Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-2h6rp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-18T04:19:22.454Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Brain Time and Phenomenological Time

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 February 2010

Rick Grush
Affiliation:
Associate Professor of Philosophy, UCSD
Andrew Brook
Affiliation:
Carleton University, Ottawa
Kathleen Akins
Affiliation:
Simon Fraser University, British Columbia
Get access

Summary

As 'tis from the disposition of visible and tangible objects we receive the idea of space, so from the succession of ideas and impressions we form the idea of time.

– David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature

… space and time … are … pure intuitions that lie a priori at the basis of the empirical… . [T]hey are mere forms of our sensibility, which must precede all empirical intuition, or perception of actual objects.

– Immanuel Kant, Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics

… there are cases in which on the basis of a temporally extended content of consciousness a unitary apprehension takes place which is spread out over a temporal interval (the so-called specious present)…. That several successive tones yield a melody is possible only in this way, that the succession of psychical processes are united “forthwith” in a common structure.

– Edmund Husserl, The Phenomenology of Inner Time-Consciousness

Introduction

The topic of this chapter is temporal representation. More specifically, I intend to provide an outline of a theory of what it is that our brains do (at the subpersonal level) such that we experience (at the personal level) certain aspects of time in the way that we do. A few words about both sides of this relation are in order.

First, the brain. I will actually be making little substantive contact with neurophysiology.

Type
Chapter
Information
Cognition and the Brain
The Philosophy and Neuroscience Movement
, pp. 160 - 207
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bach-y-Rita, P. (1972). Brain Mechanisms in Sensory Substitution. New York and London: Academic PressGoogle Scholar
Broad, C. D. (1923). Scientific Thought. London: Kegan PaulGoogle Scholar
Brook, Andrew (1994). Kant and the Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brough, J. (1989). Husserl's phenomenology of time-consciousness. In Mohanty, J. N. and McKenna, W. R. (eds.), Husserl's Phenomenology: A Textbook. Lanham, MD: University Press of AmericaGoogle Scholar
Bryson, A., and Ho, Y.-C. (1969) Applied Optimal Control: Optimization, Estimation, and Control. Waltham, MA: BlaisdellGoogle Scholar
Craik, Kenneth (1943). The Nature of Explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Dennett, Daniel (1991). Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, BrownGoogle Scholar
Dennett, Daniel, and Kinsbourne, Marcel (1992). Time and the observer. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15(2):183–247CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duhamel, J.-R., Colby, C., and Goldberg, M. E. (1992). The updating of the representation of visual space in parietal cortex by intended eye movements. Science 255(5040):90–92CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Eagleman, , David, and Sejnowski, , Terrence (2000). Motion integration and postdiction in visual awareness. Science 287 (5460):2036–2038CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Evans, Gareth (1981). Understanding demonstratives. In Parret, H. and Bouveresse, J. (eds.), Meaning and Understanding. Berlin: W. de GruyterCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, Gareth (1985). Molyneux's question. In Evans, Gareth, Collected Papers. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Gelb, A. (1974). Applied Optimal Estimation. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Geldard, F. A., and Sherrick, C. E. (1972). The Cutaneous ‘rabbit’: A perceptual illusion. Science 178(4057):178–9CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Grush, Rick (1997). The architecture of representation. Philosophical Psychology 10(1):5–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grush, Rick (1998). Skill and spatial content. Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy 6(6). (http://ejap.louisiana.edu/EJAP/1998/grusharticle98.html)Google Scholar
Grush, Rick (2000). Self, world and space: On the meaning and mechanisms of ego- and allo-centric spatial representation. Brain and Mind 1(1):59–92CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grush, Rick (2002). An introduction to the main principles of emulation: Motor control, imagery, and perception. UCSD Philosophy Tech Report
Grush, Rick (2004). The emulation theory of representation: Motor control, imagery and perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27(3):377–442CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haykin, S. (2001). Kalman filtering and neural networks. New York: WileyCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, John (1987). The Molyneux question. Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior. 17:227–241CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoerl, Christoph (1998). The perception of time and the notion of a point of view. European Journal of Philosophy 6(2):156–171CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, David (1739/1909). A Treatise of Human Nature. (Green, T. H. and Grose, T. H., eds.) London: Longmans, Green, and Co.Google Scholar
Husserl, Edmund (1905). The Phenomenology of Internal Time-Consciousness. (Heidegger, M., ed.; J. Churchill, trans.) Bloomington: Indiana University PressGoogle Scholar
Ito, M. (1970). Neurophysiological aspects of the cerebellar motor control system. International Journal of Neurology 7:162–176Google ScholarPubMed
Ito, Masao (1984). The cerebellum and neural control. New York: Raven PressGoogle Scholar
James, William (1890). The Principles of Psychology. New York: Henry HoltGoogle Scholar
Kalman, R. E. (1960). A new approach to linear filtering and prediction problems. Journal of Basic Engineering 82(d):35–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kalman, R., and Bucy, R. S. (1961). New results in linear filtering and prediction theory. Journal of Basic Engineering 83(d):95–108CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1783/1950). Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics. Indianapolis: Bobbs-MerrillGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Patricia (1990). Kant's Transcendental Psychology. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Kosslyn, S. M. (1994). Image and Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Kosslyn, S. M., and Sussman, A. L. (1995). Roles of imagery in perception: Or, there is no such thing as immaculate perception. In Gazzaniga, M. S. (ed.), The Cognitive Neurosciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Poidevin, Robin (1999). Egocentric and objective time. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society XⅭIX, 19–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mabbot, J. D. (1951). Our direct experience of time. Mind 60:153–167CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mach, Ernst (1897). Contributions to the analysis of sensations (C. M. Williams, trans.). Chicago: Open Court PublishingCrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacKay, D. M. (1958). Perceptual stability of a stroboscopically lit visual field containing self-luminous objects. Nature181:507Google ScholarPubMed
Mundle, C. W. K. (1954). How specious is the ‘specious present’? Mind 63:26–48CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plumer, Gilbert (1985). The myth of the specious present. Mind 94:19–35CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pouget, Alexandre, and Sejnowski, Terrence (1997). Spatial transformations in the parietal cortex using basis functions. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 9(2):222–237CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rao, R. P. N., Eagleman, David, and Sejnowski, Terrence (2001). Optimal smoothing in visual motion perception. Neural Computation 13:1243–1253CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stern, L. W. (1897). Psychische Präsenzzeit. Zeitschrift für Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnesorgane 13:325–349Google Scholar
Strawson, Peter F. (1966). The Bounds of Sense. London: MethuenGoogle Scholar
van Gelder, T. (1999). Wooden iron? Husserlian phenomenology meets cognitive science. In Pettitot, Jean et al. (eds.), Naturalizing Phenomenology. Stanford, CA: Stanford University PressGoogle Scholar
von Helmholtz, H. (1910). Handbuch der Physiologischen Optik, vol. 3, 3d ed. (Gullstrand, A., Kries, J. and Nagel, W., eds.) Leipzig: VossGoogle Scholar
Williams, L. E., Hubbard, E. M., and Ramachandran, V. S. (2005, April). Retrodiction in Apparent Motion. Poster presented at the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Neuroscience Society, New York, NY
Zipser, David, and Andersen, Richard A. (1988). A back-propagation programmed network that simulates response properties of a subset of posterior parietal neurons. Nature 331:679–684CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×