms, beyond ZF, and in particular the axioms of large cardinals, should be based on stronger forms of Lévy’s reflection principles. In the next section we shall see some of these arguments, as well as the limitations, clearly exposed by Koellner [Reference Koellner16], inherent to all reflection principles akin to those studied by Lévy. In Section 2 we will introduce new principles of reflection based on what we call Structural Reflection and will argue that they are in strong agreement with the notion of reflection implicit in the original idea of Cantor’s of the unknowability of the absolute, which was subsequently developed in the works of Ackermann, Lévy, Gödel, Reinhardt, and others. The rest of the paper, starting with Section 3, will present a series of results showing that different forms of the new principles of Structural Reflection are equivalent to well-known large cardinal axioms covering all regions of the large-cardinal hierarchy, thereby justifying the naturalness of the latter.Footnote 2

1 Set-Theoretic axioms as reflection principles

Cantor [Reference Cantor11, p. 205, note 2] emphasizes the unknowability of the transfinite sequence of all ordinal numbers, which he thinks of as an “appropriate symbol of the absolute”:

The absolute can only be acknowledged, but never known, not even approximately known.

This principle of the unknowability of the absolute, which in Cantor’s work seems to have only a metaphysical (non-mathematical) meaning (see [Reference Jané13]), resurfaces again in the 1950s in the work of Ackermann and Lévy, taking the mathematical form of a principle of reflection. Thus, in Ackermann’s set theory—in fact, a theory of classes—which is formulated in the first-order language of set theory with an additional constant symbol for the class V of all sets, the idea of reflection is expressed in the form of an axiom schema of comprehension:

Ackermann’s Reflection: Let $\varphi (x, z_1, \ldots , z_n)$ be a formula which does not contain the constant symbol V.

Then for every $\vec {a}=a_1,\ldots ,a_n \in V$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \forall x (\varphi (x, \vec{a}) \rightarrow x \in V) \rightarrow \exists y (y \in V \land \forall x (x \in y \leftrightarrow \varphi (x, \vec{a}))). \end{align*} $$

A consequence of Ackermann’s Reflection is that no formula can define V, or the class OR of all ordinal numbers, and is therefore in agreement with Cantor’s principle of the unknowability of the absolute. However, Ackermann’s set theory (with Foundation) was shown by Lévy [Reference Lévy19] and Reinhardt [Reference Reinhardt30] to be essentially equivalent to ZF, in the sense that both theories are equiconsistent and prove the same theorems about sets. Thus Ackermann’s set theory did not provide any real advantage with respect to the simpler and intuitively clearer ZF axioms, and so it was eventually forgotten.

Later on, in the context of the wealth of independence results in set theory that were obtained starting in the mid-1960s thanks to the forcing technique, and as a result of the subsequent need for the identification of new set-theoretic axioms, Gödel (as quoted by Wang [Reference Wang36]), places Ackermann’s principle (stated in a Cantorian, non-mathematical form) as the main source for new set-theoretic axioms beyond ZFC:

All the principles for setting up the axioms of set theory should be reducible to a form of Ackermann’s principle: The Absolute is unknowable. The strength of this principle increases as we get stronger and stronger systems of set theory. The other principles are only heuristic principles. Hence, the central principle is the reflection principle, which presumably will be understood better as our experience increases.

Thus, according to Gödel, the fundamental guiding principle in setting up new axioms of set theory is the unknowability of the absolute, and so any new axiom should be based on such principle. Gödel’s program consisted, therefore, in formulating stronger and stronger systems of set theory by adding to the base theory, which presumably could be taken as ZFC, new principles akin to Ackermann’s.

So the question is how should one understand and formulate the idea of reflection embodied in Ackermann’s principle. Some light is provided by Gödel in the following quote from [Reference Wang36, p. 285], where he asserts that the undefinability of V should be the source of all axioms of infinity, i.e., all large-cardinal axioms.

Generally I believe that, in the last analysis, every axiom of infinity should be derivable from the (extremely plausible) principle that V is undefinable, where definability is to be taken in [a] more and more generalized and idealized sense.

One possible interpretation of Gödel’s principle of the undefinability of V is as an unrestricted version of the Montague–Lévy Principle of Reflection. Namely: every formula, with parameters, in any formal language with the membership relation, that holds in V, must also hold in some $V_{\alpha }$ . This has been indeed the usual way to interpret Gödel’s view of reflection as a justification for the axioms of large cardinals. This is made explicit in Koellner [Reference Koellner16, p. 208], where he identifies reflection principles with generalized forms of the Montague–Lévy Principle of Reflection. Namely,

Reflection principles aim to articulate the informal idea that the height of the universe is “absolute infinite” and hence cannot be “characterized from below”. These principles assert that any statement true in V is true in some smaller $V_{\alpha }$ .

Moreover, he explicitly interprets Gödel’s view of reflection as a source of large cardinals in this way [Reference Koellner16, p. 208]:

Since the most natural way to assert that V is undefinable is via reflection principles and since to assert this in a “more and more generalized and idealized sense” is to move to languages of higher-order with higher-order parameters, Gödel is (arguably) espousing the view that higher-order reflection principles imply all large cardinal axioms.

This kind of reflection, namely generalised forms of the Principle of Reflection of Lévy and Montague allowing for the reflection of second-order formulas, has been used to justify weak large-cardinal axioms, such as the existence of inaccessible, Mahlo, or even weakly compact cardinals. Let us see briefly some examples to illustrate how the arguments work.

The Principle of Reflection also holds with proper classes as additional predicates. Namely, for every (definable, with set parameters) proper class A, and every n, there is an ordinal $\alpha $ such that

Thus, if we interpret second-order quantifiers over V as ranging only over definable classes, then for each n, the following second-order sentence, call it $\varphi _n$ , is true in V:

Now, applying reflection, $\varphi _n$ must reflect to some $V_{\kappa }$ . The second-order universal quantifier in $\varphi _n$ is now interpreted in $V_{\kappa }$ , hence ranging over all subsets of $V_{\kappa }$ , which are now available in $V_{\kappa +1}$ . So we have that for each subset A of $V_{\kappa }$ , there is some $\alpha <\kappa $ such that

If this is so, and even just for $n=1$ , then $\kappa $ must be an inaccessible cardinal, and this property actually characterises inaccessible cardinals [Reference Lévy20]. Thus the existence of an inaccessible cardinal follows rather easily from the reflection of the single

sentence $\varphi _1$ to some $V_{\kappa }$ .

Further, the following stronger form of reflection is provable in ZFC (as a schema): if C is a definable club proper class of ordinals, then for every proper class A, and every n, there is a club proper class of $\alpha $ in C such that

Hence, for each n, the following

sentence, with C as a second-order parameter, holds in V (again, interpreting the universal second-order quantifier as ranging over definable classes):

Applying reflection, there is $\kappa $ such that for every subset A of $V_{\kappa }$ there are unboundedly many $\alpha $ in $C\cap \kappa $ such that

But since C is a club, $\kappa \in C$ , and so (in the case of $n\geq 1$ ) $\kappa $ is an inaccessible cardinal in C. Now consider the following

sentence, which we have just shown (using

reflection) to hold in V:

$$ \begin{align*} \forall C(C\mbox{ is a club subclass of ordinals}\rightarrow \exists \kappa (\kappa \mbox{ inaccessible}\wedge \kappa \in C)). \end{align*} $$

Any cardinal that reflects the

sentence consisting of the conjunction of $\varphi _1$ above with the last displayed sentence is an inaccessible cardinal $\lambda $ with the property that every club subset of $\lambda $ contains an inaccessible cardinal, i.e., $\lambda $ is a Mahlo cardinal.

Furthermore, if we are willing to assume that all

sentences with second-order parameters reflect, we may as well reflect this property of V. So, consider the following

sentence, which says that V reflects all

sentences with parameters,

If $V_{\kappa }$ reflects this sentence, then $\kappa $ is a

-indescribable cardinal, i.e., a weakly compact cardinal (see [Reference Jech14]). Similar arguments, applied to sentences of order n, but only allowing first-order and second-order parameters, yield the existence of $\Sigma ^m_n$ and

indescribable cardinals.

While the arguments just given may seem reasonable, or even natural, we do not think they provide a justification for the existence of the large cardinals obtained in that way. The problem is that the relevant second-order statements are true in V only when interpreting second-order variables as ranging over definable classes, yet when the statements are reflected to some $V_{\alpha }$ the second-order variables are reinterpreted as ranging over the full power-set of $V_{\alpha }$ . It is precisely this transition from definable classes to the full power-set that yields the large-cardinal strength. Thus, the fundamental objection is that second-order reflection from V to some $V_{\alpha }$ , or to some set, is always problematic because so is unrestricted second-order quantification over V, as the full power-class of V is not available.

Nevertheless, even if one is willing to accept the existence of cardinals $\kappa $ that reflect n-th-order sentences, with parameters of order greater than $2$ , one does not obtain large cardinals much stronger than the indescribable ones. Indeed, to start with, and as first noted in [Reference Reinhardt29], one cannot even have reflection for sentences with unrestricted third-order parameters. For suppose, towards a contradiction, that $\kappa $ is a cardinal that reflects such sentences. Let A be the collection $\{ V_{\alpha }:\alpha <\kappa \}$ taken as a third-order parameter, i.e., as a subset of $\mathcal {P}(V_{\kappa })$ . Then the sentence

$$ \begin{align*}\forall X\exists x(X\in A\to X=x),\end{align*} $$

where X is a second-order variable and x is first-order, asserts that every element of A is a set. The sentence is clearly true in $(V_{\kappa },\in ,A)$ , but false in any $(V_{\alpha },\in ,A\cap \mathcal {P}(V_{\alpha }))$ with $\alpha <\kappa $ , because $V_{\alpha }$ belongs to $A\cap \mathcal {P}(V_{\alpha })$ but is not an element of $V_{\alpha }$ .

One possible way around the problem of second-order reflection with third-order parameters is to allow such parameters, or even higher-order parameters, but to restrict the kind of sentences to be reflected. This is the approach taken by Tait [Reference Tait35]. He considers the class $\Gamma ^{(2)}$ of formulas which, in normal form, have all universal quantifiers restricted to first-order and second-order variables and the only atomic formulas allowed to appear negated are either those of first order or of the form $x\in X$ , where x is a variable of first order and X a variable of second order. Tait shows that reflection at some $V_{\kappa }$ for the class of $\Gamma ^{(2)}$ sentences, allowing parameters of arbitrarily high finite order, implies that $\kappa $ is an ineffable cardinal (see [Reference Koellner16]), and that $V_{\kappa }$ reflects all such sentences whenever $\kappa $ is a measurable cardinal. A sharper upper bound on the consistency strength of this kind of reflection is given by Koellner [Reference Koellner16, Theorem 9]. He shows that below the first $\omega $ -Erdös cardinal, denoted by $\kappa (\omega )$ , there exists a cardinal $\kappa $ such that $V_{\kappa }$ reflects all $\Gamma ^{(2)}$ formulas. The existence of $\kappa (\omega )$ is, however, a rather mild large-cardinal assumption, since it is compatible with $V=L$ .

At this point, the question is thus whether reflection can consistently hold (modulo large cardinals) for a wider class of sentences. But Koellner [Reference Koellner16], building on some results of Tait, shows that no $V_{\kappa }$ can reflect the class of formulas of the form $\forall X\exists Y \varphi (X,Y, Z)$ , where X is of third-order, Y is of any finite order, Z is of fourth order, and $\varphi $ has only first-order quantifiers and its only negated atomic subformulas are either of first order or of the form $x\in X$ , where x is of first order and X is of second order. Other kinds of restrictions on the class of sentences to be reflected are possible (see [Reference McCallum26] for the consistency of some forms of reflection slightly stronger than Tait’s $\Gamma ^{(2)}$ ), but Koellner [Reference Koellner16] convincingly shows that the existence of a cardinal $\kappa $ such that $V_{\kappa }$ reflects any reasonable expansion of the class of sentences $\Gamma ^{(2)}$ , with parameters of order greater than 2, either follows from the existence of $\kappa (\omega )$ or is outright inconsistent.

These results seem to put an end to the program of providing an intrinsic Footnote 3 justification of large-cardinal axioms, even for axioms as strong as the existence of $\kappa (\omega )$ , by showing that their existence follows from strong higher-order reflection properties holding at some $V_{\kappa }$ . In particular, the program cannot even provide justification for the existence of measurable cardinals. Thus, the conclusion is that if one understands reflection principles as asserting that some sentences (even of higher order, and with parameters) that hold in V must hold in some $V_{\alpha }$ , then reflection principles cannot be used to justify the existence of large cardinals up to or beyond $\kappa (\omega )$ . Moreover, as we already emphasized, a more fundamental problem with the use of higher-order reflection principles is that either second-order quantification over V is interpreted as ranging over definable classes, in which case second-order reflection does not yield any large cardinals unless one makes the dubious jump from definable classes to the full power-set, or is ill-defined, as the full power-class of V does not exist.

1.1 A remark on the undefinability of V

Before we go on to propose a new kind of reflection principle, let us take a pause to consider another possible interpretation of Gödel’s principle of the undefinability of V as a justification for large-cardinal axioms.

The statement that a set A is definable is usually understood in two different senses:

  1. (1) There is a formula $\varphi (x)$ that defines A. That is, for every set a, a belongs to A if and only if $\varphi (a)$ holds. The formula $\varphi $ may have parameters, provided they are simpler than A, e.g., their rank is less than the rank of A.

  2. (2) A is the unique solution of a formula . Again, may have parameters simpler than A.

There is, however, no essential difference between (1) and (2). For the formula $\varphi (x)$ defines a set A in the sense of (1) if and only if the formula $\forall x (x\in y \leftrightarrow \varphi (x))$ defines A in the sense of (2). But if A is a proper class, then (1) and (2) are very different, even if only because (2) needs to be reformulated to make any sense. If we understand definability as in (1), then there are many formulas that define V, for instance the formula $x=x$ . So, the notion of undefinability of V can only be understood in the sense of (2), once properly reformulated. To express that V is not the unique solution of a formula, possibly with some sets as parameters, we need to make sense of the fact that a formula is true of V, as opposed to being true in V.

Let $\mathcal {L}_V$ be the first-order language of set theory expanded with a constant symbol $\bar {a}$ for every set a, and a new constant symbol v. Define the class $\mathcal {T}$ of sentences of $\mathcal {L}_V$ recursively as follows: $\varphi $ belongs to $\mathcal {T}$ if and only if:

The idea is that if $\varphi $ belongs to $\mathcal {T}$ , then $\varphi $ is true in the structure

$$ \begin{align*} \bar{V}:= \langle V\cup \{ V\}, \in , V, \langle \bar{a}\rangle_{a\in V}\rangle, \end{align*} $$

where the constant v is interpreted as V. And conversely, if $\varphi $ is a sentence in the language $\mathcal {L}_V$ that is true in $\bar {V}$ , then $\varphi \in \mathcal {T}$ . Thus one may construe the principle of undefinability of V, as expressed in Gödel’s quote above, as follows:

Undefinability of V: Every $\varphi \in \mathcal {T}$ is true in some

$$ \begin{align*} \bar{V}_{\alpha} : = \langle V_{\alpha} \cup \{ V_{\alpha} \}, \in , V_{\alpha} , \langle \bar{a}\rangle_{a\in V_{\alpha}}\rangle.\end{align*} $$

Of course, to express this principle in the first-order language of set theory one needs to do it as a schema. Namely, for each n let $\mathcal {T}_n$ be the class of $\Sigma _n$ sentences of $\mathcal {T}$ , and let

$$ \begin{align*} \Sigma_n\text{-Undefinability of } V: \text{ Every } \varphi \in \mathcal{T}_n \text{ is true in some } \bar{V}_{\alpha}. \end{align*} $$

Given a $\Sigma _n$ sentence $\varphi $ of the language of set theory, where $n\geq 1$ , if it is true in V, i.e., if $\models _n \varphi $ holds, then the sentence $\varphi ^v$ obtained from $\varphi $ by bounding all quantifiers by v belongs to $\mathcal {T}_n$ . Hence, by $\Sigma _n$ -Undefinability of V, $\varphi ^v$ is true in some $\bar {V}_{\alpha }$ , and therefore $V_{\alpha } \models \varphi $ . Thus Undefinability of V directly implies the Principle of Reflection of Montague–Lévy (over the theory ZF minus Infinity). Conversely, by induction on the complexity of $\varphi $ , it is easily shown that ZF proves $\Sigma _n$ -Undefinability of V. Thus, to derive stronger reflection principles based on the undefinability of V one needs to understand “definability,” following Gödel’s quote above, in a “more and more generalized and idealized sense.” One could expand the class $\mathcal {T}$ by adding higher-order sentences that are true of V. However this will not lead us very far. For if $\mathcal {T}'$ is any reasonable class of (higher-order) sentences that are true of V, then Undefinability of V for the class $\mathcal {T}'$ will imply the reflection, in the sense of Montague–Lévy, of all sentences in $\mathcal {T}'$ . Therefore, the limitations seen above of the extensions of the Montague–Lévy Principle of Reflection to higher-order formulas apply also to these generalized forms of Undefinability of V.

2 Structural Reflection

The main obstacle for the program of finding an intrinsic justification of large-cardinal axioms via strong principles of reflection lies, we believe, on a too restrictive interpretation of the notion of reflection, namely the interpretation investigated by Tait, Koellner, and others, according to which the reflection properties of V are exhausted by generalized forms of the Montague–Lévy Principle of Reflection to higher-order logics.

Let us think again about the notion of reflection as derived from the Cantor–Ackermann principle of the unknowability of the absolute. A different interpretation of this principle may be extracted from another claim made by Gödel, as quoted in [Reference Wang36]:

The universe of sets cannot be uniquely characterized (i.e., distinguished from all its initial segments) by any internal structural property of the membership relation in it which is expressible in any logic of finite or transfinite type, including infinitary logics of any cardinal number.

This quote does not immediately suggest that the uncharacterizability of V should be interpreted in the sense of the Montague–Lévy kind of reflection. Rather, what it seems to suggest is some sort of reflection, not (only) of formulas, but of internal structural properties of the membership relation. The quote does also state that the properties should be expressible in some logic, and any reasonable logic would do. So maybe Gödel is not saying here anything new, and he is simply advocating for a generalization of the Montague–Lévy type of reflection to formulas belonging to any (reasonable) kind of logic. But whatever the correct interpretation of Gödel’s quote above may be, let us consider in some detail the idea of reflection of structural properties of the membership relation. Thus, what one would want to reflect is not the theory of V, but rather the structural content of V.

