Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-s9k8s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-19T21:31:48.690Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

4 - Constitutional Disharmony after Roe

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 April 2013

Justin Buckley Dyer
Affiliation:
University of Missouri, Columbia
Get access

Summary

As the late Samuel Huntington noted in his seminal work on American political development, “an ever-present gap exists between American political ideals and American political institutions and practice.” If we understand a constitution as the fundamental norms, principles, and practices of a particular society (including the scheme of distributing political power), we might characterize the gap or tension between ideals and practice as a kind of constitutional disharmony. In the American context, Huntington argued, such disharmony has been particularly acute because of the “central role of moral passion” in American politics, which has given rise to myriad reform movements that appeal to foundational moral principles such as those prominently featured in the preamble to the Declaration of Independence. The classic example of disharmony, along these lines, was occasioned by the institution of slavery, which created convulsions in the polity precisely because slavery was inconsistent with the normative principles underlying the regime.

As Jennifer Hochschild writes, the American system of race-based, hereditary chattel slavery was “antiliberal in its assertion of the unequal worth of persons, of civil – not natural – determinations of rights, of the legitimacy of denying liberty and opportunity to some.” Of course, scholars still debate the best way to conceptualize the relationship between slavery and the principles of American government. One answer to the question of how slavery could co-exist with a political culture that emphasized liberty and individual rights is that slavery was simply an aberration. Another possible explanation, however, is that rights-oriented liberalism and racial slavery were actually symbiotic. A version of the symbiosis argument was prominently put forward by Edmund Morgan in his study of slavery in eighteenth-century Virginia. What made freedom and equality among the Virginia elites possible was the relative equality of leisure and economic resources provided by the system of forced labor.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Huntington, Samuel P., American Politics: The Promise of Disharmony (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981), 4Google Scholar
Hochschild, Jennifer, The New American Dilemma: School Desegregation and Liberal Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1984), 2Google Scholar
Myrdal, Gunnar, An American Dilemma: The Negro Problem and American Democracy (New York: Harper and Row, 1944)Google Scholar
Hartz, Louis, The Liberal Tradition in America (New York: Harcourt, 1955)Google Scholar
Morgan, Edmund S., American Slavery, American Freedom: The Ordeal of Colonial Virginia (New York: W. W. Norton, 1975)Google Scholar
Ericson, David F., The Debate Over Slavery: Antislavery and Proslavery Liberalism in Antebellum America (New York: New York University Press, 2000)Google Scholar
Siegel, Reva, “Abortion,” in Fox, Richard Weightman and Kloppenberg, James T., eds., Companion to American Thought (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1995), 2Google Scholar
Webster v. Reproductive Health Services 492 U.S. 490 (1989) (1989 U.S. S. Ct. Briefs LEXIS 1525).
Bradley, Gerard V., “Life’s Dominion: A Review Essay,” Notre Dame Law Review 69 (1993–1994), 329–391Google ScholarPubMed
Finnis, John, remarks delivered at the conference “Open Hearts, Open Minds, and Fair-Minded Words,” Princeton University, October 15–16, 2010
Finnis, John, “The Other F-Word,” The Public Discourse: Ethics, Law, and the Common Good (October 20, 2010),
Cardozo, Benjamin N., The Nature of the Judicial Process (Mineola, NY: Dover, 2005), 41Google Scholar
Roe v. Wade 410 U.S. 113, 154 (1973) (Blackmun, J.)
Doe v. Bolton 410 U.S. 179, 180 (1973) (Burger, J., concurring).
Maledon, William L., “The Law and the Unborn Child: The Legal and Logical Inconsistencies,” Notre Dame Lawyer 46 (1971), 349–372Google Scholar
Prosser, W., Handbook of the Law of Torts §56, 355, 3rd ed. (1964). Cited in Notre Dame Lawyer 46 (1970–71), 349–50.
Noonan, John T., A Private Choice: Abortion in America in the Seventies (New York: Free Press, 1979), 13–14.Google Scholar
Kelsen, Hans, The Pure Theory of the Law (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967), 95Google Scholar
Rossiter, Clinton, ed., The Federalist Papers (New York: Penguin, 2003), 334Google Scholar
Jacobsohn, Gary Jeffrey, “Constitutional Identity,” The Review of Politics 68 (2006), 375CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farrand, Max, ed., The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, 3 vols. (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1911)
Ingleman-Sunderberg, Alex and Wirsen, Cloes, A Child is Born: The Drama of Life Before Birth (New York: Dell, 1965)Google Scholar
Arey, Leslie B., Developmental Anatomy, 6th ed. (Philadelphia: W. B. Saunders, 1954)Google Scholar
Patten, Bradley M., Human Embryology, 3rd ed. (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1968)Google Scholar
George, Robert P. and Tollefsen, Christopher, Embryo: A Defense of Human Life (New York: Doubleday, 2008), 27–56Google Scholar
Planned Parenthood v. Danforth 428 U.S. 52 (1976)
Franklin v. Colautti 439 U.S. 379 (1979)
City of Akron v. Akron Center for Reproductive Health 462 U.S. 416 (1983)
Thornburgh v. American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists 476 U.S. 747 (1986)
Planned Parenthood v. Casey 505 U.S. 833, 846 (1992) (O’Connor, Kennedy, and Souter, JJ.).
Haskell, M.D. Martin, “Dilation and Extraction for Late Second Trimester Abortion,” Presented at the National Abortion Federation Risk Management Seminar, September 13, 1992
Gonzales v. Carhart 550 U.S. 124, 139 (2007) (Kennedy, J.).
Nebraska Rev. Stat. Ann Sec. 28–328. See Stenberg v. Carhart 530 U.S. 914, 922 (2000) (Breyer, J.).
Arkes, Hadley, Natural Rights and the Right to Choose (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Showery v. Texas 690 S.W.2d 689, 691 (1985) (Ward, J.).
“Brief of National Abortion Federation, et al., as Amici Curiae in Support of Respondant,” Gonzales v. Carhart (2006) (2006 U.S. S. Ct. Briefs LEXIS 656, 27).
Congressional Record, 106th Cong., 1st Sess., S. 12878–12880 (20 October 1999).
Smolin, David, “Fourteenth Amendment Unenumerated Rights Jurisprudence: An Essay in Response to Stenberg v. Carhart,” Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy 24, no. 3 (2001) 815–839Google Scholar
Pound, Roscoe, The Formative Era of American Law (Boston: Little, Brown & Co., 1938), 84Google Scholar
“A New Ethic for Medicine and Society,”California Medicine: The Western Journal of Medicine 113, no. 3 (1970), 67–68.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×