Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-8bhkd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T23:28:43.574Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - Neuroscience, choice and responsibility

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 August 2009

Patricia S. Churchland
Affiliation:
Professor Department of Philosophy University of California, San Diego La Jolia, CA 92093-0119
James R. Pomerantz
Affiliation:
Rice University, Houston
Get access

Summary

Introduction

Much of human social life depends on the notion that agents have control over their actions and are responsible for their choices. In daily life it is commonly assumed that it is fair to punish and reward behavior so long as the person is in control and makes choices knowingly and intentionally. Without the assumptions of agent control and responsibility, human social commerce is hardly conceivable. As members of a social species, we recognize co-operation, loyalty, honesty, and helping as prominent features of the social environment. We react with hostility when group members disappoint certain socially significant expectations. Inflicting disutilities (e.g., shunning, pinching) on the socially erring and rewarding civic virtue help restore the standards.

In other social species too, social unreliability, such as a failure to reciprocate grooming or food-sharing, provokes a reaction likely to cost the erring agent, sooner or later. In social mammals at least, mechanisms for learning and keeping the social order seem to be part of what evolution has bequeathed to our brain circuitry. Given that the stability of the social-expectation baseline is sufficiently important for survival, individuals are prepared to incur some cost in enforcing those expectations. Just as anubis baboons learn that tasty scorpions are to be found under rocks but cannot just be picked up, so they learn that failure to reciprocate grooming when it is duly expected may incur a slap.

Type
Chapter
Information
Topics in Integrative Neuroscience
From Cells to Cognition
, pp. 2 - 22
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aristotle (1955). The Nichomachean Ethics. Trans. Thompson, J. A. K.. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Ballantine, H. T. Jr., Bouckoms, A. J., and Thomas, E. K. (1987). Treatment of psychiatric illness by stereotactic cingulotomy. Biological Psychiatry, 22, 807–19.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bauman, M. L. and Kemper, T. L. (1995). Neuroanatomical observations of the brain in autism. In Panksepp, J., ed., Advances in Biological Psychiatry. New York: JAI Press, pp. 1–26.Google Scholar
Beauregard, M., Lévesque, J., and Bourgouin, P. (2001). Neural correlates of conscious self-regulation of emotion. Journal of Neuroscience, 21, 1–6.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Campbell, C. A. (1957). Has the self “free will”? On Selfhood and Godhood, London: Allen and Unwin; and New Jersey: Humanities Press Inc., pp. 158–79.Google Scholar
Casebeer, W. (2003). Natural Ethical Facts: Evolution, Connectionism, and Moral Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1995). The Engine of Reason, The Seat of the Soul. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. S. (2002). Brain-Wise: Studies in Neurophilosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Crick, F. H. C. (1994). The Astonishing Hypothesis. New York: Scribner's.Google Scholar
Damasio, A. R. (1999). The Feeling of What Happens. New York: Harcourt Brace.Google Scholar
Damasio, A. R. and Van Hoesen, G. (1983). Emotional disturbances associated with focal lesions of the limbic frontal lobe. In Heilman, K. and Satz, P., eds., Neuropsychology of Human Emotion. New York: Guilford, pp. 268–99.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (2003). Freedom Evolves. New York: Basic.Google Scholar
Hobart, R. E. (1934). Free will as involving determinism and inconceivable without it. Mind, 43, 1–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hobson, J. A. (1993). Understanding persons: the role of affect. In Baron-Cohen, S., Tager-Flusberg, H., and Cohen, D. J., eds., Understanding Other Minds: Perspectives from Autism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 204–27.Google Scholar
Hume, D. [1739] (1962). A Treatise of Human Nature. Ed. Smith, Norman Kemp. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kagan, J. (1994). Galen's Prophecy: Temperament in Human Nature. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Kane, R. (1996). The Significance of Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Robbins, T. W. and Everitt, B. J. (1995). Arousal systems and attention. In Gazzaniga, M., ed., The Cognitive Neurosciences, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 703–20.Google Scholar
Schlick, M. (1939). When is a man responsible? Problems of Ethics. New York: Prentice-Hall, pp. 143–56.Google Scholar
Stapp, H. P. (1999). Attention, intention and will in quantum physics. In Libet, B., Freeman, A., and Sutherland, K., eds., The Volitional Brain: Towards a Neuroscience of Free Will. New York: Academic Press, pp. 143–74.Google Scholar
Taylor, R. (1992). Metaphysics, 4th edn. Englewoods Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Van Inwagen, P. (1975). The incompatibility of free will and determinism. Philosophical Studies, 27, 185–99. Reprinted in Watson, G., ed., Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 46–58.Google Scholar
Vogt, B. A., Finch, D. M., and Olson, C. R. (1992). Functional heterogeneity in the cingulate cortex: the anterior executive and the posterior evaluative regions. Cerebral Cortex, 2, 435–43.Google ScholarPubMed
Walter, H. (2000). Neurophilosophy of Free Will: From Libertarian Illusions to a Concept of Natural Autonomy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Wegner, D. M. (2002). The Illusion of Conscious Will. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×