Whatever one might mean by a “structural property of the membership relation,” it is clear that such a property should be exemplified in structures of the form $\langle A, \in , \langle R_i\rangle _{i\in I} \rangle $ , where A is a set and $\langle R_i\rangle _{i\in I}$ is a family of relations on A, and where I is a set that may be empty. Moreover, any such property should be expressible by some formula of the language of set theory, maybe involving some set parameters. Thus, any internal structural property of the membership relation would be formally given by a formula $\varphi (x)$ of the first-order language of set theory, possibly with parameters, that defines a class of structures $\langle A, \in ,\langle R_i\rangle _{i\in I} \rangle $ of the same type. As we shall see later on there is no loss of generality in considering only classes of structures whose members are of the form $\langle V_{\alpha }, \in ,\langle R_i\rangle _{i\in I} \rangle $ . Now, Gödel’s vague assertion (as quoted above) that V “cannot be uniquely characterized (i.e., distinguished from all its initial segments) by any internal structural property of the membership relation” can be naturally interpreted in the sense that no formula $\varphi (x)$ characterizes V, meaning that some $V_{\alpha }$ reflects the structural property defined by $\varphi (x)$ . Let us emphasize that what is reflected is not the formula $\varphi (x)$ , but the structural property defined by $\varphi (x)$ , i.e., the class of structures defined by $\varphi (x)$ . This is the crucial difference with the Montague–Lévy type of reflection. The most natural way to make this precise is to assert that there exists an ordinal $\alpha $ such that for every structure A in the class (i.e., for every structure A that satisfies $\varphi (x)$ ) there exists a structure B also in the class which belongs to $V_{\alpha }$ and is like A. Since, in general, A may be much larger than any B in $V_{\alpha }$ , the closest resemblance of B to A is attained in the case B is isomorphic to an elementary substructure of A, i.e., B can be elementarily embedded into A. We can now formulate (an informal and preliminary version of) the general principle of Structural Reflection as follows:

  1. SR: (Structural Reflection) For every definable, in the first-order language of set theory, possibly with parameters, class $\mathcal {C}$ of relational structures of the same type there exists an ordinal $\alpha $ that reflects $\mathcal {C}$ , i.e., for every A in $\mathcal {C}$ there exist B in $\mathcal {C}\cap V_{\alpha }$ and an elementary embedding from B into A.

Observe that when $\mathcal {C}$ is a set the principle becomes trivial.

We do not wish to claim that the $\mathrm {SR}$ principle is what Gödel had in mind when talking about reflection of internal structural properties of the membership relation, but we do claim that $\mathrm {SR}$ is a form of reflection that derives naturally from the Cantor–Ackermann principle of unknowability of the Absolute and is at least compatible with Gödel’s interpretation of this principle.

In the remaining sections we will survey a collection of results showing the equivalence of different forms of $\mathrm {SR}$ with the existence of different kinds of large cardinals. Our goal is to illustrate the fact that $\mathrm {SR}$ is a general principle underlying a wide variety of large-cardinal principles. Many of the results have already been published [Reference Bagaria2Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler4, Reference Bagaria and Lücke7Reference Bagaria and Wilson9, Reference Lücke23] or are forthcoming [Reference Bagaria and Lücke6], but some are new (Theorems 4.1, 4.2, 4.5, and 4.74.9, Proposition 5.1, Theorem 5.11, Proposition 5.17, and Theorems 5.18, 5.19, 5.21, and 7.6). Each of these results should be regarded as a small step towards the ultimate objective of showing that all large cardinals are in fact different manifestations of a single general reflection principle.

3 From supercompactness to Vopěnka’s Principle

We shall begin with the $\mathrm {SR}$ principle, as stated above, which is properly formulated in the first-order language of set theory as an axiom schema. Namely, for each natural number n let

  1. Σn-SR: ( $\mathbf {\Sigma _n}$ -Structural Reflection) For every $\Sigma _n$ -definable, with parameters, class $\mathcal {C}$ of relational structures of the same type there is an ordinal $\alpha $ that reflects $\mathcal {C}$ .

- $\mathrm {SR}$ may be formulated analogously. We may also define the lightface, i.e., parameter-free versions (as customary we use the lightface types $\Sigma _n$ and for that). Namely,

  1. Σ n -SR: ( $\Sigma _n$ -Structural Reflection) For every $\Sigma _n$ -definable, without parameters, class $\mathcal {C}$ of relational structures of the same type there exists an ordinal $\alpha $ that reflects $\mathcal {C}$ .

Similarly for - $\mathrm {SR}$ .

A standard closing-off argument shows that $\mathbf {\Sigma _n}$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ is equivalent to the assertion that there exists a proper class of ordinals $\alpha $ such that $\alpha $ reflects all classes of structures of the same type that are $\Sigma _n$ -definable, with parameters in $V_{\alpha }$ . Also, $\Sigma _n$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ is equivalent to the assertion that there exists an ordinal $\alpha $ that reflects all classes of structures of the same type that are $\Sigma _n$ -definable, without parameters. Similarly for - $\mathrm {SR}$ and - $\mathrm {SR}$ . Thus, for $\Gamma $ a definability class (i.e., one of $\mathbf {\Sigma _n}$ , , $\Sigma _n$ , or ), let us say that an ordinal $\alpha $ witnesses $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {SR}$ if $\alpha $ reflects all classes of structures of the same type that are $\Gamma $ -definable (allowing for parameters in $V_{\alpha }$ , in the case of boldface classes). Then, in the case of boldface classes $\Gamma $ , $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {SR}$ holds if and only if $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {SR}$ is witnessed by a proper class of ordinals.

The first observation is that, as the next proposition shows, $\mathbf {\Sigma _1}$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ is provable in ZFC. RecallFootnote 4 that, for every $n>0$ , $C^{(n)}$ is the -definable club proper class of cardinals $\kappa $ such that , i.e., $V_{\kappa }$ is a $\Sigma _n$ -elementary substructure of V. In particular, every element of $C^{(1)}$ is an uncountable cardinal and a fixed point of the $\beth $ function.

Proposition 3.1. The following are equivalent for every ordinal $\alpha $ :

  1. (1) $\alpha $ witnesses $\mathbf {\Sigma _0}$ - $\mathrm {SR}.$

  2. (2) $\alpha $ witnesses $\mathbf {\Sigma _1}$ - $\mathrm {SR}.$

  3. (3) $\alpha \in C^{(1)}$ .

Proof The implication (2) $\Rightarrow $ (1) is trivial. The implication (3) $\Rightarrow $ (2) is proved in [Reference Bagaria, Casacuberta, Mathias and Rosický3], using a Löwenheim–Skolem type of argument.

To show that (1) implies (3), let $\alpha $ witness $\mathbf {\Sigma _0}$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ and suppose $\varphi (a_1,\ldots ,a_n)$ is a $\Sigma _1$ sentence, with parameters $a_1,\ldots ,a_n$ in $V_{\alpha }$ , that holds in V. Let ${\mathcal C}$ be the $\Sigma _0$ -definable, with $a_1,\ldots ,a_n$ as parameters, class of structures of the form

$$ \begin{align*}\langle M,\in, \{a_1,\ldots,a_n\} \rangle,\end{align*} $$

where M is a transitive set that contains $a_1,\ldots ,a_n$ . Let M be any transitive set such that $M\models \varphi (a_1,\ldots ,a_n)$ . By $\mathrm {SR}$ , there is an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*}j:\langle N,\in, \{a_1,\ldots,a_n\} \rangle\to \langle M,\in ,\{a_1,\ldots,a_n\}\rangle,\end{align*} $$

where $\langle N,\in \{a_1,\ldots ,a_n\}\rangle \in {\mathcal C} \cap V_{\alpha }$ . Since j fixes $a_1,\ldots ,a_n$ , by elementarity $N\models \varphi (a_1,\ldots ,a_n)$ , and by upwards absoluteness for $\Sigma _1$ sentences with respect to transitive sets, $V_{\alpha }\models \varphi (a_1,\ldots ,a_n)$ . This shows $\alpha \in C^{(1)}$ .

Thus, $\mathbf {\Sigma _1}$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ is provable in ZFC, and therefore does not yield any large cardinals. But - $\mathrm {SR}$ does, and is indeed very strong. The following theorem hinges on Magidor’s characterization of the first supercompact cardinal as the first cardinal that reflects the -definable class of structures of the form $\langle V_{\alpha }, \in \rangle $ , $\alpha $ an ordinal [Reference Magidor24].

Theorem 3.2 [Reference Bagaria2, Reference Bagaria, Casacuberta, Mathias and Rosický3].

The following are equivalent:

  1. (1) - $\mathrm {SR}$ .

  2. (2) $\Sigma _2$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ .

  3. (3) There exists a supercompact cardinal.

The proof of the theorem shows in fact that the following are equivalent for an ordinal $\kappa $ :

  1. (1) $\kappa $ is the least ordinal that witnesses $\mathrm {SR}$ for the -definable class of structures $\langle V_{\alpha } ,\in \rangle $ , $\alpha $ an ordinal.

  2. (2) $\kappa $ is the least cardinal that witnesses - $\mathrm {SR}$ .

  3. (3) $\kappa $ is the least cardinal that witnesses $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ .

  4. (4) $\kappa $ is the least supercompact cardinal.

The following global parametrized version then follows. Namely,

Theorem 3.3 [Reference Bagaria2, Reference Bagaria, Casacuberta, Mathias and Rosický3].

The following are equivalent:

  1. (1) - $\mathrm {SR}$ .

  2. (2) $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ .

  3. (3) There exists a proper class of supercompact cardinals.

The proof of the theorem also shows that if $\kappa $ witnesses - $\mathrm {SR}$ , then $\kappa $ is either supercompact or a limit of supercompact cardinals.

Some remarks are in order. First, the equivalence of - $\mathrm {SR}$ and $\Sigma _2$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ , and also of their boldface forms, is due to the following general fact. Given a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ definable (possibly with parameters, and with $n>0$ ) class $\mathcal {C}$ of relational structures of the same type, let $\mathcal {C}^{\ast }$ be the class of structures of the form $\langle V_{\alpha } , \in ,A\rangle $ , where $\alpha $ is the least cardinal in $C^{(n)}$ such that $A\in V_{\alpha }$ and $V_{\alpha } \models \varphi (A)$ , where $\varphi (x)$ is a fixed $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula that defines ${\mathcal C}$ . Then,

$$ \begin{align*} A\in \mathcal{C}\mbox{ if and only if }\langle V_{\alpha}, \in ,A\rangle \in \mathcal{C}^{\ast}. \end{align*} $$

Now notice that $\mathcal {C}^{\ast }$ is definable, with the same parameters as $\mathcal {C}$ (see [Reference Bagaria2]). Moreover, if a cardinal $\kappa $ reflects the class ${\mathcal C}^{\ast }$ , then it also reflects ${\mathcal C}$ : for if $A\in {\mathcal C}$ , let $\alpha $ be the least cardinal in $C^{(n)}$ such that $\langle V_{\alpha } ,\in , A\rangle \models \varphi (A)$ , where $\varphi (x)$ is a fixed $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula that defines ${\mathcal C}$ . Let $j:\langle V_{\beta } , \in , B\rangle \to \langle V_{\alpha } ,\in , A\rangle $ be elementary with $\langle V_{\beta } ,\in ,B\rangle \in {\mathcal C}^{\ast } \cap V_{\kappa }$ . Then, since $\beta \in C^{(n)}$ and $V_{\beta } \models \varphi (B)$ , we have that $B\in {\mathcal C}$ and the restriction map $j\restriction A:A\to B$ is an elementary embedding.

For P a set or a proper class and $\Gamma $ a definability class, we shall write $\Gamma (P)$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ for the assertion that $\mathrm {SR}$ holds for all $\Gamma $ -definable, with parameters in P, classes of structures of the same type. Thus, e.g., $\mathbf {\Sigma _n}$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ is $\Sigma _n(V)$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ , and $\Sigma _n$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ is $\Sigma _n(\varnothing )$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ . Our remarks above yield now the following:

Proposition 3.4. For P any set or proper class, the assertions - $\mathrm {SR}$ and $\Sigma _{n+1}(P)$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ are equivalent. In particular - $\mathrm {SR}$ and $\Sigma _{n+1}$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ are equivalent, and so are - $\mathrm {SR}$ and $\mathbf {\Sigma _{n+1}}$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ .

Second, the remarks above also show that for principles of Structural Reflection of the form $\Gamma (P)$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ the relevant structures to consider are those of the form $\langle V_{\alpha } ,\in , A\rangle $ , where $A\in V_{\alpha }$ . Let us say that a structure is natural if it is of this form. Therefore, we may reformulate $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {SR}$ , for $\Gamma $ a lightface definability class, as follows:

  1. Γ-SR: ( $\Gamma $ -Structural Reflection. Second version) There exists a cardinal $\kappa $ that reflects all $\Gamma $ -definable classes ${\mathcal C}$ of natural structures, i.e., for every $A\in {\mathcal C}$ there exist $B\in {\mathcal C} \cap V_{\kappa }$ and an elementary embedding $j:B\to A$ .

The version for $\Gamma $ a boldface definability class being as follows:

  • There exists a proper class of cardinals $\kappa $ that reflect all $\Gamma $ -definable, with parameters in $V_{\kappa }$ , classes ${\mathcal C}$ of natural structures.

At the next level of definitional complexity, i.e., $n=2$ , we have the following:

Theorem 3.5 [Reference Bagaria2, Reference Bagaria, Casacuberta, Mathias and Rosický3].

The following are equivalent:

  1. (1) - $\mathrm {SR}$ .

  2. (2) There exists an extendible cardinal.

The proof of the theorem shows that the first extendible cardinal is precisely the first cardinal that witnesses SR for one particular -definable class of natural structures. The parameterized version also holds:

Theorem 3.6 [Reference Bagaria2, Reference Bagaria, Casacuberta, Mathias and Rosický3].

The following are equivalent:

  1. (1) - $\mathrm {SR}$ .

  2. (2) There exists a proper class of extendible cardinals.

Moreover, if $\kappa $ witnesses - $\mathrm {SR}$ , then $\kappa $ is either extendible or a limit of extendible cardinals.

For the higher levels of definitional complexity we need the notion of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal from [Reference Bagaria2, Reference Bagaria, Casacuberta, Mathias and Rosický3]: $\kappa $ is $C^{(n)}$ -extendible if for every $\lambda $ greater than $\kappa $ there exists an elementary embedding $j:V_{\lambda } \to V_{\mu }$ , some $\mu $ , with $crit(j)=\kappa $ , $j(\kappa )>\lambda $ , and $j(\kappa )\in C^{(n)}$ . Note that the only difference with the notion of extendibility is that we require the image of the critical point to be in $C^{(n)}$ . Also note that every extendible cardinal is $C^{(1)}$ -extendible. We then have the following level-by-level characterizations of $\mathrm {SR}$ in terms of the existence of large cardinals:

Theorem 3.7 [Reference Bagaria2, Reference Bagaria, Casacuberta, Mathias and Rosický3].

The following are equivalent for $n\geq 1$ :

  1. (1) - $\mathrm {SR}$ .

  2. (2) There exists a $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal.

Theorem 3.8 [Reference Bagaria2, Reference Bagaria, Casacuberta, Mathias and Rosický3].

The following are equivalent for $n\geq 1$ :

  1. (1) - $\mathrm {SR}$ .

  2. (2) There exists a proper class of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals.

Similarly as in the case of supercompact and extendible cardinals, the proofs of the theorems above actually show that the first $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal is the first cardinal that witnesses SR for one single -definable class of natural structures. Also, if $\kappa $ witnesses - $\mathrm {SR}$ , then $\kappa $ is either a $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal or a limit of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals.

Recall that Vopěnka’s Principle $(\mathrm {VP})$ is the assertion that for every proper class $\mathcal {C}$ of relational structures of the same type there exist $A\ne B$ in $\mathcal {C}$ such that A is elementarily embeddable into B. In the first-order language of set theory $\mathrm {VP}$ can be formulated as a schema. The following corollary to the theorems stated above yields a characterization of $\mathrm {VP}$ in terms of $\mathrm {SR}$ . Moreover, it shows that, globally, the lightface and boldface forms of $\mathrm {SR}$ are equivalent.

Theorem 3.9 [Reference Bagaria2, Reference Bagaria, Casacuberta, Mathias and Rosický3].

The following schemata are equivalent:

  1. (1) $\mathrm {SR}$ , i.e., - $\mathrm {SR}$ for all n.

  2. (2) - $\mathrm {SR}$ for all n.

  3. (3) There exists a $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal, for every n.

  4. (4) There is a proper class of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals, for every n.

  5. (5) $\mathrm {VP}$ .

4 Structural Reflection below supercompactness

We have just seen that a natural hierarchy of large cardinals in the region between the first supercompact cardinal and $\mathrm {VP}$ can be characterized in terms of $\mathrm {SR}$ . Now the question is if the same is true for other well-known regions of the large cardinal hierarchy. Since $\mathbf {\Sigma _1}$ -SR is provable in ZFC and -SR implies already the existence of a supercompact cardinal, if large cardinals weaker than supercompact admit a characterization as principles of structural reflection, then we need to look either for $\mathrm {SR}$ restricted to particular (collections of) -definable classes of structures, or for classes of structures whose definitional complexity is between $\Sigma _1$ and (e.g., $\Sigma _1$ -definability with additional predicates), or for weaker forms of structural reflection. Let us consider first the $\mathrm {SR}$ principle restricted to particular definable classes of structures contained in canonical inner models.

4.1 Structural Reflection relative to canonical inner models

There is one single class ${\mathcal C}$ of structures in L that is -definable in V, without parameters, and such that $\mathrm {SR} ({\mathcal C})$ is equivalent to the existence of $0^{\sharp }$ . Namely, let ${\mathcal C}$ be the class of structures of the form $\langle L_{\beta } ,\in ,\gamma \rangle $ , with $\gamma <\beta $ uncountable cardinals (in V).

Theorem 4.1. The following are equivalent:

  1. (1) $\mathrm {SR}({\mathcal C}).$

  2. (2) $0^{\sharp }$ exists.

Proof (1) implies (2): Suppose that $\alpha $ reflects ${\mathcal C}$ . Pick V-cardinals $\gamma < \beta $ with $\alpha \leq \gamma $ . By reflection, there are V-cardinals $\gamma '<\beta '<\alpha $ and an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*} j:\langle L_{\beta'},\in ,\gamma'\rangle \to \langle L_{\beta} ,\in ,\gamma\rangle. \end{align*} $$

Since $j(\gamma ')=\gamma $ , j is not the identity. Let $\kappa $ be the critical point of j. Thus, $\kappa \leq \gamma '<\beta '$ . Hence by Kunen’s Theorem [Reference Kunen18] $0^{\sharp }$ exists.

(2) implies (1): Assume $0^{\sharp }$ exists. Let $\alpha $ be an uncountable limit cardinal in V. We claim that $\alpha $ reflects ${\mathcal C}$ . For suppose $\langle L_{\beta } , \in ,\gamma \rangle \in {\mathcal C}$ with $\alpha \leq \beta $ . Let $\gamma '<\beta '<\alpha $ be uncountable cardinals in V such that $\gamma ' \leq \gamma $ . Let I denote the class of Silver indiscernibles. Let $j:I\cap [\gamma ',\beta ']\to I\cap [\gamma ,\beta ]$ be order-preserving and such that $j(\gamma ')=\gamma $ and $j(\beta ')=\beta $ . Then j generates an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*} j:\langle L_{\beta'},\in ,\gamma'\rangle \to \langle L_{\beta} ,\in ,\gamma\rangle, \end{align*} $$

as required.

The existence of $0^{\sharp }$ yields also the $\mathrm {SR}$ principle restricted to classes of structures that are definable in L.

Theorem 4.2. If $0^{\sharp }$ exists, then $\mathrm {SR}({\mathcal C})$ holds for every class ${\mathcal C}$ that is definable in L, with parameters.

