Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wzw2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-17T21:19:47.453Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - Hobbes's theory of representation: anti-democratic or proto-democratic?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

David Runciman
Affiliation:
Cambridge University
Ian Shapiro
Affiliation:
Yale University, Connecticut
Susan C. Stokes
Affiliation:
Yale University, Connecticut
Elisabeth Jean Wood
Affiliation:
Yale University, Connecticut
Alexander S. Kirshner
Affiliation:
Yale University, Connecticut
Get access

Summary

Hobbes, representation, and democracy

Thomas Hobbes occupies a deeply ambivalent position in the history of modern conceptions of political representation. On the one hand, he is often credited as the thinker who did most to make representation a distinctively modern concept, by emancipating it from its medieval roots and employing it to establish a clear identity for the state as a separate entity in its own right (Skinner 1989, 2002). Hobbes used the idea of representation to ground a secular conception of political authority, and in doing so rescued the idea of political rule from various intractable theological controversies. In this sense, Hobbes's thought is foundational for modern theories of representative government. But for all its apparent modernity, Hobbes's theory of representation suffers from one obvious flaw when judged by the standards of contemporary politics: it appears to be strikingly anti-democratic, and it is very hard to see how an anti-democratic theory can also be viewed as foundational for the political world we now inhabit.

This dual role occupied by Hobbes – both foundational but also oppositional in his perceived relationship to representative democracy – is best captured by his treatment in what remains the most widely cited work on the theory of political representation in English, Hanna Pitkin's The Concept of Representation (Pitkin 1967). There, Hobbes is treated first of all as the thinker who did most to clarify the central feature of modern political representation – that it is an “authorization” concept (or what Pitkin goes on to call a “substantive” concept), in which political representation emerges as a form of “acting for” rather than merely “standing for.”

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Buchanan, James and Tullock, Gordon. 1965. The Calculus of Consent. Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Forsyth, Murray. 1987. Reason and Revolution. The Political Thought of the Abbé Sieyès. Leicester: Leicester University Press.Google Scholar
Graetz, Michael and Shapiro, Ian. 2005. Death by a Thousand Cuts. The Fight over Taxing Inherited Wealth. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas. 1996 [1651]. Leviathan, ed. Tuck, Richard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas 1998 [1642]. On the Citizen, ed. Tuck, Richard and Silverthorne, Michael. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hoekstra, Kinch. 2006. “A Lion in the House: Hobbes and Democracy,” in Rethinking the Foundations of Modern Political Thought, ed. Brett, Annabel and Tully, James. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 191–219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hont, Istvan. 2005. Jealousy of Trade. International Competition and the Nation State in Historical Perspective. Cambridge, MA: Belknap.Google Scholar
Kuper, Andrew. 2004. Democracy Beyond Borders. Justice and Representation in Global Institutions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, John. 1988 [1679]. Two Treatises of Government, ed. Laslett, Peter. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manin, Bernard. 1997. The Principles of Representative Government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 2003. “Groups with Minds of their Own,” in Socializing Metaphysics, ed. Schmitt, F.. New York: Rowman and Littlefield, 167–93.Google Scholar
Pitkin, Hanna. 1967. The Concept of Representation. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Przeworski, Adam, 1999. “Minimalist Conceptions of Democracy,” in Democracy's Value, ed. Shapiro, Ian and Hacker-Cordon, Casiano. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 23–50.Google Scholar
Przeworski, Adam, Stokes, Susan, and Manin, Bernard (eds.). 1999. Democracy, Accountability and Representation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
Runciman, David. 2000a. “What Kind of Person Is Hobbes's State? A Reply to Skinner.” Journal of Political Philosophy 8: 268–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Runciman, David 2000b. “Is the State a Corporation?Government and Opposition 35: 90–104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Runciman, David 2007. “The Paradox of Political Representation.” Journal of Political Philosophy 15: 93–117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. 1996 [1938]. The Leviathan in the State Theory of Thomas Hobbes. Meaning and Failure of a Symbol, ed. Schwab, George. Westport, CT: Greenwood.Google Scholar
Schumpeter, Joseph. 1994 [1942]. Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, ed. Swedberg, Richard. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Shapiro, Ian. 2003. The State of Democratic Theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Skinner, Quentin. 1989. “The State,” in Political Innovation and Conceptual Change, ed. Ball, T.et al. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 90–131.Google Scholar
Skinner, Quentin 2002. “Hobbes and the Purely Artificial Person of the State,” in Visions of Politics, vol. III. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 177–208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skinner, Quentin 2005. “Hobbes on Representation.” European Journal of Philosophy 13: 155–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tuck, Richard. 2006. “Hobbes and Democracy,” in Rethinking the Foundations of Modern Political Thought, ed. Brett, Annabel and Tully, James. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 171–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×