Proof Fix $\mathcal {C}$ and a formula $\varphi (x)$ , possibly with ordinals $\alpha _0 <\cdots <\alpha _m$ as parameters, that defines it in L. Let $\kappa $ be a limit of Silver indiscernibles greater than $\alpha _m$ . We claim that $\kappa $ reflects $\mathcal {C}$ . For suppose $B\in \mathcal {C}$ . Without loss of generality, $B\not \in L_{\kappa }$ . Since $0^{\sharp }$ exists, there is an increasing sequence of Silver indiscernibles $i_0,\ldots ,i_n, i_{n+1}$ and a formula

, without parameters, such that

Choose indiscernibles $j_0 <\cdots < j_n <j_{n+1} <\kappa $ , with $\alpha _m < j_0$ , and let

Thus $A\in L_{\kappa }$ . Since $L\models \varphi (B)$ , we have that

By indiscernibility,

which implies $L\models \varphi (A)$ , i.e., $A\in \mathcal {C}$ .

Let $j:L\to L$ be an elementary embedding that sends $i_k$ to $j_k$ , all $k\leq n+1$ . Then by indiscernibility, the map $j\restriction A:A\to B$ is an elementary embedding.

However, the $\mathrm {SR}$ principle restricted to classes of structures that are definable in L falls very short of yielding $0^{\sharp }$ , as we shall next show. Let us recall the following definition:

Definition 4.3 [Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler4].

A cardinal $\kappa $ is n-remarkable, for $n>0$ , if for all $\lambda>\kappa $ in $C^{(n)}$ and every $a\in V_{\lambda }$ , there is $\bar {\lambda } <\kappa $ also in $C^{(n)}$ such that in $V^{\mathrm {{Coll}(\omega , <\kappa )}}$ there exists an elementary embedding $j:V_{\bar {\lambda }}\to V_{\lambda }$ with $j(\mathrm {{crit}}(j))=\kappa $ and $a\in \mathrm {{range}}(j)$ .

A cardinal $\kappa $ is $1$ -remarkable if and only if it is remarkable, in the sense of Schindler (see [Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler4] and Definition 7.2).

If $0^{\sharp }$ exists, then every Silver indiscernible is completely remarkable in L (i.e., n-remarkable for every $n>0$ ). Moreover, the consistency strength of the existence of a $1$ -remarkable cardinal is strictly weaker than the existence of a $2$ -iterable cardinal, which in turn is weaker than the existence of an $\omega $ -Erdös cardinal (see [Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler4]).

A weaker notion than n-remarkability is obtained by eliminating from its definition the requirement that $j(\mathrm {crit}(j))=\kappa $ . So, let’s define:

Definition 4.4. A cardinal $\kappa $ is almost n-remarkable, for $n>0$ , if for all $\lambda>\kappa $ in $C^{(n)}$ and every $a\in V_{\lambda }$ , there is $\bar {\lambda } <\kappa $ also in $C^{(n)}$ such that in $V^{\mathrm {{Coll}(\omega , <\kappa )}}$ there exists an elementary embedding $j:V_{\bar {\lambda }}\to V_{\lambda }$ with $a\in \mathrm {{range}}(j)$ .

We say that $\kappa $ is almost completely remarkable if it is almost-n-remarkable for every n.

Theorem 4.5. A cardinal $\kappa $ is almost n-remarkable if and only if in $V^{\mathrm {{Coll}(\omega ,<\kappa )}} \ \kappa $ witnesses $\mathrm {SR}({\mathcal C})$ for every class ${\mathcal C}$ that is -definable in V with parameters in $V_{\kappa }$ .

Proof Assume $\kappa $ is almost n-remarkable. Fix $\mathcal {C}$ and a formula $\varphi (x)$ that defines it in V, possibly with parameters in $V_{\kappa }$ . Suppose $B\in \mathcal {C}$ . In V, let $\lambda \in C^{(n)}$ be greater than the rank of B. Thus, $V_{\lambda } \models \varphi (B)$ . Since $\kappa $ is almost n-remarkable, there is $\bar {\lambda } <\kappa $ also in $C^{(n)}$ such that in $V^{\mathrm {{Coll}(\omega ,<\kappa )}}$ there exists an elementary embedding $j:V_{\bar {\lambda }}\to V_{\lambda }$ with $B \in \mathrm {{range}}(j)$ . Let A be the preimage of B under j. So $A\in V_{\kappa }$ . By elementarity of j, $V_{\bar {\lambda }}\models \varphi (A)$ . Hence, since $\bar {\lambda } \in C^{(n)}$ , $A\in \mathcal {C}$ . Moreover, $j\restriction A: A\to B$ is an elementary embedding.

Conversely, assume that in $V^{\mathrm {{Coll}(\omega ,<\kappa )}}$ , $\kappa $ witnesses $\mathrm {SR}({\mathcal C})$ for every class ${\mathcal C}$ that is -definable in V with parameters in $V_{\kappa }$ . Let ${\mathcal C}$ be the -definable class of structures of the form $\langle V_{\alpha } ,\in , a\rangle $ where $\alpha \in C^{(n)}$ and $a\in V_{\alpha }$ . Given $\lambda \in C^{(n)}$ and $a\in V_{\lambda }$ , in $V^{\mathrm {{Coll}(\omega ,<\kappa )}}$ there exists some $\langle V_{\bar {\lambda }}, \in ,b\rangle \in {\mathcal C}$ together with an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*} j:\langle V_{\bar{\lambda}}, \in, b \rangle \to \langle V_{\lambda} ,\in ,a\rangle. \end{align*} $$

Since $j(b)=a$ , $a\in \mathrm {{range}}(j)$ . This shows $\kappa $ is almost n-remarkable.

Corollary 4.6. If $\kappa $ is an almost completely remarkable cardinal in L, then in $L^{\mathrm {{Coll}(\omega ,<\kappa )}} \ \kappa $ witnesses $\mathrm {SR}({\mathcal C})$ for all classes ${\mathcal C}$ of structures that are definable in L with parameters in $L_{\kappa }$ .

Similar arguments yield analogous results for $X^{\sharp }$ , for every set of ordinals X. Given a set of ordinals X, let $\mathcal {C}_X$ be the class of structures of the form $\langle L_{\beta } [X] ,\in ,\gamma \rangle $ , where $\gamma $ and $\beta $ are cardinals (in V) and $sup(X) <\gamma <\beta $ . Clearly, ${\mathcal C}_X$ is definable with X as a parameter.

Theorem 4.7.

  1. (1) $\mathrm {SR}({\mathcal C}_X)$ holds if and only if $X^{\sharp }$ exists.

  2. (2) If $X^{\sharp }$ exists, then $\mathrm {SR}(\mathcal {C})$ holds for all classes $\mathcal {C}$ that are definable in $L[X]$ , with parameters.

These results suggest the following forms of $\mathrm {SR}$ restricted to inner models. Let M be an inner model. Writing $M_{\alpha }$ for $(V_{\alpha })^M$ , consider the following principle for $\Gamma $ a lightface definability class:

  1. Γ-SR(M): ( $\Gamma $ -Structural Reflection for M) There exists an ordinal $\alpha $ that reflects every $\Gamma $ -definable class ${\mathcal C}$ of relational structures of the same type such that ${\mathcal C} \subseteq M$ , i.e., for every A in $\mathcal {C}$ there exist B in $\mathcal {C}\cap M_{\alpha }$ and an elementary embedding j from B into A. (Warning: j may not be in M.)

The corresponding version for a boldface $\Gamma $ being as follows:

  • There exists a proper class of ordinals $\alpha $ that reflect every $\Gamma $ -definable, with parameters in $M_{\alpha }$ , class ${\mathcal C}$ of relational structures of the same type such that ${\mathcal C} \subseteq M$ .

The last theorem shows that, for every set of ordinals X, the existence of $X^{\sharp }$ implies $\mathrm {SR}(L[X])$ , i.e., $\mathbf {\Sigma _n}$ - $\mathrm {SR}(L[X])$ , for every n.

Similar results may be obtained for other canonical inner models, e.g., $L[U]$ , the canonical inner model for one measurable cardinal $\kappa $ , where U is the (unique) normal measure on $\kappa $ in $L[U]$ . Let ${\mathcal C}^U$ be the class of structures of the form $\langle L_{\beta }[U] ,\in ,\gamma \rangle $ , with $\gamma <\beta $ uncountable cardinals (in V). The class ${\mathcal C}^U$ is -definable in V, with U as a parameter. By using well-known facts about $0^{\dagger }$ due to Solovay (see [Reference Kanamori15] 21), and arguing similarly as in Theorems 4.1 and 4.2, respectively, one obtains the following:

Theorem 4.8. The following are equivalent:

  1. (1) $\mathrm {SR}({\mathcal C}^U)$ holds if and only if $0^{\dagger }$ exists.

  2. (2) If $0^{\dagger }$ exists, then $\mathrm {SR}({\mathcal C})$ holds for every class ${\mathcal C}$ that is definable in $L[U]$ , with parameters.

Also, similarly as in Theorem 4.7, one can obtain the analogous result for $X^{\dagger }$ , for every set of ordinals X. Namely, given a set of ordinals X, let $\mathcal {C}^U_X$ be the class of structures of the form $\langle L_{\beta } [U, X] ,\in ,\gamma \rangle $ , where $\gamma $ and $\beta $ are cardinals (in V) and $sup(X) <\gamma <\beta $ . Then ${\mathcal C}^U_X$ is -definable with U and X as parameters.

Theorem 4.9.

  1. (1) $\mathrm {SR}({\mathcal C}^U_X)$ holds if and only if $X^{\dagger }$ exists.

  2. (2) If $X^{\dagger }$ exists, then $\mathrm {SR}(\mathcal {C})$ holds for all classes $\mathcal {C}$ that are definable in $L[U,X]$ , with parameters.

Analogous results should also hold for canonical inner models for stronger large-cardinal notions. For example, for the canonical inner model $L[\mathcal {E}]$ for a strong cardinal, as in [Reference Koepke17] or [Reference Mitchell27], and its sharp, zero pistol . Also for a canonical inner model for a proper class of strong cardinals, as in [Reference Schindler32], and its sharp, zero hand grenade. For inner models for stronger large cardinal notions, e.g., one Woodin cardinal, the situation is less clear, although analogous results should hold given the appropriate canonical inner model and its corresponding sharp.

5 Product Structural Reflection

Recall that for any set S of relational structures $\mathcal {A}=\langle A, \ldots \rangle $ of the same type, the set-theoretic product is the structure whose universe is the set of all functions f with domain S such that $f(\mathcal {A})\in A$ , for every $\mathcal {A}\in S$ , and whose relations are defined point-wise.

In this section we shall consider the following general product form of structural reflection, which is a variation of the Product Reflection Principle $(\mathrm {PRP})$ introduced in [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9]:

  1. PSR: (Product Structural Reflection) For every definable class of relational structures $\mathcal {C}$ of the same type, $\tau $ , there exists an ordinal $\alpha $ that product-reflects $\mathcal {C}$ , i.e., for every ${\mathcal A}$ in $\mathcal {C}$ there exists a set S of structures of type $\tau $ (although not necessarily in ${\mathcal C}$ ) with ${\mathcal A}\in S $ and an elementary embedding .

Similarly as in the case of $\mathrm {SR}$ (see Section 2), we may formally define $\mathrm {PSR}$ as a schema. Thus, we say that an ordinal $\alpha $ witnesses $\Gamma (P)$ - $\mathrm {PSR}$ (where $\Gamma $ is a definability class and P a set or a proper class) if $\alpha $ product-reflects all classes ${\mathcal C}$ that are $\Gamma $ -definable with parameters in P. Our remarks in Section 2 also apply here. In particular, an ordinal $\alpha $ witnesses - $\mathrm {PSR}$ if and only if it witnesses $\mathbf {\Sigma _{n+1}}$ - $\mathrm {PSR}$ . Moreover, we obtain equivalent principles by restricting to classes of natural structures. Thus, for $\Gamma $ a lightface definability class, we define:

  1. Γ-PSR: ( $\Gamma $ -Product Structural Reflection) There exists an ordinal $\alpha $ that product-reflects all $\Gamma $ -definable classes ${\mathcal C}$ of natural structures.

The corresponding version for $\Gamma $ boldface being as follows:

  • There exists a proper class of ordinals $\alpha $ that product-reflect all $\Gamma $ -definable, with parameters in $V_{\alpha }$ , classes ${\mathcal C}$ of natural structures.

As in [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9, Proposition 3.2] one can show that every cardinal $\kappa $ in $C^{(1)}$ witnesses $\mathbf {\Sigma _1}$ - $\mathrm {PSR}$ . The converse also holds, and in fact we have the following:

Proposition 5.1. For every n, if $\kappa $ witnesses - $\mathrm {PSR}$ , then $\kappa \in C^{(n+1)}$ .

Proof We shall prove the case $n=1$ . The general case follows by induction, using a similar argument. The case $n=0$ is similar to the case $n=1$ , but simpler, as it suffices to consider a class of structures with domain a transitive set (see the proof of Proposition 3.1). So, suppose $\varphi (x,y)$ is a

formula with $x,y$ as the only free variables, $a\in V_{\kappa }$ , and $V\models \exists x\varphi (x,a)$ . Let ${\mathcal C}$ be the

-definable, with a as a parameter, class of structures of the form

with $\alpha \in C^{(1)}$ , and where

is the

relational diagram for $\langle V_{\alpha }, \in ,a\rangle $ , i.e., if $\varphi (x_1,\ldots ,x_n, \overline {a})$ , $\overline {a}$ a constant symbol, is a

formula in the language of $\langle V_{\alpha },\in ,a \rangle $ , then

$$ \begin{align*} R^{\alpha}_{\varphi} =\{ \langle a_1,\ldots ,a_n\rangle: \langle V_{\alpha},\in,a\rangle\models \text{"}\varphi[a_1,\ldots ,a_n, a]\text{"}\}\,. \end{align*} $$

Let $\lambda>\kappa $ be in $C^{(2)}$ , so that $V_{\lambda } \models \exists x\varphi (x,a)$ . By $\mathrm {PSR}$ there exists a set S that contains ${\mathcal A}_{\lambda }$ and an elementary embedding

Since ${\mathcal A}_{\lambda } \models \exists x \varphi (x,a)$ , we have $R^{\lambda }_{\varphi } \ne \varnothing $ . Hence, since ${\mathcal A}_{\lambda } \in S$ ,

and therefore, by elementarity of j,

which implies that ${\mathcal A}_{\alpha } \models R^{\alpha }_{\varphi } \ne \varnothing $ , for some $\alpha <\kappa $ . Hence, ${\mathcal A}_{\alpha } \models \exists x \varphi (x,a)$ .

Note that, if $\varphi (x,y)$ had been a bounded formula, instead of , then we would have, by upward absoluteness, that ${\mathcal A}_{\kappa } \models \exists x\varphi (x,y)$ , thus showing that $\kappa \in C^{(1)}$ . Thus, since $\alpha , \kappa \in C^{(1)}$ , we have that , and therefore $V_{\kappa } \models \exists x\varphi (x,a)$ .

Now suppose $V_{\kappa } \models \exists x\varphi (x,a)$ . Since $\kappa \in C^{(1)}$ , by upward absoluteness, $V\models \exists x\varphi (x,a)$ .

Recall that a cardinal $\kappa $ is $\lambda $ -strong, where $\lambda>\kappa $ , if there exists an elementary embedding $j: V\to M$ , with M transitive, $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\kappa $ , $j(\kappa )>\lambda $ , and with $V_{\lambda }$ contained in M. A cardinal $\kappa $ is strong if it is $\lambda $ -strong for every cardinal $\lambda>\kappa $ .

The following proposition is proved similarly as in [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9, Proposition 3.3].

Proposition 5.2. If $\kappa $ is a strong cardinal, then $\kappa $ witnesses - $\mathrm {PSR}$ .

Proof Let $\kappa $ be a strong cardinal and let ${\mathcal C}$ be a -definable, with parameters in $V_{\kappa }$ , proper class of structures in a fixed relational language $\tau \in V_{\kappa }$ . Let $\varphi (x)$ be a formula defining it.

Given any $\mathcal {A}\in {\mathcal C}$ , let $\lambda \in C^{(1)}$ be greater than or equal to $\kappa $ and with $\mathcal {A}\in V_{\lambda }$ .

Let $j:V\to M$ be an elementary embedding, with $crit(j)=\kappa $ , $V_{\lambda } \subseteq M$ , and $j(\kappa )>\lambda $ .

By elementarity, the restriction of j to ${\mathcal C} \cap V_{\kappa }$ yields an elementary embedding

Let $S:= \{ X: M\models \varphi (X)\} \cap V^M_{j(\kappa )}$ . Since $\mathcal {A}\in V_{\lambda }$ and $\varphi (x)$ is

, by downward absoluteness $V_{\lambda } \models \varphi (\mathcal {A})$ . Hence, since the fact that $\lambda \in C^{(1)}$ is

-expressible and therefore downwards absolute for transitive classes, and since $V_{\lambda } \subseteq M$ , it follows that

and therefore $M\models \varphi (\mathcal {A})$ . Moreover $\mathcal {A}\in V_{\lambda } \subseteq V^M_{j(\kappa )}$ . Thus, ${\mathcal A} \in S$ .

Since the Product Reflection Principle ( $\mathrm {PRP}$ ) introduced in [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9] when restricted to -definable classes is an easy consequence of - $\mathrm {PSR}$ , from [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9] we obtain the following:

Theorem 5.3. The following are equivalent:

  1. (1) - $\mathrm {PSR}.$

  2. (2) There exists a strong cardinal.

as well as its boldface version:

Theorem 5.4. The following are equivalent:

  1. (1) - $\mathrm {PSR}.$

  2. (2) There exists a proper class of strong cardinals.

This shows that strong cardinals are related to $\mathrm {PSR}$ as supercompact cardinals are to $\mathrm {SR}$ (Theorems 3.2 and 3.3). For the higher levels of definability, i.e., $n>1$ , the large cardinal notion that corresponds to - $\mathrm {PSR}$ , analogous to the notion of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal in the case of $\mathrm {SR}$ , is the following:

Definition 5.5 [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9].

For $\Gamma $ a definability class and an ordinal $\lambda $ , a cardinal $\kappa $ is $\lambda $ - $\Gamma $ -strong if for every $\Gamma $ -definable (without parameters) class A there is an elementary embedding $j:V\to M$ , with M transitive, $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\kappa $ , $V_{\lambda } \subseteq M$ , and $A\cap V_{\lambda } \subseteq j(A)$ .

A cardinal $\kappa $ is $\Gamma $ -strong if it is $\lambda $ - $\Gamma $ -strong for every ordinal $\lambda $ .

As with the case of strong cardinals, standard arguments show (cf. [Reference Kanamori15] 26.7(b)) that $\kappa $ is $\lambda $ - $\Gamma $ -strong if and only if for every $\Gamma $ -definable (without parameters) class A there is an elementary embedding $j:V\to M$ , with M transitive, $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\kappa $ , $V_{\lambda } \subseteq M$ , $j(\kappa )>\lambda $ , and $A\cap V_{\lambda } \subseteq j(A)$ . As shown in [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9], every strong cardinal is $\Sigma _2$ -strong. Also, a cardinal is -strong if and only if is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -strong. Moreover, if $n\geq 1$ and $\lambda \in C^{(n+1)}$ , then the following are equivalent for a cardinal $\kappa <\lambda $ :

  1. (1) $\kappa $ is $\lambda $ - -strong.

  2. (2) There is an elementary embedding $j:V\to M$ , with M transitive, $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\kappa $ , $V_{\lambda } \subseteq M$ , and $M\models \text {"}\lambda \in C^{(n)}.\text {"}$

Similarly as in Proposition 5.2, one can prove the following (see [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9] for details):

Proposition 5.6. If $\kappa $ is a -strong cardinal, then $\kappa $ witnesses - $\mathrm {PSR}$ .

The following theorem then follows from the main result in [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9]:

Theorem 5.7. The following are equivalent for $n\geq 1$ :

  1. (1) - $\mathrm {PSR}.$

  2. (2) There exists a -strong cardinal.

The corresponding boldface version also holds. Namely,

Theorem 5.8. The following are equivalent for $n\geq 1$ :

  1. (1) - $\mathrm {PSR}.$

  2. (2) There exists a proper class of -strong cardinals.

Finally, for the $\mathrm {PSR}$ principle, the statement analogous to Vopěnka’s Principle in the case of $\mathrm {SR}$ is the following:

Definition 5.9 [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9].

$\mathrm {Ord}$ is Woodin if for every definable $A\subseteq V$ there exists some $\alpha $ which is A-strong, i.e., for every $\gamma $ there is an elementary embedding $j:V\to M$ with $\mathrm {crit} (j)=\alpha $ , $\gamma <j(\alpha )$ , $V_{\gamma } \subseteq M$ , and $A\cap V_{\gamma } =j(A)\cap V_{\gamma }$ .

Note that if $\delta $ is a Woodin cardinal (see [Reference Kanamori15] for the definition of Woodin cardinal and its equivalent formulation in terms of A-strength), then $V_{\delta }$ satisfies $\mathrm {Ord}$ is Woodin. The following equivalences then follow (cf. Theorem 3.9):

Theorem 5.10 [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9].

The following schemata are equivalent:

  1. (1) $\mathrm {PSR}$ , i.e., - $\mathrm {PSR}$ for all n.

  2. (2) - $\mathrm {PSR}$ for all n.

  3. (3) There exists a -strong cardinal, for every n.

  4. (4) There is a proper class of -strong cardinals, for every n.

  5. (5) $\mathrm {Ord}$ is Woodin.

A close inspection of the proofs of Propositions 5.2 and 5.6 reveals that, for $n>0$ , if $\kappa $ is a -strong cardinal, then for every -definable (with parameters in $V_{\kappa }$ ) class ${\mathcal C}$ of relational structures of the same type $\tau $ , and for every $\beta \geq \kappa $ , there exists a set S of structures of type $\tau $ (although possibly not in ${\mathcal C}$ ) that contains ${\mathcal C} \cap V_{\beta }$ and there exists an elementary embedding with the following properties:

  1. (1) Faithful: For every , $h(f)\restriction ({\mathcal C} \cap V_{\kappa }) =f$ .

  2. (2) $\subseteq $ -chain-preserving: If is so that $f({\mathcal A})\subseteq f({\mathcal A}')$ whenever $A \subseteq A'$ , then so is $h(f)$ .

Moreover, if $\kappa $ witnesses - $\mathrm {PSR}$ , then some cardinal less than or equal to $\kappa $ is -strong. Thus, the following is an equivalent reformulation of $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {PSR}$ , for $\Gamma =\Gamma _n$ a lightface definability class with $n>0$ :

  1. Γ-PSR: ( $\Gamma $ -Product Structural Reflection. Second version) There exists a cardinal $\kappa $ that product-reflects all $\Gamma $ -definable proper classes ${\mathcal C}$ of relational structures of the same type $\tau $ , i.e., for every $\beta $ there exists a set S of structures of type $\tau $ that contains ${\mathcal C} \cap V_{\beta }$ , and there exists a faithful and $\subseteq $ -chain-preserving elementary embedding .

The corresponding version for a boldface $\Gamma $ being as follows:

  • There exists a proper class of cardinals $\kappa $ that product-reflect all $\Gamma $ -definable, with parameters in $V_{\kappa }$ , proper class ${\mathcal C}$ of relational structures of the same type.

The next theorem implies that strong cardinals can be characterized in terms of - $\mathrm {PSR}$ . The proof follows closely [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9, Theorem 5.1], with the properties of faithfulness and $\subseteq $ -chain preservation ((1) and (2) above) playing now a key role.

Theorem 5.11. There is a -definable, without parameters, class ${\mathcal C}$ of natural structures such that if a cardinal $\kappa $ product-reflects ${\mathcal C}$ (second version), then $\kappa $ is a strong cardinal.

Proof Let C be the class of all ordinals $\alpha <\kappa $ of uncountable cofinality such that $\alpha $ is the $\alpha $ -th element of $C^{(1)}$ . Let $\mathcal {C}$ be the -definable class of all structures

$$ \begin{align*} {\mathcal A}_{\alpha}:=\langle V_{\lambda_{\alpha}}, \in , \alpha \rangle, \end{align*} $$

where $\alpha \in C$ , and $\lambda _{\alpha }$ is the least cardinal in $C^{(1)}$ greater than $\alpha $

Note that, since by Proposition 5.1, $\kappa \in C^{(2)}$ , $\kappa $ is a limit point of C.

Pick any $\gamma $ in C greater than $\kappa $ . We will show that $\kappa $ is $\gamma $ -strong. By $\mathrm {PSR}$ there is a faithful $\subseteq $ -chain-preserving elementary embedding , where S is some set with $({\mathcal C} \cap V_{\kappa }) \cup \{{\mathcal A}_{\gamma }\}\subseteq S$ .

Now pick any ${\mathcal A}_{\beta } \in {\mathcal C} \cap S$ and let

be the projection map. Let $I:=C\cap \kappa $ and define

$$ \begin{align*} k_{\beta}:V_{\kappa +1}\to V_{\beta+1} \end{align*} $$

by

$$ \begin{align*} k_{\beta}(X)=h_{\beta} ( j(\{ X\cap V_{\alpha}\}_{\alpha \in I})). \end{align*} $$

Since j is elementary, for all formulas $\varphi (x_1,\ldots ,x_n)$ and all

, if

, then

It easily follows that $k_{\beta }$ preserves Boolean operations, the subset relation, and is the identity on $\omega +1$ .

Note that $k_{\beta }(\kappa )=h_{\beta }( j(\{ \alpha \}_{\alpha \in I}))= \beta .$

For each $a\in [\beta ]^{<\omega }$ , define $E^{\beta }_a$ by

$$ \begin{align*}X\in E^{\beta}_a \quad \mbox{ iff }\quad X\subseteq [\kappa]^{|a|} \mbox{ and } a\in k_{\beta}(X)\, .\end{align*} $$

Since $k_{\beta }(\kappa )=\beta $ and $k_{\beta }(|a|)=|a|$ , we also have $k_{\beta }([\kappa ]^{|a|})=[\beta ]^{|a|}$ , hence $[\kappa ]^{|a|} \in E^{\beta }_a$ . Since $k_{\beta }$ preserves Boolean operations and the $\subseteq $ relation, $E^{\beta }_a$ is a proper ultrafilter over $[\kappa ]^{|a|}$ . Moreover, since $k_{\beta }(\omega )=\omega $ , a simple argument shows that $E^{\beta }_a$ is $\omega _1$ -complete, hence the ultrapower $\mathrm {{Ult}}(V,E^{\beta }_a)$ is well-founded. Furthermore, since j is faithful, if $\beta <\kappa $ , then $E^{\beta }_a$ is the principal ultrafilter generated by $\{ a\}$ . Let

$$ \begin{align*}j^{\beta}_a:V\to M^{\beta}_a \cong \mathrm{{Ult}}(V, E^{\beta}_a),\end{align*} $$

with $M_a^{\beta }$ transitive, be the corresponding ultrapower embedding. Note that if $\beta <\kappa $ , then $M^{\beta }_a=V$ and $j^{\beta }_a$ is the identity.

Let $\mathcal {E}_{\beta }:=\{ E^{\beta }_a: a\in [\beta ]^{<\omega }\}$ . As in [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9], one can show that $\mathcal {E}_{\beta }$ is normal and coherent. Thus, for each $a\subseteq b$ in $[\beta ]^{<\omega }$ the maps $i^{\beta }_{ab}:M^{\beta }_a\to M^{\beta }_b$ given by

for all $f:[\kappa ]^{|a|}\to V$ , are well-defined and commute with the ultrapower embeddings $j^{\beta }_a$ (see [Reference Kanamori15, p. 26]).

Let $M_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta }}$ be the direct limit of the directed system

$$ \begin{align*}\langle \langle M^{\beta}_a:a\in [\beta]^{<\omega}\rangle, \langle i^{\beta}_{ab}:a\subseteq b\rangle\rangle,\end{align*} $$

and let $j_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta }} :V\to M_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta }}$ be the corresponding direct limit elementary embedding, i.e.,

$$ \begin{align*}j_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta}}(x)=[a,[c^a_x]_{E^{\beta}_a}]_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta}}\end{align*} $$

for some (any) $a\in [\beta ]^{<\omega }$ , and where $c^a_x:[\kappa ]^{|a|}\to \{ x\}$ .

As in [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9] one can also show that $M_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta }}$ is well-founded. So, let be the transitive collapse, and let $j_{N_{\beta }}:V\to N_{\beta }$ be the corresponding elementary embedding, i.e., . Then, as in [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9] we can show that $V_{\beta } \subseteq N_{\beta }$ and $j_{N_{\beta }}(\kappa )\geq \beta $ . If $\beta>\kappa $ , this implies that $\mathrm {crit}(j_{N_{\beta }})\leq \kappa $ . (If $\beta <\kappa $ , then $j_{N_{\beta }}:V\to V$ is the identity.)

Let $I_S:=\{ \beta : {\mathcal A}_{\beta } \in {\mathcal C} \cap S\}$ .

Claim 5.12. If $\beta \leq \beta '$ are in $I_S$ , then $E^{\beta }_a = E^{\beta '}_a$ , for every $a\in [\beta ]^{<\omega }$ .

Proof of claim

Since $E^{\beta }_a, E^{\beta '}_a$ are proper ultrafilters over $[\kappa ]^{|a|}$ , it is sufficient to see that $E^{\beta }_a\subseteq E^{\beta '}_a$ . So, suppose $X\in E^{\beta }_a$ . Then $a\in k_{\beta }(X)=h_{\beta } (j(\{ X\cap V_{\alpha }\}_{\alpha \in I}))$ . Since $\{ X\cap V_{\alpha }\}_{\alpha \in I}$ forms a $\subseteq $ -chain and j is $\subseteq $ -chain-preserving, so does $j(\{ X\cap V_{\alpha }\}_{\alpha \in I})$ . Hence, $k_{\beta } (X)\subseteq k_{\beta '}(X)$ , and therefore $a\in k_{\beta '}(X)$ , which yields $X\in E^{\beta '}_a$ .

By the claim above, for every $\beta <\beta '$ in $I_S$ the map

$$ \begin{align*}k_{\beta ,\beta'}:M_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta}}\to M_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta'}}\end{align*} $$

given by

$$ \begin{align*}k_{\beta ,\beta'}([a, [f]_{E^{\beta}_a}]_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta}})=[a,[f]_{E^{\beta'}_a}]_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta'}}\end{align*} $$

is well-defined and elementary. Moreover, it commutes with the embeddings $j_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta }}:V\to M_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta }}$ and $j_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta '}}:V\to M_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta '}}$ . Let M be the direct limit of

$$ \begin{align*}\langle \langle M_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta}}:\beta \in I' \rangle, \langle k_{\beta, \beta '}: \beta <\beta' \mbox{ in }I_S\rangle\rangle,\end{align*} $$

and let $j_M :V\to M$ be the corresponding direct limit elementary embedding, which is given by

$$ \begin{align*}j_M(x)=[\beta , [a,[c^a_x]_{E^{\beta}_a}]_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta}}]\end{align*} $$

for some (any) $a\in [\beta ]^{<\omega }$ . Let be the transitive collapse, and let .

Let $\xi =\mbox {sup}(I_S)$ . Note that, as $\gamma \in I_S$ , $\xi>\kappa $ .

Claim 5.13. $j_N(\kappa )=\xi .$

Proof of claim

As in [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9], we can show that $j_{N_{\beta }}(\kappa )\geq \beta $ , for every $\beta \in I_S\setminus \kappa $ . So, for such a $\beta $ , letting $\ell _{\beta ,N}$ be the unique elementary embedding such that $j_N=\ell _{\beta ,N}\circ j_{N_{\beta }}$ , we have

$$ \begin{align*}j_N(\kappa)=\ell_{\beta,N}(j_{N_{\beta}}(\kappa))\geq \ell_{\beta , N}(\beta)\geq \beta.\end{align*} $$

Hence, $j_N(\kappa )\geq \xi $ . Also, $j_{E^{\beta }_a}(\kappa )$ can be computed in $V_{\beta }$ , for all $a\in [\beta ]^{<\omega }$ , and therefore $j_{N_{\beta }}(\kappa )\leq \beta $ . Hence, $j_N(\kappa )\leq \xi $ .

Since $\kappa <\xi $ , it follows from the claim above that $\mathrm {crit}(j_N)\leq \kappa $ . But since for $\beta <\kappa $ the map $j_{N_{\beta }}$ is the identity, we must have $\mathrm {crit}(j_N)=\kappa $ . Also, since $\gamma \in I_S$ , $V_{\gamma } \subseteq N_{\gamma }$ , hence $V_{\gamma }\subseteq N$ . This shows that $\kappa $ is $\gamma $ -strong, as wanted.

From Proposition 5.2 and Theorem 5.11 we obtain now the following characterization of strong cardinals.

Corollary 5.14. A cardinal $\kappa $ is strong if and only if it witnesses - $\mathrm {PSR}$ (second version).

Similar results can be proven for $\Gamma $ -strong cardinals (Definition 5.5). On the one hand, Proposition 5.6 shows that if $\kappa $ is -strong, then $\kappa $ witnesses - $\mathrm {PSR}$ . On the other hand, similarly as in Theorem 5.11, we can prove that if $\kappa $ witnesses - $\mathrm {PSR}$ , then $\kappa $ is -strong. This yields the following characterization of -strong cardinals:

Theorem 5.15. For every $n>0$ , a cardinal $\kappa $ is -strong if and only if it witnesses - $\mathrm {PSR}$ (second version).

5.1 Strong Product Structural Reflection

Let us consider next the following, arguably more natural, strengthening of $\mathrm {PSR}$ :

  1. SPSR: (Strong Product Structural Reflection) For every definable class of relational structures $\mathcal {C}$ of the same type, $\tau $ , there exists an ordinal $\alpha $ that strongly product-reflects $\mathcal {C}$ , i.e., for every ${\mathcal A}$ in $\mathcal {C}$ there exist an ordinal $\beta $ with ${\mathcal A} \in V_{\beta }$ and an elementary embedding .

Similarly as in the case of $\mathrm {PSR}$ , let us say that a cardinal $\kappa $ witnesses $\Gamma (P)$ - $\mathrm {SPSR}$ if $\kappa $ strongly product-reflects all classes ${\mathcal C}$ that are $\Gamma $ -definable (with parameters in P). Also, a cardinal $\kappa $ witnesses - $\mathrm {SPSR}$ if and only if it witnesses $\mathbf {\Sigma _{n+1}}$ - $\mathrm {SPSR}$ , and similarly for the lightface definability classes. Moreover, we obtain equivalent principles by restricting to classes of natural structures. Thus, we may formally define $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {SPSR}$ , for $\Gamma $ a lightface definability class, as follows:

  1. Γ-SPSR: ( $\Gamma $ -Strong Product Structural Reflection) There exists a cardinal $\kappa $ that strongly product-reflects all $\Gamma $ -definable classes ${\mathcal C}$ of natural structures.

The boldface version is as follows:

  • There exists a proper class of cardinals $\kappa $ that strongly product-reflect all $\Gamma $ -definable, with parameters in $V_{\kappa }$ , class ${\mathcal C}$ of natural structures.

Note that $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {SPSR}$ implies $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {PSR}$ , for any definability class $\Gamma $ .

We shall see next that the large cardinal notions that correspond to the $\mathrm {SPSR}$ principle are those of superstrong, globally superstrong, and $C^{(n)}$ -globally superstrong cardinals.

Definition 5.16 [Reference Cai and Tsaprounis10].

A cardinal $\kappa $ is superstrong above $\lambda $ , for some $\lambda \geq \kappa $ , if there exists an elementary embedding $j:V\to M$ , with M transitive, $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\kappa $ , $j(\kappa )>\lambda $ , and $V_{j(\kappa )}\subseteq M$ .

A cardinal $\kappa $ is globally superstrong if it is superstrong above $\lambda $ , for every $\lambda \geq \kappa $ .

More generally, a cardinal $\kappa $ is $C^{(n)}$ -superstrong above $\lambda $ , for some $\lambda \geq \kappa $ , if there exists an elementary embedding $j:V\to M$ , with M transitive, $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\kappa $ , $j(\kappa )>\lambda $ , $V_{j(\kappa )}\subseteq M$ , and $j(\kappa )\in C^{(n)}$ .

A cardinal $\kappa $ is $C^{(n)}$ -globally superstrong if it is $C^{(n)}$ -superstrong above $\lambda $ , for every $\lambda \geq \kappa $ .

Note that every globally superstrong cardinal is $C^{(1)}$ -globally superstrong. Also, every globally superstrong cardinal is superstrong, and every $C^{(n)}$ -globally superstrong cardinal belongs to $C^{(n+2)}$ [Reference Cai and Tsaprounis10]. As shown in [Reference Cai and Tsaprounis10], on the one hand, if $\kappa $ is $C^{(n)}$ -globally superstrong, then there are many $C^{(n)}$ -superstrong cardinals below $\kappa $ . On the other hand, if $\kappa $ is ( $\kappa +1$ )-extendible, then $V_{\kappa }$ satisfies that there is a proper class of $C^{(n)}$ -globally superstrong cardinals, for every n. Moreover, if $\kappa $ is $C^{(n)}$ -extendible, then there are many $C^{(n)}$ -globally superstrong cardinals below $\kappa $ .

Similarly as in Proposition 5.2 we can prove the following:

Proposition 5.17. If $\kappa $ is $C^{(n)}$ -globally superstrong, then it witnesses - $\mathrm {SPSR}$ .

Proof Let $\kappa $ be $C^{(n)}$ -globally superstrong and let ${\mathcal C}$ be a class of relational structures of the same type that is definable by a formula $\varphi (x)$ , with parameters in $V_{\kappa }$ .

Given any $\mathcal {A}\in {\mathcal C}$ , let $\lambda \in C^{(n)}$ be greater than or equal to $\kappa $ and with $\mathcal {A}\in V_{\lambda }$ .

Let $j:V\to M$ be an elementary embedding witnessing that $\kappa $ is $C^{(n)}$ -superstrong above $\lambda $ . Then the restriction of j to ${\mathcal C} \cap V_{\kappa }$ yields an elementary embedding

Let $S:= \{ X: M\models \varphi (X)\} \cap V^M_{j(\kappa )}$ . Since $j(\kappa )>\lambda $ and $j(\kappa )\in C^{(n)}$ , we have $V_{j(\kappa )}\models \varphi ({\mathcal A})$ . Hence, since $\kappa \in C^{(n)}$ (in fact $\kappa \in C^{(n+2)}$ ) [Reference Cai and Tsaprounis10], by elementarity

, and thus $M\models \varphi ({\mathcal A})$ . It follows that ${\mathcal A} \in S$ . Moreover, if ${\mathcal B}\in S$ , then $M\models \varphi ({\mathcal B})$ . Hence, since

, we have that $V_{j(\kappa )}^M=V_{j(\kappa )}\models \varphi ({\mathcal B})$ . Since $j(\kappa )\in C^{(n)}$ , $\varphi ({\mathcal B})$ holds in V, and therefore ${\mathcal B} \in {\mathcal C}$ . This shows that $S={\mathcal C} \cap V_{j(\kappa )}$ , and so

Hence, h witnesses $\mathrm {SPSR}$ for ${\mathcal A}$ .

Observe that since the function h in the proof of the last proposition is the restriction of j to , and j is elementary, it preserves all first-order properties. In particular, it is $\subseteq $ -chain-preserving, and since $\kappa =\mathrm {crit} (j)$ , h is faithful. Thus, taking into consideration our remarks from Section 2, as well as those made in the previous section before we stated the second version of the $\mathrm {PSR}$ schema, we may reformulate $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {SPSR}$ for $\Gamma $ a lightface definability class as follows:

  1. Γ-SPSR: ( $\Gamma $ -Strong Product Structural Reflection. Second version) There exists a cardinal $\kappa $ that strongly product-reflects all $\Gamma $ -definable classes ${\mathcal C}$ of natural structures, i.e., for every ${\mathcal A}\in {\mathcal C}$ there exist an ordinal $\beta $ with ${\mathcal A} \in V_{\beta }$ and a faithful and $\subseteq $ -chain-preserving elementary embedding .

The corresponding version for boldface $\Gamma $ being:

  • There exists a proper class of cardinals $\kappa $ that strongly product-reflect all $\Gamma $ -definable, with parameters in $V_{\kappa }$ , proper classes ${\mathcal C}$ of natural structures.

Arguing similarly as in the proof of Theorem 5.11 (and [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9]), we can now prove the following:

Theorem 5.18. For every $n>0$ , there is a -definable, without parameters, class ${\mathcal C}$ of natural structures such that if a cardinal $\kappa $ strongly product-reflects ${\mathcal C}$ , then $\kappa $ is a $C^{(n)}$ -globally superstrong cardinal.

Proof Let $\mathcal {C}$ be the -definable class of all structures

$$ \begin{align*} {\mathcal A}_{\alpha}:=\langle V_{\lambda_{\alpha}}, \in , \alpha \rangle, \end{align*} $$

where $\alpha $ has uncountable cofinality and is the $\alpha $ -th element of $C^{(n)}$ , and $\lambda _{\alpha }$ is the least cardinal in $C^{(n)}$ greater than $\alpha $ .

Let $\kappa $ witness $\mathrm {SPSR}$ for ${\mathcal C}$ . Let $I:=\{ \alpha :{\mathcal A}_{\alpha } \in V_{\kappa } \}$ . Since $\kappa \in C^{(n+1)}$ (Proposition 5.1), $\mathrm {{sup}}(I)=\kappa $ .

Pick any ordinal $\lambda \geq \kappa $ and let us show that $\kappa $ is $\lambda $ - $C^{(n)}$ -superstrong. Let ${\mathcal A}_{\beta }$ in ${\mathcal C}$ with $\lambda <\beta $ . Let $\kappa '$ be such that ${\mathcal A}_{\beta } \in V_{\kappa '}$ and there is a faithful $\subseteq $ -chain-preserving elementary embedding

Let

be the projection map and define $k_{\beta }:V_{\kappa +1}\to V_{\beta +1}$ by

$$ \begin{align*} k_{\beta}(X)=h_{\beta} ( j(\{ X\cap V_{\alpha}\}_{\alpha \in I})). \end{align*} $$

As in Theorem 5.11, for each $a\in [\beta ]^{<\omega }$ , define $E^{\beta }_a$ by

$$ \begin{align*} X\in E^{\beta}_a \quad \mbox{ iff }\quad X\subseteq [\kappa]^{|a|} \mbox{ and } a\in k_{\beta}(X)\,. \end{align*} $$

Then $E^{\beta }_a$ is an $\omega _1$ -complete proper ultrafilter over $[\kappa ]^{|a|}$ , and so the ultrapower $\mathrm {{Ult}}(V,E^{\beta }_a)$ is well-founded. Furthermore, since j is faithful, if $\beta \in I$ , then $E^{\beta }_a$ is the principal ultrafilter generated by $\{ a\}$ . Let

$$ \begin{align*}j^{\beta}_a:V\to M^{\beta}_a \cong \mathrm{{Ult}}(V, E^{\beta}_a),\end{align*} $$

and let $\mathcal {E}_{\beta }:=\{ E^{\beta }_a: a\in [\beta ]^{<\omega }\}$ . As in [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9], $\mathcal {E}_{\beta }$ is normal and coherent. Let $M_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta }}$ be the direct limit of

$$ \begin{align*} \langle \langle M^{\beta}_a:a\in [\beta]^{<\omega}\rangle, \langle i^{\beta}_{ab}:a\subseteq b\rangle\rangle, \end{align*} $$

where the $i_{ab}^{\beta }$ are the standard projection maps, and let $j_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta }} :V\to M_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta }}$ be the corresponding limit elementary embedding. As in [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9], $M_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta }}$ is well-founded. So, let

be the transitive collapse, and let

. We have that $V_{\beta } \subseteq N_{\beta }$ and $j_{N_{\beta }}(\kappa )\geq \beta $ (see [Reference Bagaria and Wilson9]).

By Claim 5.12, if $\beta \leq \beta '$ are in $I':=\{\alpha : {\mathcal A}_{\alpha } \in V_{\kappa '}\}$ , then $E^{\beta }_a = E^{\beta '}_a$ , for every $a\in [\beta ]^{<\omega }$ . Hence, for every $\beta <\beta '$ in $I'$ , the map

$$ \begin{align*} k_{\beta ,\beta'}:M_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta}}\to M_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta'}} \end{align*} $$

given by

$$ \begin{align*} k_{\beta ,\beta'}([a, [f]_{E_a}]_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta}})=[a,[f]_{E_a}]_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta'}} \end{align*} $$

is well-defined, elementary, and commutes with the embeddings $j_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta }}:V\to M_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta }}$ and $j_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta '}}:V\to M_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta '}}$ . Let M be the direct limit of

$$ \begin{align*} \langle \langle M_{{\mathcal E}_{\beta}}:\beta \in I' \rangle, \langle k_{\beta, \beta '}: \beta <\beta' \mbox{ in }I'\rangle\rangle, \end{align*} $$

and let $j_M :V\to M$ be the corresponding limit elementary embedding. Let be the transitive collapse, and let .

Let $\xi =\mbox {sup}(I')$ . Note that $\xi \in C^{(n)}$ and $\xi>\kappa $ . As in Claim 5.13, $j_N(\kappa )=\xi $ , hence $\mathrm {crit}(j_N)\leq \kappa $ . But since for $\beta \in I$ the map $j_{N_{\beta }}$ is the identity, $\mathrm {crit}(j_N)=\kappa $ . Also, since $V_{\xi }=\bigcup _{\beta \in I}V_{\beta }$ , and $V_{\beta } \subseteq N_{\beta }$ for all $\beta \in I$ , it follows that $V_{\xi }\subseteq N$ . This shows that $\kappa $ is $\xi $ -superstrong, hence also $\lambda $ - $C^{(n)}$ -superstrong, as wanted.

We have thus proved the following:

Theorem 5.19. For every $n\geq 1$ , the following are equivalent for any cardinal $\kappa $ :

  1. (1) $\kappa $ witnesses - $\mathrm {SPSR}.$

  2. (2) $\kappa $ is a $C^{(n)}$ -globally superstrong cardinal.

Corollary 5.20. The following are equivalent:

  1. (1) $\mathrm {SPSR}$ , i.e., - $\mathrm {SPSR}$ for every n.

  2. (2) - $\mathrm {SPSR}$ for every n.

  3. (3) There exists a $C^{(n)}$ -globally superstrong cardinal, for every n.

  4. (4) There exists a proper class of $C^{(n)}$ -globally superstrong cardinals.

5.2 Bounded Product Structural Reflection

Let us consider next some bounded forms of $\mathrm {PSR}$ . Namely, for $\Gamma $ a lightface definability class and any ordinal $\beta $ let:

  1. Γ-PSRβ: There exists a cardinal $\kappa $ that $\beta $ -product-reflects every $\Gamma $ -definable proper class ${\mathcal C}$ of natural structures, i.e., for every ${\mathcal A}$ in ${\mathcal C}$ of rank $\leq \kappa +\beta $ there exist a set S with ${\mathcal A}$ in S and an elementary embedding .

Thus $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {PSR}$ holds if and only if there exists a cardinal $\kappa $ that witnesses $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {PSR}_{\beta }$ for all (equivalently, a proper class of) ordinals $\beta $ .

The following theorem shows that measurable cardinals can be characterized in terms of bounded $\mathrm {PSR}$ .

Theorem 5.21. The following are equivalent:

  1. (1) - $\mathrm {PSR}_1.$

  2. (2) There exists a measurable cardinal.

Proof (1) implies (2): Let ${\mathcal C}$ be the

-definable class of $\langle V_{\gamma }, \in \rangle $ , $\gamma \geq \omega $ . Let $\kappa $ witness $\mathrm {PSR}_1$ for ${\mathcal C}$ , and let S be a set that contains $V_{\kappa +1}$ such that there exists an elementary embedding

Define $k:V_{\kappa +1}\to V_{\kappa +2}$ by

$$ \begin{align*}k(X)=h_{\kappa +1}(h(\{ X\cap V_{\gamma}\}_{\gamma <\kappa})),\end{align*} $$

where $h_{\kappa +1}$ is the projection on $V_{\kappa +1}$ . Then k preserves Boolean operations and the subset relation, and is the identity on $\omega +1$ . Moreover, $k(\kappa )=\kappa +1$ . Now for each $a\in V_{\kappa +1}$ , define ${\mathcal U}_a$ by

$$ \begin{align*}X\in{\mathcal U}_a \quad \mbox{ iff }\quad X\subseteq \kappa \mbox{ and } a \in k(X)\, .\end{align*} $$

Clearly, $\kappa \in {\mathcal U}_a$ . Also, since k preserves Boolean operations and the $\subseteq $ relation, ${\mathcal U}_a$ is a proper ultrafilter over $\kappa $ . Moreover, since $k(\omega )=\omega $ , ${\mathcal U}_a$ is $\omega _1$ -complete. Furthermore, since $|V_{\kappa +1}|=2^{|V_{\kappa } | }> |\kappa |$ , some ${\mathcal U}_a$ is non-principal. So, some cardinal less than or equal to $\kappa $ is measurable.

(2) implies (1): Let $\kappa $ be a measurable cardinal, and let $\varphi (x)$ be a formula (we may allow parameters in $V_{\kappa }$ ) that defines a proper class ${\mathcal C}$ of natural structures. We claim that $\kappa \ 1$ -product-reflects ${\mathcal C}$ .

Let $j:V\to M$ be an ultrapower elementary embedding, given by some $\kappa $ -complete normal measure over $\kappa $ . Thus, $\mathrm {crit} (j)=\kappa $ and $V_{\kappa + 1}^M=V_{\kappa +1}$ . By elementarity, the restriction of j to ${\mathcal C} \cap V_{\kappa }$ yields an elementary embedding

Let $S:= \{ X: M\models \varphi (X)\} \cap V^M_{j(\kappa )}$ . If $\mathcal {A}=\langle V_{\gamma } ,\in \rangle \in {\mathcal C}$ , with $\gamma \leq \kappa +1$ , then ${\mathcal A} \in M$ , and since $\varphi ({\mathcal A})$ holds in V, by

downward absoluteness for transitive classes it also holds in M. Moreover, since $j(\kappa )>\kappa +1$ , ${\mathcal A} \in V^M_{j(\kappa )}$ , hence ${\mathcal A}\in S$ .

Let us note that the proof of the theorem above also shows that the least measurable cardinal is precisely the least cardinal $\kappa $ that witnesses $\mathrm {PSR}_1$ for all classes ${\mathcal C}$ that are -definable with parameters in $V_{\kappa }$ .

6 Large cardinals below measurability

We shall next consider Structural Reflection for classes of relational structures that are $\Sigma _1$ -definable in the language of set theory extended with additional predicates. That is, classes of structures of complexity between $\Sigma _1$ and $\Sigma _2$ .

Let ${\mathcal R}$ be a set of predicates or relations. A class ${\mathcal C}$ of structures in a fixed countable relational type is said to be $\Sigma _1({\mathcal R})$ -definable if it is definable by means of a $\Sigma _1$ formula of the first-order language of set theory with additional predicate symbols for the predicates in ${\mathcal R}$ , without parameters. We define the following form of $\mathrm {SR}$ :

  1. Σ 1(ℛ)-SR: For every $\Sigma _1({\mathcal R})$ -definable class ${\mathcal C}$ of structures of the same type there exists a cardinal $\kappa $ that reflects $\mathcal {C}$ , i.e., for every A in $\mathcal {C}$ there exist B in $\mathcal {C}\cap V_{\kappa }$ and an elementary embedding from B into A.

For the rest of this section we shall write $\mathrm {SR}_{\mathcal R}$ instead of the more cumbersome $\Sigma _1({\mathcal R})$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ . Also, if ${\mathcal R}=\{ R_1,\ldots ,R_n\}$ , then we may write $\mathrm { SR}_{R_1,\ldots ,R_n}$ for $\mathrm {SR}_{\mathcal R}$ .

We have that $\mathrm {SR}_{\varnothing }$ , i.e., $\Sigma _1$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ , is provable in ZFC (Proposition 3.1). However, if R is the relation “x is an ordinal and $y=V_x$ ,” then $\mathrm {SR}_R$ holds if and only if there exists a supercompact cardinal ([Reference Bagaria2, Reference Bagaria, Casacuberta, Mathias and Rosický3]; see also Theorem 3.2). Moreover, if $\kappa $ is supercompact, then $\mathrm {SR}_{\mathcal R}$ holds for $\kappa $ , for any set ${\mathcal R}$ of predicates (cf. Theorem 3.2).

6.1 The principle $\mathrm {SR}^-_{\mathcal R}$

For $\Gamma $ any lightface definability class, the following is a natural restricted form of $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {SR}$ :

  1. Γ-SR: There exists a cardinal $\kappa $ such that for every $\Gamma $ -definable class ${\mathcal C}$ of structures of the same type and every $A\in {\mathcal C}$ of cardinality $\kappa $ there exist $B\in {\mathcal C}\cap H_{\kappa }$ and an elementary embedding from B into A. We say that the cardinal $\kappa \ \kappa $ -reflects $\mathcal {C}$ .

The restriction of $\mathrm {SR}^-$ to $\Sigma _1(\mathcal {R})$ -definable classes of structures was first introduced in [Reference Bagaria and Väänänen8]. Namely, for ${\mathcal R}$ a finite set of predicates or relations, let

  1. SR : There exists a cardinal $\kappa $ that $\kappa $ -reflects every $\Sigma _1({\mathcal R})$ -definable (with parameters in $H_{\kappa }$ ) class ${\mathcal C}$ of structures of the same type.

6.1.1 The Cardinality predicate

Let $\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d}$ be the predicate $"x$ is a cardinal.” Magidor and Väänänen [Reference Magidor and Väänänen25] show that the principle $\mathrm {SR}_{\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d}}$ implies $0^{\sharp }$ , and much more, e.g., there are no good scales. The principle $\mathrm {SR}^-_{\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d}}$ is much weaker, but it does have some large-cardinal strength, as the next theorem shows.

Theorem 6.1 [Reference Bagaria and Väänänen8].

$\mathrm {SR}^-_{\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d}}$ holds, witnessed by $\kappa $ , then there exists a weakly inaccessible cardinal $\lambda \leq \kappa $ .

It is shown in [Reference Magidor and Väänänen25] that, starting form a supercompact cardinal, one can produce a model of ZFC in which $\mathrm {SR}_{\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d}}$ holds for the first weakly inaccessible cardinal. Thus, no large-cardinal properties beyond weak inaccessibility may be proved in ZFC to hold for the least cardinal witnessing $\mathrm {SR}_{\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d}}$ .

6.1.2 The Regularity predicate

Let $\mathop {R\hspace {-0.8pt}g}$ be the predicate “x is a regular ordinal.”

Theorem 6.2 [Reference Bagaria and Väänänen8].

If $\mathrm {SR}^-_{\mathop {R\hspace {-0.8pt}g}}$ holds, witnessed by $\kappa $ , then there exists a weakly Mahlo cardinal $\lambda \leq \kappa $ .

It follows from [Reference Magidor and Väänänen25] that one cannot hope to get from $\mathrm {SR}_{\mathop {R\hspace {-0.8pt}g}}$ more than a weakly Mahlo cardinal $\leq \kappa $ , for starting from a weakly Mahlo cardinal one can obtain a model in which $\mathrm {SR}_{\mathop {R\hspace {-0.8pt}g}}$ is witnessed by the least weakly Mahlo cardinal. One cannot hope either to show that the least $\kappa $ witnessing $\mathrm { SR}_{\mathop {R\hspace {-0.8pt}g}}$ is strongly inaccessible, for in [Reference Stavi and Väänänen34] it is shown that one can have $\mathrm {SR}_{\mathop {R\hspace {-0.8pt}g}}$ witnessed by $\kappa =2^{\aleph _0}$ .

Let us note that, since the predicate $\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d}$ is $\Sigma _1(\mathop {R\hspace {-0.8pt}g})$ -definable (see [Reference Bagaria and Väänänen8]), the principle $\mathrm {SR}_{\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d} ,\mathop {R\hspace {-0.8pt}g}}$ is equivalent to $\mathrm {SR}_{\mathop {R\hspace {-0.8pt}g}}$ .

6.1.3 The Weakly Inaccessible predicate

There is a principle between $\mathrm {SR}^-_{\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d}}$ and $\mathrm {SR}^-_{\mathop {R\hspace {-0.8pt}g}}$ , namely $\mathrm {SR}^-_{\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d}, \mathop {W\!I}}$ , where $\mathop {W\!I}$ is the predicate “x is weakly inaccessible.”

Proposition 6.3 [Reference Bagaria and Väänänen8].

If $\mathrm {SR}^-_{\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d}, \mathop {W\!I}}$ holds, witnessed by $\kappa $ , then there exists a $2$ -weakly inaccessible cardinal $\lambda \leq \kappa $ .

We may also consider predicates $\alpha $ - $\mathop {W\!I}$ , for $\alpha $ an ordinal. That is, the predicate “x is $\alpha $ -weakly inaccessible.” Then, similar arguments as in [Reference Bagaria and Väänänen8] would show that the principle $\mathrm {SR}^-_{\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d}, \, \alpha \,\mbox {-} \mathop {W\!I}}$ holding for $\kappa $ implies that there is an $(\alpha +1)$ -weakly inaccessible cardinal $\lambda \leq \kappa $ .

6.1.4 Weak compactness

Let $\mathop {W\!C}(x,\alpha )$ be the relation “ $\alpha $ is a limit ordinal and x is a partial ordering with no chain of order-type $\alpha $ .”

Theorem 6.4 [Reference Bagaria and Väänänen8].

If $\mathrm {SR}^-_{\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d}, \mathop {W\!C}}$ holds, witnessed by some $\kappa $ such that if $\gamma \leq \kappa $ is weakly inaccessible, then $2^{\delta } \leq \gamma $ for all cardinals $\delta <\gamma $ , then there exists a weakly compact cardinal $\lambda \leq \kappa $ .Footnote 5

Since the first weakly Mahlo cardinal may satisfy $\mathrm {SR}_{\mathop {R\hspace {-0.8pt}g}}$ [Reference Magidor and Väänänen25], we cannot prove the existence of a weakly compact cardinal $\leq \kappa $ just from $\mathrm { SR}_{\mathop {R\hspace {-0.8pt}g}}$ . Hence, $\mathrm {SR}_{\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d}, \mathop {W\!C}}$ is stronger than $\mathrm {SR}_{\mathop {R\hspace {-0.8pt}g}}$ .

Let $\mathop {P\hspace {-0.8pt}w\hspace {-0.8pt}S\hspace {-0.8pt}e\hspace {-0.8pt}t}$ be the relation $\{ (x,y): y=\mathcal {P}(x)\}$ . Then we have the following:

Theorem 6.5 [Reference Magidor24].

$\kappa $ is the least cardinal witnessing $\mathrm {SR}_{\mathop {P\hspace {-0.8pt}w\hspace {-0.8pt}S\hspace {-0.8pt}e\hspace {-0.8pt}t}}$ if and only if $\kappa $ is the first supercompact cardinal.

It follows from Theorem 3.2 that $\mathrm {SR}_{\mathop {P\hspace {-0.8pt}w\hspace {-0.8pt}S\hspace {-0.8pt}e\hspace {-0.8pt}t}}$ is in fact equivalent to - $\mathrm {SR}$ , and also equivalent to $\Sigma _2$ - $\mathrm {SR}$ . However, Lücke [Reference Lücke23] has established that $\mathrm {SR}^-_{\mathop {P\hspace {-0.8pt}w\hspace {-0.8pt}S\hspace {-0.8pt}e\hspace {-0.8pt}t}}$ is much weaker than $\mathrm { SR}_{\mathop {P\hspace {-0.8pt}w\hspace {-0.8pt}S\hspace {-0.8pt}e\hspace {-0.8pt}t}}$ . Indeed, he shows that $\mathrm {SR}^-_{\mathop {P\hspace {-0.8pt}w\hspace {-0.8pt}S\hspace {-0.8pt}e\hspace {-0.8pt}t}}$ is equivalent to the existence of a weakly shrewd cardinal, a large cardinal notion obtained by weakening the definition of shrewd cardinal studied by Rathjen in [Reference Rathjen28] and whose consistency strength is strictly between the large cardinal notions of total indescribability and subtleness. However, as shown in [Reference Lücke23], shrewd and weakly shrewd cardinal are equiconsistent.

Definition 6.6 [Reference Lücke23].

A cardinal $\kappa $ is weakly shrewd if for every formula $\varphi (x,y)$ of the language of set theory, every cardinal $\theta>\kappa $ , and every $A\subseteq \kappa $ such that $\varphi (A,\kappa )$ holds in $H_{\theta }$ , there exist cardinals $\bar {\kappa } <\bar {\theta }$ such that $\bar {\kappa }<\kappa $ and $\varphi (A\cap \bar {\kappa }, \bar {\kappa })$ holds in $H_{\bar {\theta }}$ .

Theorem 6.7 [Reference Lücke23].

The following are equivalent:

  1. (1) $\kappa $ is the least weakly shrewd cardinal.

  2. (2) $\kappa $ is the least cardinal witnessing $\mathrm {SR}^-_{\mathop {P\hspace {-0.8pt}w\hspace {-0.8pt}S\hspace {-0.8pt}e\hspace {-0.8pt}t}}$ .

  3. (3) $\kappa $ is the least cardinal witnessing $\Sigma _2$ - $\mathrm {SR}^-$ .

Since, as shown in [Reference Lücke23], weakly shrewd cardinals may be smaller than $2^{\aleph _0}$ , the principle $\Sigma _2$ - $\mathrm {SR}^-$ , and therefore also $\mathrm {SR}^-_{\mathcal {R}}$ , for any set $\mathcal {R}$ of predicates, does not imply the existence of a strongly inaccessible cardinal. Moreover, [Reference Lücke23] shows that it is consistent, modulo the existence of a weakly shrewd cardinal that is not shrewd (a large cardinal notion consistency-wise weaker than subtleness), that there exists a cardinal less than $2^{\aleph _0}$ witnessing the principle $\mathrm {SR}^-$ for all definable classes of structures of the same type, taken as a schema, i.e., $\Sigma _n$ - $\mathrm {SR}^-$ , for all $n<\omega $ . Thus, even $\mathrm {SR}^-$ cannot imply the existence of a strongly inaccessible cardinal.

6.2 Strong $\Sigma _1(\mathcal {R})$ -definability

Notice that a class ${\mathcal C}$ is $\Sigma _1$ -definable iff there is a $\Sigma _1$ formula $\varphi $ such that for every A, $A\in {\mathcal C}$ if and only if some transitive structure $\langle M,\in \rangle $ that contains A satisfies $\varphi (A)$ . Now let $\mathcal {L}_{\dot {R}}$ be the language of set theory expanded with an additional predicate symbol $\dot {R}$ , and suppose R is a predicate. Naturally, one may define a class ${\mathcal C}$ to be $\Sigma _1(R)$ if it is $\Sigma _1$ -definable in the language $\mathcal {L}_{\dot {R}}$ with $\dot {R}$ being interpreted as R. However, unlike the case of $\Sigma _1$ -definability, this is not equivalent to saying that there is a $\Sigma _1$ formula $\varphi $ of the language $\mathcal {L}_{\dot {R}}$ such that for every A, $A\in {\mathcal C}$ if and only if some transitive structure $\langle M,\in , R^M \rangle $ that contains A satisfies $\varphi (A)$ . For the equivalence to hold we need to require that $R^M$ is precisely $R\cap M$ . Namely,

Proposition 6.8. The following are equivalent for all classes ${\mathcal C}$ and predicates R:

  1. (1) ${\mathcal C}$ is $\Sigma _1(R)$ , i.e., there exists a $\Sigma _1$ formula $\varphi (x)$ of $\mathcal {L}_{\dot {R}}$ such that

    $$ \begin{align*} {\mathcal C}=\{ A:\varphi(A), \mbox{ with } \dot{R} \mbox{ interpreted as } R\}. \end{align*} $$
  2. (2) There is a $\Sigma _1$ formula $\varphi (x)$ of the language $\mathcal {L}_{\dot {R}}$ such that for every A, $A\in {\mathcal C}$ if and only if

    $$ \begin{align*} \langle M,\in, R\cap M \rangle \models \varphi(A)\end{align*} $$

    for some transitive structure $\langle M,\in \rangle $ that contains A.

Notice also that if ${\mathcal C}$ is a $\Sigma _1$ -definable class of structures of the same type, then the closure of ${\mathcal C}$ under isomorphisms is also $\Sigma _1$ -definable, and we have the following equivalences:

Proposition 6.9. The following are equivalent for any class ${\mathcal C}$ of structures of the same type that is closed under isomorphisms:

  1. (1) ${\mathcal C}$ is $\Sigma _1$ .

  2. (2) There is a $\Sigma _1$ formula $\varphi (x)$ of the language of set theory such that for every A, $A\in {\mathcal C}$ if and only if

    $$ \begin{align*} \langle M,\in \rangle \models \varphi(B) \end{align*} $$

    for some transitive structure $\langle M,\in \rangle $ of size $|A|$ that contains B, where B is isomorphic to A.

Based on the considerations above, the following is therefore a natural definition for a class of structures closed under isomorphisms to be $\Sigma _1$ -definable with an additional predicate R. This is a reformulation, for the case $n=1$ , of Lücke’s [Reference Lücke23] definition of local $\Sigma _n(R)$ -class:

Definition 6.10. A class ${\mathcal C}$ of structures of the same type and closed under isomorphisms is $\Sigma _1(R)^{\ast }$ if there is a $\Sigma _1$ formula $\varphi (x)$ of the language $\mathcal {L}_{\dot {R}}$ such that for every A, $A\in {\mathcal C}$ if and only if

$$ \begin{align*} \langle M,\in, R \cap M \rangle \models \varphi(B) \end{align*} $$

for some transitive structure $\langle M,\in \rangle $ of size $|A|$ that contains B, where B is isomorphic to A.

Observe that although every $\Sigma _1(R)^{\ast }$ class ${\mathcal C}$ is $\Sigma _1(R)$ , the converse is not true, even assuming closure under isomorphisms. An example is the class ${\mathcal C}$ of all structures isomorphic to some transitive $\langle M,\in , \mathrm {{Cd}}\cap M\rangle $ , where $\mathrm {{Cd}}$ is the class of cardinals.

The closure under isomorphisms of the $\Sigma _1(\mathcal {R})$ -definable classes of structures that are used in the proofs of Theorems 6.1 and 6.2, Proposition 6.3, and Theorem 6.4 (as given in [Reference Bagaria and Väänänen8]) are easily seen to be $\Sigma _1(\mathcal {R})^{\ast }$ , for the corresponding $\mathcal {R}$ . Thus, the results follow from the weaker $\Sigma _1(\mathcal {R})^{\ast }$ - $\mathrm {SR}^-$ corresponding assumptions. Also, the argument in the proof of Theorem 5.5 from [Reference Bagaria and Väänänen8] can be adapted to show that if $\mathcal {L}^{\ast }$ and $\mathcal {R}$ are symbiotic, then the $SLST(\mathcal {L}^{\ast })$ property implies $\Sigma _1(\mathcal {R})^{\ast }$ - $\mathrm {SR}^-$ (see [Reference Bagaria and Väänänen8]).Footnote 6 Thus, from the results in Section 8 of [Reference Bagaria and Väänänen8] one may obtain the following equivalences:

Theorem 6.11.

  1. (1) [Reference Lücke23] $\kappa $ is the least weakly inaccessible cardinal iff $\kappa $ is the least cardinal witnessing $\Sigma _1(\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d})^{\ast }$ - $\mathrm {SR}^-$ .

  2. (2) [Reference Lücke23] $\kappa $ is the least weakly Mahlo cardinal iff $\kappa $ is the least cardinal witnessing $\Sigma _1(\mathop {R\hspace {-0.8pt}g})^{\ast }$ - $\mathrm {SR}^-$ .

  3. (3) $\kappa $ is the least $\alpha $ -weakly inaccessible cardinal iff $\kappa $ is the least cardinal witnessing $\Sigma _1(\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d}, \alpha $ - $\mathop {W\!I})^{\ast }$ - $\mathrm {SR}^-$ .

  4. (4) Suppose $\kappa $ is such that if $\gamma \leq \kappa $ is weakly inaccessible, then $2^{\delta } \leq \gamma $ for all cardinals $\delta <\gamma $ . Then $\kappa $ is the least weakly compact cardinal iff $\kappa $ is the least cardinal witnessing $\Sigma _1(\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d}, \mathop {W\!C})^{\ast }$ - $\mathrm {SR}^-$ .

Under the assumption of GCH, or just assuming that every weakly inaccessible cardinal is inaccessible, the theorem above yields exact characterizations in terms of $\mathrm {SR}$ for the first inaccessible, Mahlo, $\alpha $ -inaccessible, and weakly compact cardinals.

Corollary 6.12 (GCH).

  1. (1) $\kappa $ is the least inaccessible cardinal iff $\kappa $ is the least cardinal witnessing $\Sigma _1(Cd)^{\ast }$ - $\mathrm {SR}^-$ .

  2. (2) $\kappa $ is the least Mahlo cardinal iff $\kappa $ is the least cardinal witnessing $\Sigma _1(Rg)^{\ast }$ - $\mathrm {SR}^-$ .

  3. (3) $\kappa $ is the least $\alpha $ -inaccessible cardinal iff $\kappa $ is the least cardinal witnessing $\Sigma _1(Cd, \alpha $ - $WI)^{\ast }$ - $\mathrm {SR}^-$ .

  4. (4) $\kappa $ is the least weakly compact cardinal iff $\kappa $ is the least cardinal witnessing $\Sigma _1(Cd, WC)^{\ast }$ - $\mathrm {SR}^-$ .

In items (1)–(4) above one may, equivalently, strengthen $\Sigma _1(\mathcal {R})^{\ast }$ - $\mathrm {SR}^-$ by allowing $\kappa $ -reflection for classes of structures ${\mathcal C}$ that are $\Sigma _1(\mathcal {R})^{\ast }$ -definable with parameters in $H_{\kappa }$ .

7 Generic Structural Reflection

If A and B are structures of the same type, we say that an elementary embedding $j:A\to B$ is generic if it exists in some forcing extension of V. We shall next consider the following generic version of $\mathrm {SR}$ :

  1. GSR: (Generic Structural Reflection) For every definable (with parameters) class $\mathcal {C}$ of relational structures of the same type there exists an ordinal $\alpha $ that generically reflects $\mathcal {C}$ , i.e., for every A in $\mathcal {C}$ there exist B in $\mathcal {C}\cap V_{\alpha }$ and a generic elementary embedding from B into A.

Thus, $\mathrm {GSR}$ is just like $\mathrm {SR}$ , but the elementary embeddings may not exist in V but in some forcing extension of V. The next proposition shows that this is equivalent to requiring that the elementary embedding exists in any forcing extension resulting from collapsing the structure B to make it countable.

Proposition 7.1 [Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler4].

The following are equivalent for structures B and A of the same type.

  1. (1) $V^{\mathrm {Coll}(\omega ,B)}\models \text {"There is an elementary embedding }j:B\to A.\text {"}$

  2. (2) For some forcing notion ${\mathbb P}$ ,

    $V^{{\mathbb P}}\models \text {"There is an elementary embedding }j:B\to A.\text {"}$

Taking into account similar considerations as in the case of $\mathrm {SR}$ and $\mathrm {PSR}$ , we may properly formulate $\mathrm {GSR}$ as a schema. Namely, for $\Gamma $ a lightface definability class, let:

  1. Γ-GSR: ( $\Gamma $ -Generic Structural Reflection) There exists a cardinal $\kappa $ that generically reflects all $\Gamma $ -definable, with parameters in $V_{\kappa }$ , classes $\mathcal {C}$ of natural structures, i.e., for every A in $\mathcal {C}$ there exists B in $\mathcal {C}\cap V_{\alpha }$ such that in $V^{\mathrm {Coll}(\omega ,B)}$ there is an elementary embedding from B into A.

The boldface version being:

  • There exists a proper class of cardinals $\kappa $ that generically reflect all $\Gamma $ -definable, with parameters in $V_{\kappa }$ , classes $\mathcal {C}$ of natural structures.

The assertion that $\kappa $ witnesses $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {GSR}$ , for $\Gamma $ a boldface definability class, is equivalent to the Generic Vopěnka Principle $\mathrm {{gVP}}(\kappa ,\Gamma )$ introduced in [Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler4].

Similar considerations as in the case of $\mathrm {SR}$ (see the remarks before and after Proposition 3.4) show that - $\mathrm {GSR}$ and $\mathbf {\Sigma _{n+1}}$ - $\mathrm {GSR}$ are equivalent, and also - $\mathrm {GSR}$ and $\Sigma _{n+1}$ - $\mathrm {GSR}$ are equivalent.

We shall see next that some large cardinals, such as Schindler’s remarkable cardinals, can be characterized in terms of $\mathrm {GSR}$ .

Definition 7.2 [Reference Schindler31, Reference Schindler33].

A cardinal $\kappa $ is remarkable if for every regular cardinal $\lambda>\kappa $ , there is a regular cardinal $\bar {\lambda } <\kappa $ such that in $V^{\mathrm { Coll}(\omega ,<\kappa )}$ there is an elementary embedding $j:H_{\bar {\lambda }}^V\to H_{\lambda }^V$ with $j(\mathrm {crit}(j))=\kappa $ .

A cardinal is remarkable if and only if it is $1$ -remarkable (Definition 4.3). Remarkable cardinals are downward absolute to L and their consistency strength is strictly below a $2$ -iterable cardinal. Remarkable cardinals are in $C^{(2)}$ , and they are totally indescribable and ineffable, hence limits of totally indescribable cardinals (see [Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler4]).

Theorem 7.3 [Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler4].

The following are equiconsistent:

  1. (1) - $\mathrm {GSR}.$

  2. (2) There exists a cardinal $\kappa $ that witnesses - $\mathrm {GSR}.$

  3. (3) There exists a remarkable cardinal.

Let us say that a cardinal $\kappa $ is almost remarkable if it is almost- $1$ -remarkable (Definition 4.4), namely: for all $\lambda>\kappa $ in $C^{(1)}$ and every $a\in V_{\lambda }$ , there is $\bar {\lambda } <\kappa $ also in $C^{(1)}$ such that in $V^{\mathrm {{Coll}(\omega , <\kappa )}}$ there exists an elementary embedding $j:V_{\bar {\lambda }}\to V_{\lambda }$ with $a\in \mathrm {{range}}(j)$ . Then Theorem 4.5 yields the following:

Theorem 7.4. A cardinal $\kappa $ witnesses - $\mathrm {GSR}$ if and only if $\kappa $ is almost remarkable.

It follows that the notions of remarkable cardinal and of almost-remarkable cardinal are equiconsistent.

Magidor [Reference Magidor24] shows that a cardinal $\kappa $ is supercompact if and only if for every regular cardinal $\lambda>\kappa $ there is a regular cardinal $\bar {\lambda } <\kappa $ and an elementary embedding $j:H_{\bar {\lambda }}\to H_{\lambda }$ with $j(\mathrm {crit}(j))=\kappa $ . One can thus view a remarkable cardinal as a virtually supercompact Footnote 7 cardinal. In analogy with Theorem 3.2 one might therefore expect - $\mathrm {GSR}$ to be not just equiconsistent, but actually equivalent with the existence of a remarkable cardinal. Even more, since the first supercompact cardinal is precisely the first cardinal that witnesses - $\mathrm {SR}$ , one might conjecture that the first remarkable cardinal is the first cardinal that witnesses - $\mathrm {GSR}$ . This is almost true, but not exactly. On the one hand, if $\kappa $ is a remarkable cardinal, then $\kappa $ witnesses - $\mathrm {GSR}$ [Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler4]. On the other hand, as shown in Theorem 7.6, if there is no $\omega $ -Erdös cardinal in L, then the least cardinal witnessing - $\mathrm {GSR}$ is also the first remarkable cardinal.

The following equivalent definition of remarkability was given in [Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler4]: a cardinal $\kappa $ is remarkable if and only if for every $\lambda>\kappa $ there exist some $\bar {\lambda }<\kappa $ and a generic elementary embedding $j:V_{\bar {\lambda }}\to V_{\lambda }$ with $j(\mathrm {crit}(j))=\kappa $ .

Wilson [Reference Wilson37] defines the notion of weakly remarkable cardinal by not requiring that $\bar {\lambda }$ is strictly below $\kappa $ . Namely,

Definition 7.5 [Reference Wilson37].

$\kappa $ is weakly remarkable if and only if for every $\lambda>\kappa $ there exist some $\bar {\lambda }$ and a generic elementary embedding $j:V_{\bar {\lambda }}\to V_{\lambda }$ with $j(\mathrm {crit}(j))=\kappa $ .

Wilson shows that if there exists a weakly remarkable non-remarkable, cardinal $\kappa $ , then some ordinal greater than $\kappa $ is an $\omega $ -Erdös cardinal in L. Moreover, the statements “There exists an $\omega $ -Erdös cardinal” and “There exists a weakly remarkable non-remarkable cardinal” are equiconsistent modulo ZFC, and equivalent assuming $V=L$ .

Observe that if $\kappa $ is cardinal witnessing - $\mathrm {GSR}$ , then $\kappa $ also witnesses - $\mathrm {GSR}$ in L. Thus, if $\kappa $ witnesses - $\mathrm {GSR}$ and in $L \ \lambda $ is the least inaccessible cardinal above $\kappa $ , then $L_{\lambda }$ is a model of ZFC in which $\kappa $ satisfies - $\mathrm {GSR}$ and there is no $\omega $ -Erdös cardinal above $\kappa $ . By combining arguments from [Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler4, Reference Wilson37] we have the following:

Theorem 7.6. Assume there is no $\omega $ -Erdös cardinal in L. Then, the least cardinal that satisfies - $\mathrm {GSR}$ , if it exists, is remarkable.

Proof Let $\kappa $ be the least cardinal witnessing - $\mathrm {GSR}$ . Let ${\mathcal C}$ be the -definable class of structures of the form $\langle V_{\lambda +1},\in \rangle $ with $\lambda \in C^{(1)}$ . Pick a singular cardinal $\lambda \in C^{(2)}$ greater than $\kappa $ . By - $\mathrm {GSR}$ , let $j:V_{\bar {\lambda }+1}\to V_{\lambda +1}$ be a generic elementary embedding with $\bar \lambda <\kappa $ . Let $\bar \alpha =\mathrm { crit}(j)$ . Note that $\bar \alpha <\bar \lambda $ , because $\bar \alpha $ is regular and $\bar \lambda $ is not.

We claim that $\bar \alpha $ is weakly remarkable up to $\bar \lambda $ . So, fix some $\delta>\bar \alpha $ smaller than $\bar \lambda $ . Consider the restriction $j:V_{\delta } \to V_{j(\delta )}$ , which has $j(\mathrm { crit}(j))=j(\bar \alpha )$ . Then $V_{\lambda +1}$ satisfies that for some $\bar \delta $ there exists a generic elementary embedding $j^{\ast } :V_{\bar \delta }\to V_{j(\delta )}$ such that $j^{\ast }(\mathrm { crit}(j^{\ast }))=j(\bar \alpha )$ . Hence, by elementarity $V_{\bar \lambda +1}$ satisfies that for some $\bar \delta $ there exists a generic elementary embedding $j^{\ast } :V_{\bar \delta }\to V_{\delta }$ with $j^{\ast }(\mathrm { crit}(j^{\ast }))=\bar \alpha $ .

By elementarity, $\alpha := j(\bar \alpha )$ is weakly remarkable up to $\lambda $ , and since $\lambda \in C^{(2)}$ , $\alpha $ is weakly remarkable. Since the existence of a weakly remarkable non-remarkable cardinal implies the existence of an $\omega $ -Erdös cardinal in L [Reference Wilson37], by our assumption we have that $\alpha $ is in fact remarkable. Hence, since every remarkable cardinal witnesses - $\mathrm {GSR}$ [Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler4], we have that $\kappa \leq \alpha $ .

The theorem will be proved by showing that $\alpha =\kappa $ . For suppose, aiming for a contradiction, that $\kappa <\alpha $ . Since $\alpha $ is remarkable and therefore belongs to $C^{(2)}$ , we have

By elementarity, there is some $\gamma <\bar \alpha $ such that

Hence, since $j(\gamma )=\gamma $ , again by elementarity,

and therefore $\gamma $ witnesses

- $\mathrm {GSR}$ , thus contradicting the minimality of $\kappa $ .

Corollary 7.7. Assume there is no $\omega $ -Erdös cardinal in L. Then, the following are equivalent for a cardinal $\kappa $ :

  1. (1) $\kappa $ is the least cardinal witnessing - $\mathrm {GSR}$ .

  2. (2) $\kappa $ is the least cardinal witnessing - $\mathrm {GSR}$ .

  3. (3) $\kappa $ is the least almost remarkable cardinal.

  4. (4) $\kappa $ is the least weakly remarkable cardinal.

  5. (5) $\kappa $ is the least remarkable cardinal.

We don’t know if the assumption that there is no $\omega $ -Erdös cardinal in L is necessary for the equivalence above to hold. However, we have the following:

Proposition 7.8. For every $n>0$ , if $\kappa $ witnesses - $\mathrm {GSR}$ , then $\kappa \in C^{(n+1)}$ . In particular, if $\kappa $ witnesses - $\mathrm {GSR}$ , then $\kappa \in C^{(2)}$ .

Proof Let us prove the case $n=1$ . The general case follows by induction, using a similar argument. So, suppose $a\in V_{\kappa }$ , $\varphi (x,y)$ is a formula with $x,y$ as the only free variables, and $V\models \exists x \varphi (x,a)$ . Pick $\lambda \in C^{(2)}$ greater than $\kappa $ , so that $V_{\lambda } \models \exists x \varphi (x,a)$ . Since the class of structures of the form $\langle V_{\alpha } ,\in ,a\rangle $ is -definable with a as a parameter, there exists a generic elementary embedding $j:\langle V_{\bar \lambda }, \in , a\rangle \to \langle V_{\lambda } ,\in ,a\rangle $ with $\bar \lambda <\kappa $ . Note that, on the one hand, since $\lambda $ belongs to $C^{(1)}$ so does $\bar \lambda $ , hence by downward absoluteness for sentences, $V_{\kappa } \models \text {"}\bar \lambda \in C^{(1)}.\text {"}$ On the other hand, by elementarity of j, $V_{\bar \lambda }\models \exists x \varphi (x,a)$ . Hence by upwards absoluteness, $V_{\kappa } \models \exists x \varphi (x,a)$ .

A simpler similar argument, using the fact that $\Sigma _1$ sentences are absolute for transitive sets, shows that $\kappa \in C^{(1)}$ . Hence, if $\varphi (x,y)$ and a are as above, and $V_{\kappa } \models \exists x \varphi (x,a)$ , then by upwards absoluteness, $V\models \exists x \varphi (x,a)$ .

For the general case $n>1$ , assume $\kappa \in C^{(n)}$ , and consider the -definable (with a as a parameter) class of structures of the form $\langle V_{\alpha } ,\in ,a\rangle $ with $\alpha \in C^{(n)}$ .

As Wilson [Reference Wilson37] shows that a cardinal is remarkable if and only if it is weakly remarkable and belongs to $C^{(2)}$ , if the least cardinal $\kappa $ that witnesses - $\mathrm {GSR}$ is not remarkable, then is not weakly remarkable. Thus, the question is if it is provable in ZFC that the least cardinal $\kappa $ witnessing - $\mathrm {GSR}$ , if it exists, is weakly remarkable. Notice, however, that the proof of Theorem 7.6 does show that if $\kappa $ is the least cardinal witnessing - $\mathrm {GSR}$ , then either $\kappa $ is remarkable or there is a weakly remarkable cardinal below $\kappa $ . Also, if $\kappa $ is the least cardinal witnessing - $\mathrm {GSR}$ , then either $\kappa $ is remarkable or there are unboundedly many weakly remarkable cardinals below $\kappa $ .

More generally, recall (Definition 4.3) that a cardinal $\kappa $ is n-remarkable, for $n>0$ , if for every $\lambda>\kappa $ in $C^{(n)}$ , there is $\bar \lambda < \kappa $ also in $C^{(n)}$ such that in $V^{\mathrm {Coll}(\omega ,<\kappa )}$ , there is an elementary embedding $j:V_{\bar \lambda } \to V_{\lambda }$ with $j(\mathrm {crit}(j))=\kappa $ . Equivalently, we may additionally require that for any given $a\in V_{\lambda }$ , a is in the range of j. A cardinal $\kappa $ is completely remarkable if it is n-remarkable for every $n>0$ . Remarkable cardinals are precisely the $1$ -remarkable cardinals.

As shown in [Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler4], if $0^{\sharp }$ exists, then every Silver indiscernible is completely remarkable in L. Moreover, if $\kappa $ is $2$ -iterable, then $V_{\kappa }$ is a model of ZFC in which there exists a proper class of completely remarkable cardinals.

Theorem 7.3 also holds for n-remarkable cardinals. Namely,

Theorem 7.9. The following are equiconsistent for $n>0$ :

  1. (1) - $\mathrm {GSR}.$

  2. (2) There exists a cardinal $\kappa $ that witnesses - $\mathrm {GSR}.$

  3. (3) There exists an n-remarkable cardinal.

As it turns out, ( $n+1$ )-remarkable cardinals correspond precisely to the virtual form of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals. Namely,

Definition 7.10 [Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler4].

A cardinal $\kappa $ is virtually extendible if for every $\alpha>\kappa $ there is a generic elementary embedding $j:V_{\alpha }\to V_{\beta }$ such that $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\kappa $ and $j(\kappa )>\alpha $ .

A cardinal $\kappa $ is virtually $C^{(n)}$ -extendible if additionally $j(\kappa )\in C^{(n)}$ .

Note that virtually extendible cardinals are virtually $C^{(1)}$ -extendible because $j(\kappa )$ must be inaccessible in V.

In contrast with the definition of extendible cardinal, in which the requirement that $j(\kappa )>\alpha $ is superfluous, in the definition of virtually extendible cardinal it is necessary. The reason is that while there is no non-trivial elementary embedding $j:V_{\lambda +2}\to V_{\lambda +2}$ , such an embedding may exist generically (see [Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler4]).

Theorem 7.11 [Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler4].

A cardinal $\kappa $ is virtually extendible if and only if it is $2$ -remarkable. More generally, $\kappa $ is virtually $C^{(n)}$ -extendible if and only if it is $(n+1)$ -remarkable.

The requirement that $j(\kappa )>\alpha $ in the definition of virtually extendible cardinals suggests the following strengthening of $\mathrm {GSR}$ . Let us say that an elementary embedding $j:V_{\alpha } \to V_{\beta }$ is overspilling if j has a critical point and $j(\mathrm {crit}(j))>\alpha $ . For $\Gamma $ a lightface definability class, let:

  1. Γ-SGSR: ( $\Gamma $ -Strong Generic Structural Reflection) There exists a cardinal $\kappa $ that strongly generically reflects all $\Gamma $ -definable classes $\mathcal {C}$ of natural structures, i.e., for every A in $\mathcal {C}$ there exists B in $\mathcal {C}\cap V_{\alpha }$ such that in $V^{\mathrm {Coll}(\omega ,B)}$ there is an overspilling elementary embedding from B into A.

With the boldface version being:

  • There exists a proper class of cardinals $\kappa $ that strongly generically reflect all $\Gamma $ -definable, with parameters in $V_{\kappa }$ , classes $\mathcal {C}$ of natural structures.

Then we have the following:

Theorem 7.12. The following are equivalent for every $n\geq 1$ :

  1. (1) - $\mathrm {SGSR}.$

  2. (2) There exists an $(n+1)$ -remarkable cardinal.

  3. (3) There exists a virtually $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal.

8 Beyond $\mathrm {VP}$

We have seen that a variety of large cardinal notions, ranging from weakly inaccessible to Vopěnka’s Principle, can be characterised as some form of Structural Reflection for classes of relational structures of some degree of complexity. The question is now if the same is true for large-cardinal notions stronger than $\mathrm {VP}$ , up to rank-into-rank embeddings, or even for large cardinals that contradict the Axiom of Choice (see [Reference Bagaria, Koellner and Woodin5]). This is largely a yet unexplored realm, although there are some very recent results showing that this is indeed the case. In [Reference Bagaria and Lücke7], we introduce a simple form of $\mathrm {SR}$ , which we call Exact Structural Reflection $(\mathrm {ESR})$ , and show that some natural large-cardinal notions in the region between almost-huge and superhuge cardinals can be characterised in terms of $\mathrm {ESR}$ . Also, sequential forms of $\mathrm {ESR}$ akin to generalised versions of Chang’s Conjecture yield large-cardinal principles at the highest reaches of the known large-cardinal hierarchy, and beyond. We give next a brief summary of the results.

Given infinite cardinals $\kappa <\lambda $ and a class ${\mathcal C}$ of structures of the same type, let

  1. ESR𝒞(κ,λ): (Exact Structural Reflection) For every $A\in {\mathcal C}$ of rank $\lambda $ , there exist some $B\in {\mathcal C}$ of rank $\kappa $ and an elementary embedding from B into A.

We let $\Gamma (P)$ - $\mathrm {ESR}(\kappa ,\lambda )$ denote the statement that $\mathrm {ESR}_{\mathcal C} (\kappa ,\lambda )$ holds for every class ${\mathcal C}$ of structures of the same type that is $\Gamma $ -definable with parameters from P.

The general $\mathrm {ESR}$ principle restricted to classes of structures that are closed under isomorphic images is just equivalent to $\mathrm {VP}$ :

Theorem 8.1 [Reference Bagaria and Lücke7].

Over the theory ZFC, the following schemata of sentences are equivalent:

  1. (1) For every class ${\mathcal C}$ of structures of the same type that is closed under isomorphic images, there is a cardinal $\kappa $ with the property that $\mathrm {ESR}_{\mathcal C}(\kappa ,\lambda )$ holds for all $\lambda>\kappa $ .

  2. (2) $\mathrm {VP}$ .

However, even the principle - $\mathrm {ESR} (\kappa ,\lambda )$ holding for some $\kappa <\lambda $ already implies the existence of large cardinals, the weakly exact cardinals, whose consistency strength is beyond that of $\mathrm {VP}$ .

Definition 8.2 [Reference Bagaria and Lücke7].

Given a natural number $n>0$ , an infinite cardinal $\kappa $ is weakly n-exact for a cardinal $\lambda>\kappa $ if for every $A\in V_{\lambda +1}$ , there exist a transitive, -correct set M with $V_{\kappa }\cup \{\kappa \} \subseteq M$ , a cardinal $\lambda '\in C^{(n-1)}$ greater than $\beth _{\lambda }$ , and an elementary embedding $j:M\to H_{\lambda '}$ with $j(\kappa )=\lambda $ and $A\in \mathrm {range}(j)$ .

If we further require that $j(\mathrm {crit}{j})=\kappa $ , then we say that $\kappa $ is weakly parametrically n-exact for $\lambda $ .

We have the following equivalence:

Theorem 8.3 [Reference Bagaria and Lücke7].

The following statements are equivalent for all cardinals $\kappa $ and all natural numbers $n>0$ :

  1. (1) $\kappa $ is the least cardinal such that - $\mathrm {ESR}(\kappa , \lambda )$ holds for some $\lambda $ .

  2. (2) $\kappa $ is the least cardinal that is weakly n-exact for some $\lambda $ .

  3. (3) $\kappa $ is the least cardinal that is weakly parametrically n-exact for some $\lambda $ .

In contrast with the $\mathrm {SR}$ principles considered in previous sections, the $\mathrm {ESR}$ principles for -definable and $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable classes of structures are not equivalent. Indeed, for $\Sigma _n$ -definable classes, the relevant large cardinals are the exact cardinals:

Definition 8.4 [Reference Bagaria and Lücke7].

Given a natural number n, an infinite cardinal $\kappa $ is n-exact for some cardinal $\lambda>\kappa $ if for every $A\in V_{\lambda +1}$ , there exist a cardinal $\kappa '\in C^{(n)}$ greater than $\beth _{\kappa }$ , a cardinal $\lambda '\in C^{(n+1)}$ greater than $\lambda $ , an with $V_{\kappa } \cup \{\kappa \} \subseteq X$ , and an elementary embedding $j:X\to H_{\lambda '}$ with $j(\kappa )=\lambda $ and $A\in \mathrm {range}{(j)}$ .

If we further require that $j(\mathrm {crit}{(j)})=\kappa $ holds, then we say that $\kappa $ is parametrically n-exact for $\lambda $ .

The characterization of $\mathrm {ESR}$ for $\Sigma _n$ -definable classes of structures in terms of exact cardinals is now given by the following:

Theorem 8.5 [Reference Bagaria and Lücke7].

The following statements are equivalent for all cardinals $\kappa $ and all natural numbers $n>0$ :

  1. (1) $\kappa $ is the least cardinal such that $\Sigma _{n+1}(V_{\kappa })$ - $\mathrm {ESR}(\kappa ,\lambda )$ holds for some $\lambda $ .

  2. (2) $\kappa $ is the least cardinal that is n-exact for some $\lambda $ .

  3. (3) $\kappa $ is the least cardinal that is parametrically n-exact for some $\lambda $ .

The strength of weakly n-exact and n-exact cardinals, and therefore also of their corresponding equivalent forms of $\mathrm {ESR}$ , goes beyond $\mathrm {VP}$ , for as shown in [Reference Bagaria and Lücke7] they imply the existence of almost huge cardinals:Footnote 8 If $\kappa <\lambda $ are cardinals such that $\kappa $ is either parametrically $0$ -exact for $\lambda $ or weakly parametrically $1$ -exact for $\lambda $ , then the set of cardinals that are almost huge with target $\kappa $ is stationary in $\kappa $ . Also, if $\kappa $ is parametrically $0$ -exact for some cardinal $\lambda>\kappa $ , then it is almost huge with target $\lambda $ .

As for upper bounds, if $\kappa $ is huge with target $\lambda $ , then it is weakly parametrically $1$ -exact for $\lambda $ . Hence, - $\mathrm {ESR}(\mu ,\nu )$ holds for some $\mu \leq \kappa $ and $\nu>\mu $ . Moreover, - $\mathrm {ESR}(\kappa , \lambda ')$ holds in $V_{\lambda }$ , for some $\lambda '$ . However, if $\kappa $ is the least huge cardinal, then $\kappa $ is not $1$ -exact for any cardinal $\lambda>\kappa $ . The best upper bound for the consistency strength of exact cardinals is given by the following:

Proposition 8.6 [Reference Bagaria and Lücke7].

If $\kappa $ is a $2$ -huge cardinal,Footnote 9 then there exist an inaccessible cardinal $\lambda>\kappa $ and a cardinal $\rho>\lambda $ such that $V_{\rho }$ is a model of $\mathrm {ZFC}$ and, in $V_{\rho }$ , the cardinal $\kappa $ is weakly parametrically n-exact for $\lambda $ , for all $n>0$ .

As for direct implication, the best known upper bound for the existence of exact cardinals is given by the following:

Proposition 8.7 [Reference Bagaria and Lücke7].

Let $\kappa $ be an $I3$ -cardinal,Footnote 10 witnessed by $j:V_{\delta }\to V_{\delta }$ . If $l,m,n<\omega $ , then, in $V_{\delta }$ , the cardinal $j^l(\kappa )$ is parametrically n-exact for $j^{l+m+1}(\kappa )$ .

The existence of an $I3$ -cardinal is a very strong principle which implies the consistency of n-huge cardinals, for every n, and much more (see [Reference Kanamori15, p. 24], also [Reference Bagaria2, Theorem 7.1]). Yet even stronger large-cardinal principles bordering the inconsistency with ZFC are implied by the following sequential forms of $\mathrm {ESR}$ , also introduced in [Reference Bagaria and Lücke7].

8.1 Sequential $\mathrm {ESR}$

Let $0<\eta \leq \omega $ and let $\mathcal {L}$ be a first-order language containing unary predicate symbols $\vec {P}=\langle {\dot {P}_i}~\vert ~{i<\eta }\rangle $ .

Given a sequence $\vec {\mu }=\langle {\mu _i}~\vert ~{i<\eta }\rangle $ of cardinals with supremum $\mu $ , an $\mathcal {L}$ -structure A has type $\vec {\mu }$ (with respect to $\vec {P}$ ) if the universe of A has rank $\mu $ and $\mathrm {rank}{(\dot {P}_i^{A})}=\mu _i$ for all $i<\eta $ .

Given a class ${\mathcal C}$ of $\mathcal {L}$ -structures and a strictly increasing sequence $\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _i}~\vert ~{i<1+\eta }\rangle $ of cardinals, let

  • $\mathrm {ESR}_{{\mathcal C}} ({\vec {\lambda }})$ : (Sequential $\mathrm {ESR}$ ) For every structure B in ${\mathcal C}$ of type $\langle {\lambda _{i+1}}~\vert ~{i<1+\eta }\rangle $ , there exists an elementary embedding of a structure A in ${\mathcal C}$ of type $\langle {\lambda _i}~\vert ~{i<\eta }\rangle $ into B.

The large-cardinal notions corresponding to sequential $\mathrm {ESR}$ are the sequential analogs of weakly exact and exact cardinals (given in Definitions 8.2 and 8.4). Namely,

Definition 8.8 [Reference Bagaria and Lücke7].

Let $0<\eta \leq \omega $ and let $\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _m}~\vert ~{m<\eta }\rangle $ be a strictly increasing sequence of cardinals with supremum $\lambda $ .

  1. (1) Given $0<n<\omega $ , a cardinal $\kappa <\lambda _0$ is weakly n-exact for $\vec {\lambda }$ if for every $A\in V_{\lambda +1}$ , there are a cardinal $\rho $ , a transitive, -correct set M with $V_{\rho } \cup \{\rho \}\subseteq M$ , a cardinal $\lambda '\in C^{(n-1)}$ greater than $\beth _{\lambda }$ , and an e. e. $j:M\to H_{\lambda '}$ with $A\in \mathrm {range}{j}$ , $j(\rho )=\lambda $ , $j(\kappa )=\lambda _0$ , and $j(\lambda _{m-1})=\lambda _m$ , all m.

    If we further require that $j(\mathrm {crit}{j})=\kappa $ , then we say that $\kappa $ is parametrically weakly n-exact for $\vec {\lambda }$ .

  2. (2) Given $n<\omega $ , a cardinal $\kappa <\lambda _0$ is n-exact for $\vec {\lambda }$ if for every $A\in V_{\lambda +1}$ , there are a cardinal $\rho $ , a cardinal $\kappa '\in C^{(n)}$ greater than $\beth _{\rho }$ , a cardinal $\lambda ' \in C^{(n+1)}$ greater than $\lambda $ , an with $V_{\rho }\cup \{\rho \}\subseteq X$ , and an e. e. $j:X\to H_{\lambda '}$ with $A\in \mathrm {range}{j}$ , $j(\rho )=\lambda $ , $j(\kappa )=\lambda _0$ , and $j(\lambda _{m-1})=\lambda _m$ , all m.

    If we further require that $j(\mathrm {crit}{j})=\kappa $ , then we say that $\kappa $ is parametrically n-exact for $\vec {\lambda }$ .

Then we have the following equivalences:

Theorem 8.9 [Reference Bagaria and Lücke7].

Let $0<n<\omega $ , let $0<\eta \leq \omega $ , and let $\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _i}~\vert ~{i<1+\eta }\rangle $ be a strictly increasing sequence of cardinals.

  1. (1) The cardinal $\lambda _0$ is weakly n-exact for $\langle {\lambda _{i+1}}~\vert ~{i<\eta }\rangle $ if and only if - $\mathrm {ESR} ({\vec {\lambda }})$ holds.

  2. (2) If $\lambda _0$ is weakly parametrically n-exact for $\langle {\lambda _{i+1}}~\vert ~{i<\eta }\rangle $ , then - $\mathrm {ESR}(\vec {\lambda })$ holds.

Also:

  1. (1) The cardinal $\lambda _0$ is n-exact for $\langle {\lambda _{i+1}}~\vert ~{i<\eta }\rangle $ if and only if $\Sigma _{n+1}$ - $\mathrm {ESR}(\vec {\lambda })$ holds.

  2. (2) If $\lambda _0$ is parametrically n-exact for $\langle {\lambda _{i+1}}~\vert ~{i<\eta }\rangle $ , then $\Sigma _{n+1}(V_{\lambda _0})$ - $\mathrm {ESR}(\vec {\lambda })$ holds.

In the case of finite sequences $\vec {\lambda }$ of length n, the sequentially 1-exact cardinals correspond roughly to n-huge cardinals. More precisely [Reference Bagaria and Lücke7]: If $\kappa $ is an n-huge cardinal, witnessed by an elementary embedding $j:V\to M$ , then $\kappa $ is weakly parametrically $1$ -exact for the sequence $\langle {j^{m+1}(\kappa )}~\vert ~{m<n}\rangle $ . Also, if $\kappa $ is a cardinal and $\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _m}~\vert ~{m\leq n}\rangle $ is a sequence of cardinals such that $\kappa $ is either weakly $1$ -exact for $\vec {\lambda }$ or $0$ -exact for $\vec {\lambda }$ , then some cardinal less than $\kappa $ is n-huge.

As for infinite sequences $\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _m}~\vert ~{m<\omega }\rangle $ , there is a dramatic increase in consistency strength, as shown by the following facts proved in [Reference Bagaria and Lücke7]: Let $\lambda $ be the supremum of $\vec {\lambda }$ and let $\kappa <\lambda _0$ be a cardinal. If $\kappa $ is either weakly $1$ -exact for $\vec {\lambda }$ or $0$ -exact for $\vec {\lambda }$ , then there exists an $I3$ -embedding $j:V_{\lambda }\to V_{\lambda }$ . Also, if $\kappa $ is either parametrically weakly $1$ -exact for $\vec {\lambda }$ or parametrically $0$ -exact for $\vec {\lambda }$ , then the set $I3$ -cardinals is stationary in $\kappa $ .

To prove the existence of a weakly parametrically $1$ -exact cardinal, for some infinite sequence $\vec {\lambda }$ , the best known upper bound is an $I1$ -cardinalFootnote 11 [Reference Bagaria and Lücke7]: If $\kappa $ is an $I1$ -cardinal and $k>0$ is a natural number, then $\kappa $ is weakly parametrically $1$ -exact for the sequence $\langle {j^{k(m+1)}(\kappa )}~\vert ~{m<\omega }\rangle $ . In particular, for $k=1$ , $\kappa $ is weakly parametrically $1$ -exact for $\langle {j^{(m+1)}(\kappa )}~\vert ~{m<\omega }\rangle $ , hence - $\mathrm {ESR}(\vec {\lambda })$ holds.

Many open questions remain (see [Reference Bagaria and Lücke7]), the most pressing one being the consistency with ZFC of the principle $\Sigma _2$ - $\mathrm {ESR}(\vec {\lambda })$ for some sequence $\vec {\lambda }$ of length $\omega $ .

Table 1 Between supercompact and $\mathrm{VP}$ .

9 Summary

The following tables summarize the results exposed in previous sections. Presented in this form, the equivalences between the various kinds of $\mathrm {SR}$ and (mostly already well-known) different large cardinal notions illustrate the fact that $\mathrm {SR}$ is a general reflection principle that underlies (many stretches of) the large cardinal hierarchy, thus unveiling its concealed uniformity. Table 1 encompasses the region of the large-cardinal hierarchy comprised between supercompact and VP, Table 2 the region between strong and “ $\mathrm {Ord}$ is Woodin,” and Table 3 the region between globally superstrong and $C^{(n)}$ -globally superstrong, all n. The tables are read as, e.g., $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {SR}$ for $\Gamma $ being or $\Sigma _2$ is equivalent to the existence of a supercompact cardinal (Table 1). For the boldface definability classes we have the equivalence of $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {SR}$ with a proper class of the corresponding large cardinals. In the limit cases, i.e., VP in Table 1, “ $\mathrm {Ord}$ is Woodin” in Table 2, and $C^{(n)}$ -globally superstrong, all n, in Table 3, the lightface and the boldface versions are equivalent.

Table 2 Between strong and “Ord is Woodin”.

Table 3 Between globally superstrong and $C^{(n)}$ -globally superstrong, all $n$ .

Table 4 $\mathrm{SR}$ relative to inner models.

Table 5 Small large cardinals.

Table 6 From almost remarkable to virtually $C^{(n)}$ -extendible.

Table 7 Beyond Vopěnka's Principle.

Table 8 Beyond I3-cardinals.

We also have the equivalence between - $\mathrm {PSR}_1$ and the existence of a measurable cardinal (Theorem 5.21).

Table 4 summarizes the results on $\mathrm {SR}$ relative to inner models. The classes ${\mathcal C}$ , ${\mathcal C}_X$ , ${\mathcal C}^U$ , and ${\mathcal C}^U_X$ are defined in Section 4.1. Similar results should hold for canonical inner models for stronger large cardinals, and their corresponding sharps.

Tables 5 and 6 summarize the results characterizing large cardinals of consistency strength below $0^{\sharp }$ in terms of restricted $\mathrm {SR}$ and generic $\mathrm {SR}$ , respectively.

Finally, Tables 7 and 8 cover some equivalences in the region above Vopěnka’s Principle.

Funding statement

Part of this research was supported by the Spanish Government under grants MTM2017-86777-P and MTM-PID2020-116773GB-I00, and by the Generalitat de Catalunya (Catalan Government) under grant SGR 270-2017.

Footnotes

1 For all undefined set-theoretic notions see [Reference Jech14] or [Reference Kanamori15].

2 The work presented in the following sections started over 10 years ago. After a talk I gave in Barcelona in 2011 on large cardinals as principles of structural reflection, John Baldwin, who attended the talk and was at the time editor of the BSL, encouraged me to write a survey article on the topic for the Bulletin. Well, here it is. I’m thankful to him for the invitation and I apologise for the long delay.

3 See [Reference Koellner16] for a discussion on intrinsic versus extrinsic justification of the axioms of set theory.

5 In [Reference Bagaria and Väänänen8] it is only assumed that $\kappa $ witnesses $\mathrm {SR}^-_{\mathop {C\hspace {-0.8pt}d}, \mathop {W\!C}}$ . However, Lücke [Reference Lücke23] has shown that some additional assumption on $\kappa $ is needed. Note that our assumption on $\kappa $ in the current statement of the theorem follows form the GCH.

6 However, as shown in [Reference Lücke23], it does not imply $(\mathrm {SR})^-_{\mathcal {R}}$ , as claimed in [Reference Bagaria and Väänänen8].

7 We choose to call it virtually supercompact, as in [Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler4], instead of the perhaps more natural generic supercompact, for the latter notion already exists in the literature with a different meaning.

8 Recall that a cardinal $\kappa $ is almost huge if there exist a transitive class M and a non-trivial elementary embedding $j:V\to M$ with $\mathrm { crit}{j}=\kappa $ and ${}^{{<}j(\kappa )}M\subseteq M$ . We then say that a cardinal $\kappa $ is almost huge with target $\lambda $ if there exists such a j with $j(\kappa )=\lambda $ .

9 That is, there is an elementary embedding $j:V\to M$ with M transitive, $\mathrm {crit}{(j)}=\kappa $ , and $^{j^2(\kappa )}M\subseteq M$ .

10 That is, the critical point of a non-trivial elementary embedding $j:V_{\delta }\to V_{\delta }$ , for some limit ordinal $\delta $ . Then $V_{\delta }$ is a model of $\mathrm {ZFC}$ and the sequence $\langle {j^m(\kappa )}~\vert ~{m<\omega }\rangle $ is cofinal in $\delta $ .

11 That is, the critical point of a non-trivial elementary embedding $j:V_{\lambda +1}\to V_{\lambda +1}$ for some limit ordinal $\lambda $ .

References

Ackermann, W., Zur Axiomatik der Mengenlehre . Mathematische Annalen , vol. 131 (1956), pp. 336345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bagaria, J., ${C}^{(n)}$ -cardinals . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 51 (2012), pp. 213240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bagaria, J., Casacuberta, C., Mathias, A. R. D., and Rosický, J., Definable orthogonality classes in accessible categories are small . Journal of the European Mathematical Society , vol. 17 (2015), no. 3, pp. 549589.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bagaria, J., Gitman, V., and Schindler, R. D., Generic Vopěnka’s principle, remarkable cardinals, and the weak proper forcing axiom . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 56 (2017), nos. 1–2, pp. 120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bagaria, J., Koellner, P., and Woodin, H., Large cardinals beyond choice, this Journal, vol. 25 (2019), no. 3, pp. 283–318.Google Scholar
Bagaria, J. and Lücke, P.. Patterns of structural reflection in the large-cardinal hierarchy, 2022, submitted.Google Scholar
Bagaria, J. and Lücke, P., Huge reflection . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 174 (2023), no. 1, p. 103171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bagaria, J. and Väänänen, J., On the symbiosis between model-theoretic and set-theoretic properties of large cardinals . The Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 81 (2016), no. 2, pp. 584604.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bagaria, J. and Wilson, T., The Weak Vopěnka Principle for definable classes of structures . The Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 88 (2023), pp. 145168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cai, J. and Tsaprounis, K., On strengthenings of superstrong cardinals . New York Journal of Mathematics , vol. 25 (2019), pp. 174194.Google Scholar
Cantor, G., Grundlagen einer allgemeinen Mannigfaltigkeitslehre. Ein Mathematisch-Philosophischer Versuch in der Lehre des Unendlichen , B. G. Teubner, Leipzig, 1883.Google Scholar
Feferman, S., Review of: Azriel Lévy, “On the principles of reflection in axiomatic set theory” , Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science (Proceedings of the 1960 International Congress) (E. Nagel, P. Suppes, and A. Tarski, editors), Stanford University Press, Stanford, 1962, pp. 8793.Google Scholar
Jané, I., Idealist and realist elements in Cantor’s approach to set theory . Philosophia Mathematica , vol. 18 (2010), no. 2, pp. 193226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jech, T., Set Theory , The Third Millenium Edition, Revised and Expanded, Springer Monographs in Mathematics, Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg, 2002.Google Scholar
Kanamori, A., The Higher Infinite , second ed., Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg, 2003.Google Scholar
Koellner, P., On reflection principles . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 157 (2009), nos. 2–3, pp. 206219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koepke, P., An introduction to extenders and core models for extender sequences , Logic Colloquium’87 (H.-D. Ebbinghaus et al., editors), Elsevier, North Holland, Amsterdam, 1989.Google Scholar
Kunen, K., Elementary embeddings and infinitary combinatorics . The Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 36 (1971), pp. 407413.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lévy, A., On Ackermann’s set theory . The Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 24 (1959), pp. 154166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lévy, A., Axiom schemata of strong infinity in axiomatic set theory . Pacific Journal of Mathematics , vol. 10 (1960), pp. 223238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lévy, A., Principles of reflection in axiomatic set theory . Fundamenta Mathematicae , vol. 49 (1960/1961), pp. 110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lévy, A., On the principles of reflection in axiomatic set theory , Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science (Proceedings of the 1960 International Congress) , Stanford University Press, Stanford, 1962, pp. 8793.Google Scholar
Lücke, P., Structural reflection, shrewd cardinals and the size of the continuum . Journal of Mathematical Logic , vol. 22 (2022), no. 2, p. 2250007.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Magidor, M., On the role of supercompact and extendible cardinals in logic . Israel Journal of Mathematics , vol. 10 (1971), no. 2, pp. 147157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Magidor, M. and Väänänen, J., On Löwenheim–Skolem–Tarski numbers for extensions of first-order logic . Journal of Mathematical Logic , vol. 11 (2011), no. 1, pp. 87113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCallum, R., A consistency proof for some restrictions of Tait’s reflection principles . Mathematical Logic Quarterly , vol. 50 (2013), nos. 1–2, pp. 112118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitchell, W. J., Beginning inner model theory , Handbook of Set Theory (M. Foreman and A. Kanamori, editors), Springer, Dordrecht, 2010, pp. 14491495.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rathjen, M., Recent advances in ordinal analysis: ${\varPi}_2^1$ -CA and related systems, this Journal, vol. 1 (1995), no. 4, pp. 468–485.Google Scholar
Reinhardt, W., Remarks on reflection principles, large cardinals, and elementary embeddings , Axiomatic Set Theory. Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics, XIII, Part II , vol. 10, American Mathematical Society, Providence, 1974, pp. 189205.Google Scholar
Reinhardt, W. N., Ackermann’s set theory equals ZF . Annals of Mathematical Logic , vol. 2 (1970), no. 2, pp. 189249.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schindler, R.-D., Proper forcing and remarkable cardinals . The Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 6 (2000), no. 2, pp. 176184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schindler, R.-D., The core model for almost linear iterations . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 116 (2002), no. 1, pp. 205272.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schindler, R.-D., Remarkable cardinals , Infinity, Computability, and Metamathematics: Festschrift in Honour of the 60th Birthdays of Peter Koepke and Philip Welch, Tributes (S. Geschke, B. Loewe and P. Schlicht, editors), College Publications, London, 2014, pp. 299308.Google Scholar
Stavi, J. and Väänänen, J., Reflection principles for the continuum , Logic and Algebra , Contemporary Mathematics, vol. 302 (Y. Zhang, editor), American Mathematical Society, Providence, 2002, pp. 5984.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tait, W. W., Gödel’s unpublished papers on foundations of mathematics . Philosophia Mathematica , vol. 9 (2001), pp. 87126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wang, H., A Logical Journey: From Gödel to Philosophy , MIT Press, Cambridge, 1996.Google Scholar
Wilson, T., Weakly remarkable cardinals, Erdös cardinals, and the generic Vopěnka principle . The Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 84 (2019), no. 4, pp. 17111721.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1 Between supercompact and $\mathrm{VP}$.

Figure 1

Table 2 Between strong and “Ord is Woodin”.

Figure 2

Table 3 Between globally superstrong and $C^{(n)}$-globally superstrong, all $n$.

Figure 3

Table 4 $\mathrm{SR}$ relative to inner models.

Figure 4

Table 5 Small large cardinals.

Figure 5

Table 6 From almost remarkable to virtually $C^{(n)}$-extendible.

Figure 6

Table 7 Beyond Vopěnka's Principle.

Figure 7

Table 8 Beyond I3-cardinals.